Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-hc48f Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-23T00:20:18.356Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Numerosity, Number, Arithmetization, Measurement and Psychology

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  14 March 2022

Thomas M. Nelson
Affiliation:
Michigan State University
S. Howard Bartley
Affiliation:
Michigan State University

Abstract

The paper aims to put certain basic mathematical elements and operations into an empirical perspective, evaluate the empirical status of various analytic operations widely used within psychology and suggest alternatives to procedures criticized as inadequate.

Experimentation shows the “manyness” of items to be a perceptual quality for both young children and animals and that natural operations are performed by naive children analogous to those performed by persons tutored in arithmetic. Number, counting, arithmetic operations therefore can make distinctions that are not inevitably arbitrary, and conceptual operations can obviously have a status as natural events with psychology. If the elements and conceptual operations involved in mathematical systems were not inherent in physiological process, various primitive discriminations could not be possible. Also, since some calculi have a natural status in a given empirical circumstance, the axioms of others can not be satisfied. Therefore the psychologist when acting as an empirical scientist seeks a calculus having a structure whose elements are isomorphic with natural units of stimulus and response and whose operations are isomorphic with whatever natural processes are involved.

Measurement poses a special problem for the empirical scientist. It concerns but a single class of natural qualities and this only in a limited way. The concept of quantity has a natural counterpart but quantity and measurement are not wholly analogous. Measurement is defined, as H. S. Leonard suggests, as a theoretical activity. Measurement theory has a formal structure but empirical end. Measurement hypothesizes about the position of a particular quality within a definite range of qualities. It therefore is beholden to definite empirical restrictions.

Some hypotheses-making systems use terms and relations per se as the context and starting point for dealing with discriminable events. Such procedures are “transcendent.” In empirical science, questions are part of problem-solving activity and their reference is naturally restricted. In providing description and explanation, psychological researchers frequently use calculi in a transcendent way. This results in theories that are only quasi-empirical and “half” true.

The roles measurement plays in psychology are discussed. Of particular concern are those cases in which the results of measuring or a theory of measurement are used to define the “real” units, or the “real” relations involved in problematic psychological events, and thence to describe and explain behaviors of interest. Metaphysical or ontological usages of measurement sometimes occur. The implication of these arguments with regard to a view of empirical science is discussed.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Philosophy of Science Association 1961

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

[1] Barnett, S. The world and Dr. Einstein. New York: William Sloan Assoc, 1948.Google Scholar
[2] Bartley, S. H. Principles of perception. New York: Harper and Bros., 1958.Google Scholar
[3] Bridgeman, P. W. Reflections of a physicist. New York: Philosophical Library, 1950.Google Scholar
[4] Bridgeman, P. W. Probability, logic, and ESP. Sci., 1956, 123, 1517.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[5] Carnap, R. Foundations of logic and measurement. International encyclopedia of unified science, I. Chicago: Univ. Chicago Press, 1955.Google Scholar
[6] Cassirer, E. Substance and function. New York: Dover Public., 1953.Google Scholar
[7] Dantzig, T. Number, the language of science. New York: Macmillan, 1954Google Scholar
[8] Ducasse, C. J. What has science done to religion? The Centennial Review, 1959, 3, 115126.Google Scholar
[9] Duhem, P. The aim and structure of physical theory. Princeton: Princeton Univ. Press, 1954.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[10] Estes, W. K. The statistical approach to learning theory. In S. Koch (Ed.), Psychology: a study of a science, II. New York: McGraw-Hill Book Co., Inc., 1959.Google Scholar
[11] Helson, H. Adaptation-level as a basis for a quantitative theory of frames of reference. Psychol. Rev., 1948, 55, 297313.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[12] Hovland, C. I. Human learning and retention. In S. S. Stevens (Ed.), Handbook of experimental psychology. New York: John Wiley & Sons, Inc., 1951, 613-690Google Scholar
[13] Hull, C. C., et al. Mathematico-deductive theory of rote learning. New Haven: Yale Univ. Press, 1940.Google Scholar
[14] Jeans, J. The new background of science. (2nd ed.) New York: The Macmillan Co., 1934.Google Scholar
[15] Johnson, A. H. A. N. Whitehead's theory of intuition. J. gen. Psychol., 1947, 37, 6166.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[16] Koehler, O. The ability of birds to count. In I. R. Newman (Ed), The world of mathematics, I. New York: Simon and Schuster, 1956, 489498.Google Scholar
[17] Leonard, H. S. The formal presupposition of measurement theory. Paper read at Interdisciplinary Seminar of Measurement in the Social Sciences, Univ. Michigan, Nov. 13, 1951.Google Scholar
[18] Leonard, H. S. Authorship and purpose. Phil. of Sci., 1959, 26, 277294.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[19] Leonard, H. S. Interrogatives, imperatives, truth, falsity and lies. Phil. of Sci., 1959, 26, 172186.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[20] Maier, N. R. F., and Schneirla, T. C. Principles of animal psychology. New York: McGraw-Hill Book Co., Inc., 1956.Google Scholar
[21] Morgan, C. T. Introduction to psychology. New York: McGraw-Hill Book Co. Inc., 1956.Google Scholar
[22] Osgood, C. E. Method and theory in experimental psychology. New York: Oxford Univ. Press, 1953.Google Scholar
[23] Piaget, J. The child's conception of number. New York: The Humanities Press, Inc., 1952.Google Scholar
[24] Rapaport, D. The structure of psychoanalytic theory; a systematizing attempt. In S. Koch (Ed.), Psychology: a study of a science, III. New York: McGraw-Hill Book Co. Inc., 1959.Google Scholar
[25] Razran, G. H. S. Conditioned responses in animals other than dogs. Psychol. Bull., 1933, 30, 261324.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[26] Sarton, G. Six wings, men of science in the Renaissance. Bloomington, Indiana: Indiana Univ. Press, 1957.Google Scholar
[27] Schlosberg, H. and Katy, A. A double alternation lever-pressing in the white rat. Amer. J. Psychol., 1943, 56, 274282.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[28] Schurrager, P. S. and Culler, E. H. Conditioning in the spinal dog. J. exp. Psychol., 1939, 26, 133159.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[29] Stevens, S. S. On the theory of scales of measurement. Sci., 1946, 103, 677680.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[30] Stevens, S. S. The measurement of loudness. J. Acoust. Soc. Am., 1955, 27, 815829.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[31] Stevens, S. S. Problems and methods of psycho-physics. Psychol. Bull., 1958, 54, 177196.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[32] Taves, E. H. Two mechanisms for the perception of visual numerousness. Arch. Psychol., 1941, 37, no. 265.Google Scholar
[33] Whitehead, A. N. Science and the modern world. New York: Mentor Books, 1954.Google Scholar