Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-m6dg7 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-06T10:07:05.543Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Review of Caitlin Donahue Wylie’s Preparing Dinosaurs: The Work Behind the Scenes - Caitlin Donahue Wylie, Preparing Dinosaurs: The Work Behind the Scenes. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press (2021), 264 pp. $75.00 (paperback)

Review products

Caitlin Donahue Wylie, Preparing Dinosaurs: The Work Behind the Scenes. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press (2021), 264 pp. $75.00 (paperback)

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  20 June 2023

Matilde Carrera
Affiliation:
Boston University, Boston, MA, USA
Aja Watkins*
Affiliation:
University of Wisconsin-Madison, Madison, WI, USA
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Type
Book Review
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2023. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of the Philosophy of Science Association

Preparing Dinosaurs: The Work Behind the Scenes, by science and technology studies scholar Caitlin Donahue Wylie, presents the results of an ethnographic study of different communities of fossil preparators and their pivotal—though quite often unrecognized—role in vertebrate paleontology. After summarizing Wylie’s main contributions, we discuss how fossil preparation may be of interest to philosophers of data, especially those interested in metadata practices.

After being recovered, fossils are not immediately available to researchers but rather have to undergo a long process that eventually turns them from natural objects into specimens that can be studied (3). Fossil preparators are some of the people in charge of this epistemologically crucial process (chapter 1). Fossils might need to be separated from background noise by removing the surrounding rock matrix, to be reassembled, or to be made mobile for use in subsequent research purposes: as a consequence of this multiplicity of goals, preparators show great methodological flexibility in their techniques and approaches, usually informed by aesthetic considerations, tacit priorities, and a tendency to innovation and creativity (26, 29, 49). According to Wylie, the autonomy of preparators to make methodological decisions concerning fossil preparation is a defining characteristic of preparators’ communities. Preparators’ autonomy, in turn, is made possible by their relatively invisible role; the work of preparators is seldom recorded or mentioned in scientific publications, which reduces the potential for paleontologists to exercise oversight over preparators’ actions.

Despite the lack of standardized procedures, Wylie argues that preparators’ communities are built around shared values (e.g., patience, attention to detail, visual judgments), and common methodological concerns about fossil specimen preservation (chapter 2). Differences in abilities and skills also produce a hierarchical structure within preparator communities, differentiating technicians from volunteers and resulting in different tasks assigned to each group (94). Wylie’s analysis of communities is also informed by her investigation of the role that technologies play in the process of fossil preparation. In particular, the recent introduction of computed tomography scans to paleontological research, and the consequent possibility to avoid manually intervening on the fossil and thus potentially damaging it, has initiated a reflection by preparators on the value of different preparation techniques. Wylie describes the debate surrounding benefits and limitations of new technologies and how they coexist along with more traditional approaches to fossil preparation, insofar as they serve different epistemic purposes (chapter 3).

In the fourth chapter, Wylie discusses to what extent preparators and scientists need to iteratively negotiate their priorities to converge on a “researchable fossil” (138). The interaction between researchers and preparators revolves around a trade-off between maximizing research output and minimizing preparation time (142). This iterative negotiation is made possible only by a mutual understanding of priorities and values that also requires a common language to communicate and transform knowledge. In her analysis, Wylie highlights the mutual interdependence of researchers and preparators, under the common goal of advancing scientific knowledge, without which the two groups would struggle to align their opinions and values.

The final chapter of Preparing Dinosaurs is devoted to public science and how museums portray scientific practice by frequently installing windows into preparation laboratories in their exhibitions. Wylie carefully elucidates the purpose of showing the public preparators at work, which invites museum visitors to reconsider the standard conception of science as a static collection of facts in favor of a more dynamic, contextual activity. Wylie also points out a possible synergy between this educational goal and museums’ directive to entertain the public.

Through this detailed ethnographic exploration of what happens before a fossil reaches a museum’s exhibition or is used in scientific research, Wylie provides a convincing theoretical framework according to which knowledge is prepared via an iterative process in which different specialized research workers contribute to knowledge products. The metaphor of “preparation,” which Wylie applies to specimens, communities, technologies, and public conceptions of science, is supposed to provide a middle ground between traditional realist and social constructivist conceptions of science (for further discussion, see Currie Reference Currie2023). For philosophers of science, “preparing knowledge” can be a useful heuristic tool that emphasizes stages and protagonists of scientific research usually black-boxed by accounts of science that look only at the collection of evidence and the production of results, to the neglect of the complex processes that happen in between. For example, Wylie’s investigation highlights the various elements that enter the process of turning “natural objects” into “researchable fossils,” ranging from more individual judgments about the aesthetic value of a specimen to communal values negotiated through the iterative processes of preparing communities. As a result, Wylie’s ethnographic approach (above and beyond existing historical studies of paleontology; e.g., Rieppel Reference Rieppel2019) has the potential to be extremely valuable for philosophers of science, especially for those concerned with the nature and use of data and evidence.

One of the most philosophically interesting issues illuminated by Wylie’s account of “preparing knowledge” has to do with how data and metadata are collected and managed in a paleontological context. Several philosophers of science are in agreement with Wylie that we should think of prepared fossils as data or data models (e.g., Bokulich Reference Bokulich2021; Leonelli Reference Leonelli2018). Preparing fossils involves separating signal from noise, for example, just as many other data processing practices do. Additionally, as Wylie (Reference Wylie2019) has also argued, prepared fossils are underdetermined by “raw” specimens; preparators’ creative decisions shape prepared fossils for later use as evidence by paleontologists. In preparing fossils, preparators have to make some predictions about the scope of the future evidential use of the specimens, such as what material will and won’t be informative.

Philosophers and scientists alike are increasingly in agreement that one of the necessary conditions for use of data as evidence is availability of ample and usable metadata. For example, Nora Boyd (Reference Boyd2018) discusses the need for evidence to be “enriched” with metadata—both what she calls “provenance metadata,” about the origins of the data, and “workflow metadata,” concerning how the data have been processed so far. Sabina Leonelli (Reference Leonelli2018) has also stressed the importance of metadata for scientists’ ability to interpret data or reuse them in additional research contexts. One might, then, reasonably assume that the same holds in the paleontological context: that metadata about how fossils are prepared would be a necessary ingredient for their future use and interpretation.

However, one of the most striking features of Wylie’s account of fossil preparation and the fossil preparator community is just how seldom workflow metadata about fossil preparation are collected. By contrast, provenance metadata, concerning the fossil’s location and position before extraction, are often collected and used by paleontologists. For example, Wylie writes, “by choosing how to work with fossils, preparators make momentous, though rarely documented, decisions about the physical and epistemic characteristics of the evidence they prepare” (102). In chapter 4, Wylie also discusses the fact that the work of preparators is rarely acknowledged or discussed in scientific publications. Of course, across all of paleontology, there are bound to be exceptions—cases in which preparation metadata are systematically collected—and it would be interesting in future work to see if there are any patterns that delineate the research communities that adopt or do not adopt this practice. For example, Wylie mentions how paleoanthropologists and invertebrate paleontologists divide labor differently from vertebrate paleontologists, which consequently affects data management, publication practices, and more (12).

On the basis of existing philosophical accounts concerning the importance of metadata for enabling data to be used as evidence, we might, then, assume that the lack of workflow metadata in the context of fossil preparation would be a flaw in paleontological practice. On one hand, Wylie (Reference Wylie2019, 16) attributes this absence of workflow metadata to a general tendency of obscuring the work of making fossils researchable, a tendency that “limits specimens’ potential uses and interpretations as scientific evidence by omitting information about how they were processed.” On the other hand, she argues that the lack of documentation of fossil preparators’ work goes hand in hand with a lack of oversight of their work by the paleontologists themselves, which, in turn, preserves the preparators’ autonomy. For instance, she writes,

a lack of recognition can protect practitioners’ autonomous decision making, while, by contrast, imposing documentation of previously unwritten work can cause the insulting “eradication of discretion from skilled workers.” So if scientists begin to coauthor with preparators or record preparators’ methods in print, it’s likely that the scientists would pay more attention to preparators’ training and methodological decisions, and try to align them with scientists’ own relatively standardized backgrounds and techniques. This would limit or even deny preparators’ cherished creative problem solving and control over their practices. (208, citing Star and Strauss Reference Star and Strauss1999)

From a philosophical perspective, this conflict is surprising and indicates that there will be trade-offs between the potential epistemic benefits of metadata and the likely costs of collecting or reporting such metadata to the workers involved. Philosophers of the historical sciences may be able to provide advice on how to negotiate this trade-off, for instance, by welcoming Wylie’s (Reference Wylie2019) suggestion as to how preparators can record their work (in specimen records but not in publications) or by helping to describe the range of ways in which a lack of workflow metadata about fossil preparation techniques constrains or limits the evidential value of fossil data.

Furthermore, the emphasis Wylie places on the preparators’ autonomy—perhaps over and above the possible epistemic gains of imposing metadata reporting requirements on preparators—calls attention to one of the broader themes of Preparing Dinosaurs overall, namely, that science is not only conducted by and for scientists but incorporates the labor and expertise of a wide range of workers with different backgrounds, incentives, skills, and prestige. Wylie’s account of knowledge preparation thus serves as a needed reminder to practice-oriented philosophers of science that oftentimes the scientific practices that do not make it into scientific publications, or cannot even be learned about by talking to trained scientists, can have serious implications for the structure and scope of scientific research.

References

Bokulich, Alisa. 2021. “Using Models to Correct Data: Paleodiversity and the Fossil Record.” Synthese 198:5919–40.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Boyd, Nora Mills. 2018. “Evidence Enriched.” Philosophy of Science 85 (3):403–21.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Currie, Adrian. 2023. “Cleaning, Sculpting or Preparing? Scientific Knowledge in Caitlin Wylie’s Preparing Dinosaurs .” Biology and Philosophy 38 (2):10.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Leonelli, Sabina. 2018. “The Time of Data: Timescales of Data Use in the Life Sciences.” Philosophy of Science 85 (5):741–54.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rieppel, Lukas. 2019. Assembling the Dinosaur: Fossil Hunters, Tycoons, and the Making of a Spectacle. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Star, Susan Leigh, and Strauss, Anselm. 1999. “Layers of Silence, Arenas of Voice: The Ecology of Visible and Invisible Work.” Computer Supported Cooperative Work 8 (1):930.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wylie, Caitlin Donahue. 2019. “Overcoming the Underdetermination of Specimens.” Biology and Philosophy 34 (2):24.CrossRefGoogle Scholar