Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-jn8rn Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-23T00:51:13.325Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Theory in History

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  14 March 2022

Leon J. Goldstein*
Affiliation:
State University of New York at Binghamton

Abstract

Present-day interest in history among philosophers seems largely limited to a debate over the nature of historical explanation among those who for Humean reasons insist that all explanations must rest upon general laws and history cannot be an exception to this, and those who say the historians do explain and since they do not use general laws the Humean claim is obviously mistaken. Like the latter, the present paper takes the explanations of historians seriously, but unlike the latter it is not willing to limit the role of philosophy of history merely to the elucidation of the language in which historians give final expression of their work. Rather it recognizes that those explanations themselves set the stage for further inquiry in that they are required to be justified. It is here that the theories or general laws demanded by Humean analysis come in. After examining examples of general laws offered by way of example of what the “Humean” philosophers are supposed to have in mind, each of which is an immediate generalization of the explanation it is called upon to explain and is, hence, an instance of what has been called “the dogma of universality,” some examples of more promising prospects of theory in history are examined.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Philosophy of Science Association 1967

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

1

This is a slightly revised version of a paper which was read to the Boston Colloquium for the Philosophy of Science (November 1, 1965), and which will also be published in their proceedings, Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science, vol. 4.

References

REFERENCES

[1] Beer, Samuel H., “Causal Explanation and Imaginative Re-enactment,” History and Theology, vol. 3, 1963, pp. 629.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[2] Dray, William, Laws and Explanations in History, Oxford, 1957.Google Scholar
[3] Elkins, Stanley M., Slavery: A Problem in American Institutional and Intellectual Life, Chicago, 1959.Google Scholar
[4] Gardiner, Patrick, ed., Theories of History, Glencoe, Ill., 1959.Google Scholar
[5] Gardiner, , The Nature of Historical Explanation, London, 1952.Google Scholar
[6] Hanson, N. R., Patterns of Discovery, Cambridge, 1958.Google Scholar
[7] Hempel, C. G., “The Function of General Laws in History,” in [4], p. 349f.Google Scholar
[8] Nagel, Ernest, “Determination in History,” “Philosophy and Phenomenological Research,” vol. 20, 1960, pp. 291–317; p. 303.Google Scholar
[9] Pirenne, Henri, Mohammed and Charlemagne, London, 1939 and 1954.Google Scholar
[10] Popper, Karl R., The Open Society and It's Enemies, Princeton, 1950, p. 448.Google Scholar
[11] Scriven, Michael, “Truisms as the Grounds for Historical Explanations,” in [4], p. 454.Google Scholar
[12] Teggart, Frederick J., Theory and Process of History, Berkeley and Los Angeles, 1949, Paperback ed. 1961; pp. 1829, 51–66.Google Scholar
[13] Tilly, Charles, “The Analysis of a Counter-Revolution,” History and Theory, vol. 3, 1963, pp. 3058.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[14] Weber, Max, The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism, tr. Talcott Parsons, New York and London, 1930: references will be to the third British impression, 1950.Google Scholar
[15] White, Morton, “Historical Explanation,” in [4] pp. 356–73.Google Scholar
[16] Woodham-Smith, Cecil, The Reason Why, New York, 1953; (Time Reading Program edition, 1962.)Google Scholar