Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-t7czq Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-25T17:05:34.878Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The Value of Cognitive Values

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2022

Abstract

Traditionally, cognitive values have been thought of as a collective pool of considerations in science that frequently trade against each other. I argue here that a finer-grained account of the value of cognitive values can help reduce such tensions. I separate the values into groups, minimal epistemic criteria, pragmatic considerations, and genuine epistemic assurance, based in part on the distinction between values that describe theories per se and values that describe theory-evidence relationships. This allows us to clarify why these values are central to science and what role they should play, while reducing the tensions among them.

Type
General Philosophy of Science
Copyright
Copyright © The Philosophy of Science Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

My thanks to Kareem Khalifa for the conversation that got this paper going, to Ted Richards for his editing skill, to Dan Hicks for reading the paper at PSA in my absence, and to the National Science Foundation (grant 1026999) for supporting my time at the Center for Philosophy of Science at the University of Pittsburgh, where this wok began.

References

Collins, Robin. 1994. “Against the Epistemic Value of Prediction over Accommodation.” Nous 28 (2): 210–24..CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Douglas, Heather E. 2009. Science, Policy, and the Value-Free Ideal. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Duhem, Pierre. 1906/1906. The Aim and Structure of Physical Theory. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Fisch, Menachem. 1985. “Whewell’s Consilience of Inductions—and Evaluation.” Philosophy of Science 52:239–55.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Forster, Malcolm, and Sober, Elliott. 1994. “How to Tell When Simpler, More Unified, or Less Ad Hoc Theories Will Provide More Accurate Predictions.” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 45:135.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harker, David. 2008. “On the Predilections for Predictions.” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 59:429–53.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kellert, Stephen, Longino, Helen, and Waters, Kenneth, eds. 2006. Scientific Pluralism. Minnesota Studies in Philosophy of Science 19. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Kuhn, Thomas. 1977. “Objectivity, Value, and Theory Choice.” In The Essential Tension, 320–39. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lacey, Hugh. 1999. Is Science Value Free? Values and Scientific Understanding. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
Laudan, Larry. 1984. Science and Values. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Laudan, Larry 2004. “The Epistemic, the Cognitive, and the Social.” In Science, Values, and Objectivity, ed. Machamer, Peter and Wolters, Gereon, 1423. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Levi, Isaac. 1960. “Must the Scientist Make Value Judgments?Journal of Philosophy 57:345–57.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Levi, Isaac 1962. “On the Seriousness of Mistakes.” Philosophy of Science 29:4765.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Longino, Helen. 1996. “Cognitive and Non-cognitive Values in Science: Rethinking the Dichotomy.” In Feminism, Science, and the Philosophy of Science, ed. Nelson, Lynn Hankinson and Nelson, Jack, 3958. Dordrecht: Kluwer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Longino, Helen. 2002. The Fate of Knowledge. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McMullin, Ernan. 1983. “Values in Science.” In Proceedings of the 1982 Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association, Vol. 1, ed. Peter D. Asquith and Thomas Nickles, 3–28. East Lansing, MI: Philosophy of Science Association.Google Scholar
Mitchell, Sandra. 2009. Unsimple Truths. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Popper, Karl. 1935/2002. The Logic of Scientific Discovery. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Rooney, Phyllis. 1992. “On Values in Science: Is the Epistemic/Non-epistemic Distinction Useful?” In Proceedings of the 1992 Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association, Vol. 2, ed. David Hull, Micky Forbes, and Kathleen Okruhlik, 13–22. East Lansing, MI: Philosophy of Science Association.Google Scholar
Solomon, Miriam. 2001. Social Empiricism. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Steel, Daniel. 2010. “Epistemic Values and the Argument from Inductive Risk.” Philosophy of Science 77:1434.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Thagard, Paul. 2000. Coherence in Thought and Action. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar