Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-t7czq Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-22T05:19:51.756Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Dretske on Laws of Nature

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 April 2022

Ilkka Niiniluoto*
Affiliation:
University of Helsinki

Extract

In a recent article [4], Fred I. Dretske has proposed a new analysis of natural laws. Dretske rejects the more or less standard view which says that laws are universal truths with a special function or status in science. As an alternative account, he suggests that laws are expressed by singular statements describing the relationship between universal properties and magnitudes: the statement

(1) It is a law that F's are G's3.

is to be analysed as

(2) F-ness ↦ G-ness.

I shall argue, however, that Dretske's reasons for rejecting the standard account are not conclusive. Moreover, his own proposal seems to be either inadequate or reducible to that version of the standard account which takes laws to be nomically necessary generalizations.

Type
Discussion
Copyright
Copyright © Philosophy of Science Association 1978

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

[1] Carnap, R. Logical Foundations of Probability (2nd ed.). Chicago: Chicago University Press, 1962.Google Scholar
[2] Causey, R. L. Unity of Science. Dordrecht: D. Reidel, 1977.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[3] de Finetti, B.Foresight: Its Logical Laws, Its Subjective Sources.” In Studies in Subjective Probability. Edited by Kyburg, H. E. and H, E. Smokier. New York: Wiley, 1964.Google Scholar
[4] Dretske, F.Laws of Nature.” Philosophy of Science 44 (1977): 248268.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[5] Hempel, C. G.Inductive Inconsistencies.” In C. G. Hempel, Aspects of Scientific Explanation. New York: The Free Press. 1965. Pp. 5379.Google Scholar
[6] Hintikka, K. J.A Two-Dimensional Continuum of Inductive Methods.” In Aspects of Inductive Logic. Edited by Hintikka, K. J. and Suppes, P. Amsterdam: North-Holland, 1966. Pp. 113132.10.1016/S0049-237X(08)71666-5CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[7] Hintikka, K. J.Carnap's Semantics in Retrospect.” Synthese 25 (1973): 372397.10.1007/BF00499687CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[8] Lewis, D. Counterfactuals. Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1973.Google Scholar
[9] Montague, R. Formal Philosophy. Selected Papers of Richard Montague. Edited by Thomason, R. H. New Haven: Yale University Press, 1974.Google Scholar
[10] Niiniluoto, I.Inductive Explanation, Propensity, and Action.” In Essays on Explanation and Understanding. Edited by Manninen, J. and Tuomela, R. Dordrecht: D. Reidel, 1976. Pp. 335368.10.1007/978-94-010-1823-4_16CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[11] Niiniluoto, I.On a K-dimensional System of Inductive Logic.” In PSA 1976, vol. 2. Edited by F. Suppe and P. D. Asquith. East Lansing: Philosophy of Science Association, 1977.Google Scholar
[12] Niiniluoto, I. and Tuomela, R. Theoretical Concepts and Hypothetico-Inductive Inference. Dordrecht: D. Reidel, 1973.10.1007/978-94-010-2596-6CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[13] Smokier, H. E.Conflicting Conceptions of Confirmation.” Journal of Philosophy 65 (1968): 300312.10.2307/2024080CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[14] Uchii, S.Inductive Logic with Causal Modalities.” Philosophy of Science 39 (1972): 162178.10.1086/288431CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[15] von Wright, G. H. Explanation and Understanding. Cornell: Cornell University Press, 1971.Google Scholar