Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-vdxz6 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-25T05:06:44.410Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Realism, Empiricism and Scientific Revolutions

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 April 2022

Abstract

The logical empiricists knew that scientific theories sometimes arise out of the attempt to reconcile or unify two existing theories. They also thought that, at best, old theories would be retained as approximations to their successors. Kuhn lost both insights when he rejected the logical empiricists' formal approach in favor of an exclusively historical and psychological one. But when Putnam tried to restore such ideas he failed to provide them with the historical support they require. An account of revolutionary unifications is defended as reconciling Putnam's realist ideas about methodology with Kuhn's historical approach.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © 1991 The Philosophy of Science Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

I am grateful to Dr. W. Demopoulos, Dr. N. Jardine, and Dr. T. Williamson for making helpful comments on earlier drafts of this essay.

References

Feyerabend, P. (1970), “Consolations for the Specialist”, in I. Lakatos and A. Musgrave (eds.), Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 197230.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gardner, M. R. (1979), “Realism and Instrumentalism in 19th-Century Atomism”, Philosophy of Science 46: 134.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hardin, C. L. and Rosenberg, A. (1982), “In Defense of Convergent Realism”, Philosophy of Science 49: 604615.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Heilbron, J. L. (1964), A History of the Problem of Atomic Structure from the Discovery of the Electron to the Beginning of Quantum Mechanics. Ph.D. Dissertation, University of California, Berkeley.Google Scholar
Hempel, C. G. (1962), “Deductive-Nomological vs. Statistical Explanation”, in H. Feigl and G. Maxwell (eds.), Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science. Vol. 3, Scientific Explanation, Space, and Time. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, pp. 98169.Google Scholar
Hempel, C. G. ([1948] 1965a), “Studies in the Logic of Explanation”, in C. G. Hempel, Aspects of Scientific Explanation; and Other Essays in the Philosophy of Science. (Originally coauthored with P. Oppenheim and published in Philosophy of Science 15: 135–175.) New York: The Free Press, pp. 245295.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hempel, C. G. ([1958] 1965b), “The Theoretician's Dilemma: A Study in the Logic of Theory”, in C. G. Hempel, Aspects of Scientific Explanation; and Other Essays in the Philosophy of Science. (Originally published in H. Feigl, M. Scriven and G. Maxwell (eds.), Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, vol. 2. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.) New York: The Free Press, pp. 173226.Google Scholar
Hempel, C. G. (1966), Philosophy of Natural Science. Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall.Google Scholar
Joseph, G. (1980), “The Many Sciences and the One World”, Journal of Philosophy 77: 773791.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Joseph, G. (1982), “Special Cases”, Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 63: 297310.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kemeny, J. G. and Oppenheim, P. (1956), “On Reduction”, Philosophical Studies 7: 619.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Krüger, L. (1973), “Falsification, Revolution, and Continuity in the Development of Science”, in P. Suppes, L. Henkin, A. Joja and Gr. C. Moisil (eds.), Logic, Methodology and Philosophy of Science, 4. Amsterdam: North-Holland, pp. 333343.Google Scholar
Kuhn, T. S. (1957), The Copernican Revolution; Planetary Astronomy in the Development of Western Thought. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Kuhn, T. S. (1970a), “Logic of Discovery or Psychology of Research?”, in I. Lakatos and A. Musgrave (eds.), Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 123.Google Scholar
Kuhn, T. S. (1970b), “Reflections on my Critics”, in I. Lakatos and A. Musgrave (eds.), Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 231278.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kuhn, T. S. (1970c), The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. 2d. ed. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Kuhn, T. S. (1978), Black-Body Theory and the Quantum Discontinuity, 1894–1912. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Laudan, L. (1981), “A Confutation of Convergent Realism”, Philosophy of Science 48: 1949.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nagel, E. (1961), The Structure of Science; Problems in the Logic of Scientific Explanation. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Pais, A. (1982), Subtle is the Lord—: The Science and Life of Albert Einstein. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Popper, K. R. (1959), The Logic of Scientific Discovery. London: Hutchison.Google Scholar
Popper, K. R. (1963), Conjectures and Refutations: The Growth of Scientific Knowledge. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Popper, K. R. ([1957] 1972a), “The Aim of Science”, in K. R. Popper, Objective Knowledge; An Evolutionary Approach. Oxford: Clarendon Press, pp. 191205.Google Scholar
Popper, K. R. ([1949] 1972b), “The Bucket and the Searchlight: Two Theories of Knowledge”, in K. R. Popper, Objective Knowledge; An Evolutionary Approach. Oxford: Clarendon Press, pp. 341361.Google Scholar
Putnam, H. (1975a), Mathematics, Matter, and Method. London: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Putnam, H. (1975b), Mind, Language and Reality. Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Putnam, H. (1978), Meaning and the Moral Sciences. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Smart, J. J. C. (1963), Philosophy and Scientific Realism. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
van Fraassen, B. C. (1980), The Scientific Image. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Watkins, J. W. N. (1970), “Against ‘Normal Science‘”, in I. Lakatos and A. Musgrave (eds.), Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 2537.CrossRefGoogle Scholar