Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-dh8gc Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-05T11:57:06.863Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The Analytic and the Synthetic

The Duhemian Argument and Some Contemporary Philosophers

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  14 March 2022

Abstract

This article is devoted to the question: does the Duhemian argument support the position taken by those contemporary philosophers who—like W. V. O. Quine and M. White—reject the distinction between analytic and synthetic statements? The term “Duhemian argument” is used to refer to the following statement: it is impossible to put to the test one isolated empirical statement; testing empirical statements involves testing a whole group of hypotheses. An analysis of the logical structure of reductive reasoning leads to the conclusion that the Duhemian argument is valid and that it entails the following statements: (1)—experience alone cannot compel us absolutely to the acceptance of any isolated empirical statement whatsoever, independently of our acceptance or rejection of some other statements, and (2)—no isolated empirical statement can be conclusively falsified by experience, independently of our acceptance or rejection of some other statements. The Duhemian argument seems then to establish conclusively the cogency of the claim that, in principle, it is possible to reject or to maintain any particular empirical statement, provided we make appropriate changes in the system of hypotheses which is put to test. The philosophers who reject the distinction between analytic and synthetic statements—in particular Quine—claim that the same line of reasoning supports their contention. It is alleged that: (1)—the Duhemian argument makes impossible a definition of statement synonymy and, consequently, a definition of analyticity in terms of synonymy, and (2)—that the unit of empirical significance is the whole of science or the total science, and (3)—that it is a folly to seek a boundary between synthetic and analytic statements, because all our statements are equally open to revision. The article tries to show that these conclusions do not follow from the Duhemian argument. In particular it is shown: (1)—that the Duhemian argument does not exclude the definition of statement synonymy, (2)—that this argument does not support the contention that the enigmatic entity called “the whole of science” or the “total science” is involved in each and every testing procedure, (3)—that the principle of fundamental revisability of every statement does not change the fact that in scientific practice the situation is never so hopeless as the Duhemian argument seems to imply, because even inconclusive arguments may differ in their adequacy, and (4)—that the term “revision” is ambiguous and only this ambiguity lends an air of plausibility to Quine's formulations. The conclusion is that the Duhemian line of reasoning does not support the contention of philosophers who reject the distinction between analytic and synthetic statements.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © 1959 by Philosophy of Science Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 W. V. O. Quine: “Two Dogmas of Empiricism”, in From A Logical Point of View, Cambridge, Mass., 1953; M. White: “The Analytic and the Synthetic: An Untenable Dualism”, in John Dewey: Philosopher of Science and Freedom, ed. by S. Hook, New York, 1950; Toward Reunion in Philosophy, Cambridge, Mass., 1956.

2 P. Duhem: La Théorie Physique, Paris, 1906, pp. 303 ff.

3 G. Ryle: The Concept of Mind, New York, 1949, p. 121.

4 E. Nagel: Logic Without Metaphysics, Glencoe, Ill., 1956, pp. 303-315.

5 R. B. Braithwaite: Scientific Explanation, London, 1953, p. 86.

6 Quoted from H. Weyl: Philosophy of Mathematics and Natural Sciences, Princeton, 1949, p. 153.

7 Quine: op. cit., p. 41.

8 ibid., p. 38.

9 ibid., p. 42.

10 ibid., p. 41.

11 ibid., p. 42.

12 ibid., p. 43.

13 E. Nagel: Principles of the Theory of Probability, Chicago, 1939, p. 1.

14 The example is derived from the Polish philosopher Leszek Kolakowski.

15 G. Birkhoff and J. von Neumann: “The Logic of Quantum Mechanics”, Annals of Mathematics, 37, 1936, pp. 823-43; J. L. Destouches: Principes Fondamentaux de Physique Théorique, Paris 1942; H. Reichenbach: Philosophic Foundations of Quantum Mechanics, Los Angeles, 1944.

16 M. White: Toward Reunion in Philosophy, Cambridge, Mass., 1956, pp. 256-7.