Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-ndw9j Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-19T03:03:11.327Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Crash Testing an Engineering Framework in Neuroscience: Does the Idea of Robustness Break Down?

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2022

Abstract

In this article, I discuss the concept of robustness in neuroscience. Various mechanisms for making systems robust have been discussed across biology and neuroscience (e.g., redundancy and fail-safes). Many of these notions originate from engineering. I argue that concepts borrowed from engineering aid neuroscientists in (1) operationalizing robustness, (2) formulating hypotheses about mechanisms for robustness, and (3) quantifying robustness. Furthermore, I argue that the significant disanalogies between brains and engineered artifacts raise important questions about the applicability of the engineering framework. I argue that the use of such concepts should be understood as a kind of simplifying idealization.

Type
Cognitive Sciences
Copyright
Copyright © The Philosophy of Science Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

I am greatly indebted to Timothy O’Leary, Nancy Nersessian, and Peter Sterling for their feedback on this work. I would also like to thank the participants in a fall 2015 workshop on robustness in neuroscience for discussion of the ideas behind this article and the audience at a spring 2016 reengineering biology conference for their questions and comments on it. Both events were hosted by the Center for Philosophy of Science at the University of Pittsburgh. I am also grateful to the audience members at the 2016 Philosophy of Science Association meeting for a lively discussion.

References

Bechtel, W. 2015. “Can Mechanistic Explanation Be Reconciled with Scale-Free Constitution and Dynamics?Studies in History and Philosophy of Science C 53:8493.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Bechtel, W., and Abrahamsen, A. 2013. “Thinking Dynamically about Biological Mechanisms: Networks of Coupled Oscillators.” Foundations of Science 18:707–23.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Buzsáki, G. 2006. Rhythms of the Brain. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Davis, G. W. 2006. “Homeostatic Control of Neural Activity: From Phenomenology to Molecular Design.” Annual Review of Neuroscience 29:307–23.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Day, T. A. 2005. “Defining Stress as a Prelude to Mapping Its Neurocircuitry: No Help from Allostasis.” Progress in Neuro-Psychopharmacology and Biological Psychiatry 29:11951200.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Dupré, J. 2012. Processes of Life. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Edelman, G. M., and Gally, J. A. 2001. “Degeneracy and Complexity in Biological Systems.” Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences 98 (24): 13763–68.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Hesse, M. B. 1953. “Models in Physics.” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 4 (15): 198214.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kitano, H. 2004. “Biological Robustness.” Nature Reviews Genetics 5:826–37.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Knuuttila, T., and Loettgers, A. 2013. “Basic Science through Engineering? Synthetic Modeling and the Idea of Biology-Inspired Engineering.” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science C 48:158–69.Google Scholar
Li, N., Daie, K., Svoboda, K., and Druckmann, S. 2016. “Robust Neuronal Dynamics in Premotor Cortex during Motor Planning.” Nature 532:459–64.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Marder, E., and Goaillard, J.-M. 2012. “Variability, Compensation, and Homeostasis in Neuron and Network Function.” Nature Reviews Neuroscience 7:563–74.Google Scholar
O’Leary, T., Williams, A. H., Caplan, J. C., and Marder, E. 2013. “Correlations in Ion Channel Expression Emerge from Homeostatic Tuning Rules.” Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences 110 (28): E2645E2654.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
O’Leary, T., Williams, A. H., Franci, A., and Marder, E. 2014. “Cell Types, Network Homeostasis, and Pathological Compensation from a Biologically Plausible Ion Channel Expression Model.” Neuron 82 (4): 809–21.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
O’Leary, T., and Wyllie, D. J. A. 2011. “Neuronal Homeostasis: Time for a Change?Journal of Physiology 589 (20): 4811–26.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Rose, S. 2012. “The Need for a Critical Neuroscience.” In Critical Neuroscience: A Handbook of the Social and Cultural Contexts of Neuroscience, ed. Choudhury, S. and Slaby, J. Hoboken, NJ: Wiley-Blackwell.Google Scholar
Sporns, O. 2010. Networks of the Brain. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sterling, P. 2012. “Allostasis: A Model of Predictive Regulation.” Physiology and Behavior 106:515.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sterling, P., and Freed, M. 2007. “How Robust Is a Neural Circuit?Visual Neuroscience 24:563–71.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Sterling, P., and Laughlin, S. B. 2015. Principles of Neural Design. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Svoboda, K. 2015. Abstract of “Probing Frontal Cortical Networks during Motor Planning.” Seminar, Center for the Neural Basis of Cognition, November 10. http://www.braininstitute.pitt.edu/event/probing-frontal-cortical-networks-during-motor-planning.Google Scholar
von Békésy, G. 1967. Sensory Inhibition. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zhang, Y., and Chase, S. M. 2015. “Recasting Brain-Machine Interface Design from a Physical Control System Perspective.” Journal of Computational Neuroscience 39:107–18.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed