Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-vdxz6 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-25T04:10:36.298Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Relational Theories of Euclidean Space and Minkowski Spacetime

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 April 2022

Brent Mundy*
Affiliation:
History and Philosophy of Science University of Pittsburgh

Abstract

We here present explicit relational theories of a class of geometrical systems (namely, inner product spaces) which includes Euclidean space and Minkowski spacetime. Using an embedding approach suggested by the theory of measurement, we prove formally that our theories express the entire empirical content of the corresponding geometric theory in terms of empirical relations among a finite set of elements (idealized point-particles or events) thought of as embedded in the space. This result is of interest within the general phenomenalist tradition as well as the theory of space and time, since it seems to be the first example of an explicit phenomenalist reconstruction of a realist theory which is provably equivalent to it in observational consequences.

The interesting paper “On the Space-Time Ontology of Physical Theories” by Ken Manders, Philosophy of Science, vol. 49, number 4, December 1982, p. 575–590, has significant affinities to this one. We both, in a sense, try to formally vindicate Leibniz's notion of a relational theory of space, by constructing theories of spatial relations among physical objects which are provably equivalent to the standard absolutist theories. The essential difference between our approaches is that Manders retains Leibniz's explicitly modal framework, whereas I do not. Manders constructs a spacetime theory which explicitly characterizes the totality of possible configurations of physical objects, using a modal language in which the notion of a possible configuration occurs as a primitive. There is no doubt that this is a more accurate realization of Leibniz's own conception of space than the embedding-based approach developed here. However, it also remains open to objections (such as those cited here from Sklar) on account of the special appeal to modal notions.

Our approach here, by contrast, aims to avoid the special appeal to modal notions by giving directly a set of laws which are satisfied by a configuration individually, if and only if it is one of the allowable ones. One thus avoids the need for reference to possible but not actual configurations or objects, in the statement of the spacetime laws. We may then take this alternative set of laws as the actual geometric theory, and do away with the hypothetical entity called ‘space'. Yet at the same time there is no invocation of modality, except in the ordinary sense in which every physical theory constrains what is possible. So that a relationalist is not forced to utilize a modal language (though Leibniz certainly does.)

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © 1983 by the Philosophy of Science Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Adler, R., Bazin, M., Schiffer, M. (1975), Introduction to General Relativity, second Edition. New York: McGraw-Hill.Google Scholar
Hilbert, D. (1971), Foundations of Geometry (first published 1901). La Salle: Open Court Publishing Co.Google Scholar
Krantz, D., Luce, R., Suppes, P., Tversky, A. (1971), Foundations of Measurement, vol. 1. New York: Academic Press.Google Scholar
Luce, R. (1979), “Suppes’ Contributions to the Theory of Measurement”, in Bogdan, R. (ed.), Patrick Suppes. Dordrecht: D. Reidel.Google Scholar
Nerlich, G. (1976), The Shape of Space. Cambridge Mass.: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Roberts, F. (1979), Measurement Theory. Encyclopedia of Mathematics and Its Applications, vol. 7. Reading: Addison-Wesley.Google Scholar
Sklar, L. (1974), Space, Time, and Spacetime. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Suppes, P. (1973), “Some Open Problems in the Philosophy of Space and Time”, in Suppes, Space, Time, and Geometry (ed.). Dordrecht: D. Reidel.Google Scholar
Wrede, R. C. (1963), Introduction to Vector and Tensor Analysis. New York: Wiley.Google Scholar