Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-gxg78 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-23T00:54:32.008Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Instrumentalism, Parsimony, and the Akaike Framework

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2022

Elliott Sober*
Affiliation:
University of Wisconsin and London School of Economics and Political Science
*
Send requests for reprints to the author, Department of Philosophy, University of Wisconsin, Madison, WI 53706; [email protected].

Abstract

Akaike's framework for thinking about model selection in terms of the goal of predictive accuracy and his criterion for model selection have important philosophical implications. Scientists often test models whose truth values they already know, and they often decline to reject models that they know full well are false. Instrumentalism helps explain this pervasive feature of scientific practice, and Akaike's framework helps provide instrumentalism with the epistemology it needs. Akaike's criterion for model selection also throws light on the role of parsimony considerations in hypothesis evaluation. I explain the basic ideas behind Akaike's framework and criterion; several biological examples, including the use of maximum likelihood methods in phylogenetic inference, are considered.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Philosophy of Science Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Akaike, H. (1973), “Information Theory as an Extension of the Maximum Likelihood Principle”, in Petrov, B. and Csaki, F. (eds.), Second International Symposium on Information Theory. Budapest: Akademiai Kiado, 267281.Google Scholar
Burnham, K., and Anderson, D. (1998), Model Selection and Inference—a Practical Information-Theoretic Approach. New York: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Edwards, A. (1972), Likelihood. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Felsenstein, J. (1978), “Cases in which Parsimony and Compatibility Methods Can Be Positively Misleading”, Cases in which Parsimony and Compatibility Methods Can Be Positively Misleading 27:401410.Google Scholar
Felsenstein, J. (1983), “Statistical Inference of Phylogenies”, Statistical Inference of Phylogenies A 146:246272.Google Scholar
Forster, M. (1986), “Statistical Covariance as a Measure of Phylogenetic Relationship”, Statistical Covariance as a Measure of Phylogenetic Relationship 2:297317.Google Scholar
Forster, M. (1988), “Sober’s Principle of Common Cause and the Problem of Comparing Incomplete Hypotheses”, Sober’s Principle of Common Cause and the Problem of Comparing Incomplete Hypotheses 55:538559.Google Scholar
Forster, M. (2000a), “Hard Problems in the Philosophy of Science—Idealisation and Commensurability”, in Nola, R. and Sankey, H. (eds.), After Popper, Kuhn, and Feyerabend. London: Kluwer, 231250.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Forster, M. (2000b), “Key Concepts in Model Selection—Performance and Generality”, Key Concepts in Model Selection—Performance and Generality 44:205231.Google Scholar
Forster, M., and Sober, E. (1994), “How to Tell When Simpler, More Unified, or Less Ad Hoc Theories Will Provide More Accurate Predictions”, How to Tell When Simpler, More Unified, or Less Ad Hoc Theories Will Provide More Accurate Predictions 45:136.Google Scholar
Forster, M., and Sober, E. (2003), “Why Likelihood?”, in Taper, M. and Lee, S. (eds.), The Nature of Scientific Evidence, Chicago: University of Chicago Press, forthcoming.Google Scholar
Gilovich, T., Valone, R., and Tversky, A. (1985), “The Hot Hand in Basketball—On the Misperception of Random Sequences”, The Hot Hand in Basketball—On the Misperception of Random Sequences 17:295314.Google Scholar
Johnson, D. (1995), “Statistical Sirens—the Allure of Nonparametrics”, Statistical Sirens—the Allure of Nonparametrics 76:19982000.Google Scholar
Jukes, T., and Cantor, C. (1969), “Evolution of Protein Molecules”, in Munro, H. (ed.), Mammalian Protein Metabolism. New York: Academic Press, 21132.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewis, P. (1998), “Maximum Likelihood as an Alternative to Parsimony for Inferring Phylogeny Using Nucleotide Sequence Data”, in Soltis, D., Soltis, P., and Doyle, J. (eds.), Molecular Systematics of Plants II. Boston: Kluwer, 132163.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Linhart, H., and Zucchini, W. (1986), Model Selection. New York: Wiley.Google Scholar
McQuarrie, A., and Tsai, C. (1998), Regression and Time Series Model Selection. Singapore: World Scientific.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Morgenbesser, S. (1960), “The Realist-Instrumentalist Controversy”, in. S. Morgenbesser, P. Suppes, and M. White (eds.), Philosophy, Science, and Method. New York: Harcourt, Brace, and World, 106122.Google Scholar
Nagel, E. (1979), The Structure of Science. Indianapolis: Hackett.Google Scholar
Popper, K. (1959), Logic of Scientific Discovery. London: Hutchinson.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Possada, D., and Crandall, K. (2001), “Selecting Models of Nucleotide Substitution—an Application to Human Immunodeficiency Virus 1 (HIV-1)”, Molecular Biology and Evolution (18) 6:897906.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Royall, R. (1997), Statistical Evidence — a Likelihood Paradigm. Boca Raton: Chapman and Hall.Google Scholar
Sakamoto, Y., Ishiguro, M., and Kitagawa, G. (1986), Akaike Information Criterion Statistics. New York: Springer.Google Scholar
Schoener, T. (1970), “Nonsynchronous Spatial Overlap of Lizards in Patchy Habitats”, Nonsynchronous Spatial Overlap of Lizards in Patchy Habitats 51:408418.Google Scholar
Schwarz, G. (1978), “Estimating the Dimension of a Model”, Estimating the Dimension of a Model 6:461465.Google Scholar
Sober, E. (1988), Reconstructing the Past—Parsimony, Evolution, and Inference. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Sober, E. (1998), “Instrumentalism Revisited”, Instrumentalism Revisited 31:338.Google Scholar
Steel, M., Szekely, L., and Hendy, M. (1994), “Reconstructing Trees When Sequence Sites Evolve at Variable Rates”, Reconstructing Trees When Sequence Sites Evolve at Variable Rates 1:153163.Google ScholarPubMed
Swofford, D., Olsen, G., Waddell, P., and Hillis, D., (1996), “Phylogenetic Inference”, in Hillis, D., Moritz, C., and Marble, B. (eds.), Molecular Systematics, 2nd ed. Sunderland, Mass.: Sinauer, 407514.Google Scholar
van Fraassen, B. (1980), The Scientific Image. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Yoccoz, N. (1991), “Use, Overuse, and Misuse of Significance Tests in Evolutionary Biology and Ecology”, Use, Overuse, and Misuse of Significance Tests in Evolutionary Biology and Ecology 32:106111.Google Scholar