Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-8bhkd Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-05T10:01:08.291Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Thought Experiments and the Belief in Phenomena

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2022

Abstract

Thought experiment acquires evidential significance only on particular metaphysical assumptions. These include the thesis that science aims at uncovering “phenomena”—universal and stable modes in which the world is articulated—and the thesis that phenomena are revealed imperfectly in actual occurrences. Only on these Platonically inspired assumptions does it make sense to bypass experience of actual occurrences and perform thought experiments. These assumptions are taken to hold in classical physics and other disciplines, but not in sciences that emphasize variety and contingency, such as Aristotelian natural philosophy and some forms of historiography. This explains why thought experiments carry weight in the former but not the latter disciplines.

Type
The Epistemology of thought Experiments
Copyright
Copyright © 2004 by the Philosophy of Science Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

I thank the other speakers, James Robert Brown, Tamar Szabó Gendler, and John D. Norton, the chair, Nancy J. Nersessian, and the audience for a very enjoyable symposium on “The Epistemology of Thought Experiments” at the 2002 Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association, Milwaukee. I benefited from their stimulating comments on the draft of this paper that I presented there.

References

Adler, Carl G., and Coulter, Byron L. (1975), “Aristotle: Villain or Victim?”, Aristotle: Villain or Victim? 13:3537.Google Scholar
Arthur, Richard (1999), “On Thought Experiments as A Priori Science”, On Thought Experiments as A Priori Science 13:215229.Google Scholar
Bishop, Michael A. (1999), “Why Thought Experiments Are Not Arguments”, Why Thought Experiments Are Not Arguments 66:534541.Google Scholar
Bogen, James, and Woodward, James (1988), “Saving the Phenomena”, Saving the Phenomena 97:303352.Google Scholar
Brown, James R. (1991), The Laboratory of the Mind: Thought Experiments in the Natural Sciences. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Brown, James R. (2004), “Peeking into Plato’s Heaven”, Peeking into Plato’s Heaven 71 (Proceedings): 11261138.Google Scholar
Casper, Barry M. (1977), “Galileo and the Fall of Aristotle: A Case of Historical Injustice?”, Galileo and the Fall of Aristotle: A Case of Historical Injustice? 45:325330.Google Scholar
Cowley, Robert (ed.) (1999), What If? The World’s Foremost Military Historians Imagine What Might Have Been. New York: Putnam.Google Scholar
Feinberg, Gerald (1965), “Fall of Bodies Near the Earth”, Fall of Bodies Near the Earth 33:501502.Google Scholar
Ferguson, Niall (ed.) (1997), Virtual History: Alternatives and Counterfactuals. London: Picador.Google Scholar
Galilei, Galileo ([1632] 1953), Dialogue Concerning the Two Chief World Systems—Ptolemaic and Copernican. Translated by Drake, Stillman. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Galilei, Galileo ([1638] 1974), Two New Sciences. Translated by Drake, Stillman. Madison: University of Wisconsin Press.Google Scholar
Gendler, Tamar Szabó (2000), Thought Experiment: On the Powers and Limits of Imaginary Cases. New York: Garland.Google Scholar
Gendler, Tamar Szabó (2004), “Thought Experiments Rethought—and Reperceived”, Thought Experiments Rethought—and Reperceived 71 (Proceedings): 11521163.Google Scholar
Gooding, David C. (1993), “What Is Experimental about Thought Experiments?”, in Hull, David, Forbes, Micky, and Okruhlik, Kathleen (eds.), Proceedings of the 1992 Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association, 2 vols. East Lansing, MI: Philosophy of Science Association, vol. 2:280290.Google Scholar
Grant, Edward (1984), “In Defense of the Earth’s Centrality and Immobility: Scholastic Reaction to Copernicanism in the Seventeenth Century”, In Defense of the Earth’s Centrality and Immobility: Scholastic Reaction to Copernicanism in the Seventeenth Century 74, pt. 4.Google Scholar
Hacking, Ian (1983), Representing and Intervening: Introductory Topics in the Philosophy of Natural Science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hempel, Carl G. (1965), Aspects of Scientific Explanation and Other Essays in the Philosophy of Science. New York: Free Press.Google Scholar
King, Peter (1991), “Mediaeval Thought-Experiments: The Metamethodology of Mediaeval Science”, in Horowitz, Tamara and Massey, Gerald J. (eds.), Thought Experiments in Science and Philosophy. Savage, MD: Rowman and Littlefield, 4364.Google Scholar
Koertge, Noretta (1977), “Galileo and the Problem of Accidents”, Galileo and the Problem of Accidents 38:389408.Google Scholar
Koyré, Alexandre (1968), Metaphysics and Measurement: Essays in Scientific Revolution. London: Chapman and Hall.Google Scholar
Laymon, Ronald (1978), “Newton’s Bucket Experiment”, Newton’s Bucket Experiment 16:399413.Google Scholar
McAllister, James W. (1996), “The Evidential Significance of Thought Experiment in Science”, The Evidential Significance of Thought Experiment in Science 27:233250.Google Scholar
McAllister, James W. (1999), “Universal Regularities and Initial Conditions in Newtonian Physics”, Universal Regularities and Initial Conditions in Newtonian Physics 120:325343.Google Scholar
Naylor, Ronald H. (1989), “Galileo’s Experimental Discourse”, in Gooding, David, Pinch, Trevor, and Schaffer, Simon (eds.), The Uses of Experiment: Studies in the Natural Sciences. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 117134.Google Scholar
Norton, John D. (1996), “Are Thought Experiments Just What You Thought?”, Are Thought Experiments Just What You Thought? 26:333366.Google Scholar
Norton, John D. (2004), “On Thought Experiments: Is There More to the Argument?”, On Thought Experiments: Is There More to the Argument? 71 (Proceedings): 11391151.Google Scholar
Shea, William R. (1972), Galileo’s Intellectual Revolution. London: Macmillan.Google Scholar
Sorensen, Roy A. (1992), Thought Experiments. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Tetlock, Philip E., and Belkin, Aaron (eds.) (1996), Counterfactual Thought Experiments in World Politics: Logical, Methodological, and Psychological Perspectives. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar