Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-r5fsc Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-22T05:04:36.405Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Specious Intrinsicalism

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2022

Abstract

Over the last 2,300 years or so, many philosophers have believed that species are individuated by essences that are at least in part intrinsic. Psychologists tell us most folks also believe this view. But most philosophers of biology have abandoned the view, in light of evolutionary conceptions of species. In defiance, Michael Devitt has attempted in this journal to resurrect a version of the view, which he calls Intrinsic Biological Essentialism. I show that his arguments for the resurrection fail, and I identify challenges that face anyone wishing to defend Intrinsic Biological Essentialism.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Philosophy of Science Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

I am grateful to Michael Devitt, Marc Ereshefsky, Larry Shapiro, Elliott Sober, Joel Velasco, and Peter Vranas for helpful comments and to Georges Rey and Robert Wilson for discussion of the topic. The Social Sciences and Humanities Research Council of Canada provided generous financial support.

References

Barker, Matthew J. (2007), “The Empirical Inadequacy of Species Cohesion by Gene Flow”, The Empirical Inadequacy of Species Cohesion by Gene Flow 74:654665.Google Scholar
Barker, Matthew J., and Wilson, Robert A. (2010), “Cohesion, Gene Flow, and the Nature of Species”, Journal of Philosophy 107.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Blomberg, Simon P., and Garland, Theodore Jr. (2002), “Tempo and Mode in Evolution: Phylogenetic Inertia, Adaptation and Comparative Methods”, Tempo and Mode in Evolution: Phylogenetic Inertia, Adaptation and Comparative Methods 15:899910.Google Scholar
Devitt, Michael (2008), “Resurrecting Biological Essentialism”, Resurrecting Biological Essentialism 75:344382.Google Scholar
Ereshefsky, Marc (2001), The Poverty of the Linnaean Hierarchy: Philosophical Study of Biological Taxonomy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Futuyma, Douglas (1998), Evolutionary Biology. 3rd ed. Sunderland, MA: Sinauer.Google Scholar
Futuyma, Douglas (2005), Evolution. Sunderland, MA: Sinauer.Google Scholar
Gould, Stephen J., and Lewontin, Richard C. (1979), “The Spandrels of San Marco and the Panglossian Paradigm: A Critique of the Adaptationist Programme”, The Spandrels of San Marco and the Panglossian Paradigm: A Critique of the Adaptationist Programme 205 (1161): 581598..Google Scholar
Hansen, Thomas F. (1997), “Stabilizing Selection and the Comparative Analysis of Adaptation”, Stabilizing Selection and the Comparative Analysis of Adaptation 51:13411351.Google ScholarPubMed
Hellberg, Michael E., Burton, Ronald S., Neigel, Joseph E., and Palumbi, Stephen R. (2002), “Genetic Assessment of Connectivity among Marine Populations”, Genetic Assessment of Connectivity among Marine Populations 70 (Supplement): 273290.Google Scholar
Hull, David (1999), “On the Plurality of Species: Questioning the Party Line”, in Wilson, Robert A. (ed.), Species: New Interdisciplinary Essays. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2348.Google Scholar
Mayr, Ernst (1970), Populations, Species and Evolution. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Mayr, Ernst (2000), “The Biological Species Concept”, in Wheeler and Meier 2000, 1729.Google Scholar
Mishler, Brent, and Brandon, Robert (1987), “Individuality, Pluralism, and the Phylogenetic Species Concept”, Individuality, Pluralism, and the Phylogenetic Species Concept 2:397414.Google Scholar
Sidelle, Alan (1989), Necessity, Essence, and Individuation: A Defense of Conventionalism. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sober, Elliott (1980), “Evolution, Population Thinking, and Essentialism”, Evolution, Population Thinking, and Essentialism 47:350383.Google Scholar
Sober, Elliott (2008), Evidence and Evolution: The Logic Behind the Science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Van Valen, Leigh ([1976] 1992), “Ecological Species, Multispecies, and Oaks”, Ecological Species, Multispecies, and Oaks 25:233239. Reprinted in M. Ereshefsky (ed.), The Units of Evolution: Essays on the Nature of Species. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 70–77.Google Scholar
Wheeler, Quentin D., and Meier, Rudolf, eds. (2000), Species Concepts and Phylogenetic Theory: A Debate. New York: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Wiley, Edward O. (1981), Phylogenetics: The Theory and Practice of Phylogenetic Systematics. New York: Wiley.Google Scholar
Wilson, Robert A. (2004), Boundaries of the Mind: The Individual in the Fragile Sciences; Cognition. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Wilson, Robert A., Barker, Matthew J., and Brigandt, Ingo (2007), “When Traditional Essentialism Fails: Biological Natural Kinds”, When Traditional Essentialism Fails: Biological Natural Kinds 35:189215.Google Scholar