Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-p9bg8 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-23T00:31:12.439Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Game Theoretic Explanations and the Evolution of Justice

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 April 2022

Justin D'Arms*
Affiliation:
Department of Philosophy, Ohio State University
Robert Batterman*
Affiliation:
Department of Philosophy, Ohio State University
Krzyzstof Górny*
Affiliation:
Department of Physics, Ohio State University

Abstract

Game theoretic explanations of the evolution of human behavior have become increasingly widespread. At their best, they allow us to abstract from misleading particulars in order to better recognize and appreciate broad patterns in the phenomena of human social life. We discuss this explanatory strategy, contrasting it with the particularist methodology of contemporary evolutionary psychology. We introduce some guidelines for the assessment of evolutionary game theoretic explanations of human behavior: such explanations should be representative, robust, and flexible. Distinguishing these features sharply can help to clarify the import and accuracy of game theorists' claims about the robustness and stability of their explanatory schemes. Our central example is the work of Brian Skyrms, who offers a game theoretic account of the evolution of our sense of justice. Modeling the same Nash game as Skyrms, we show that, while Skyrms' account is robust with respect to certain kinds of variation, it fares less well in other respects.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Philosophy of Science Association 1998

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

Send reprint requests to Justin D'Arms, Department of Philosophy, Ohio State University, 350 University Hall, 230 North Oval Mall, Columbus, OH 43210. Or e-mail: [email protected].

We would like to thank John Doris, William Harms, Brian Skyrms, Neil Tennant, Mark Wilson, an audience at University of Pittsburgh Center for History and Philosophy of Science, and seminars at Bowling Green State University and Ohio State University for helpful discussions and criticism. We would also like to thank Elliott Sober and an anonymous referee for Philosophy of Science for detailed and helpful written comments. Robert Batterman's work has been partially supported by the National Science Foundation under Award No. SBR-952052.

References

Alexander, Richard (1979), Darwinism and Human Affairs. Seattle: University of Washington Press.Google Scholar
Axelrod, Robert (1984), The Evolution of Cooperation. New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
Batterman, Robert (1992), “Explanatory Instability”, Noûs 26: 325348.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Boyd, Robert and Richerson, Peter J. (1985), Culture and the Evolutionary Process. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Buss, David (1994), The Evolution of Desire. New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
Campbell, Donald T. (1975), “On the Conflicts Between Biological and Social Evolution and Between Psychology and Moral Tradition”, American Psychologist 30: 11031126.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cosmides, Leda and Tooby, John (1992), “Cognitive Adaptations for Social Exchange”, in Barkow, Jerome, Cosmides, Leda, and Tooby, John (eds.), The Adapted Mind: Evolutionary Psychology and the Generation of Culture. New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 163228.Google Scholar
Daly, Martin and Wilson, Margo (1988), Homicide. New York: Aldine de Gruyter.Google ScholarPubMed
D'Arms, Justin (1996), “Sex, Fairness, and the Theory of Games”, Journal Of Philosophy 93: 615627.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dawkins, Richard (1976), The Selfish Gene. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Dawkins, Richard (1982), The Extended Phenotype. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Emlen, Stephen T. and Wrege, Peter H. (1994), “Gender, status and family fortunes in the white-fronted bee-eater”, Nature 367, 13: 129132.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fodor, Jerry (1983), The Modularity of Mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gibbard, Allan (1982), “Human Evolution and the Sense of Justice”, Midwest Studies in Philosophy VII: 3146.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gould, Stephen J. and Lewontin, Richard W. (1979), “The Spandrels of San Marco and the Panglossian Paradigm: a critique of the adaptationist programme”, Proceedings of the Royal Society of London, B 205: 581598.Google Scholar
Kamil, Allan C., Krebs, John R., and Pulliam, H. Ronald (eds.) (1987), Foraging Behavior. New York: Plenum.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kitcher, Philip (1985), Vaulting Ambition. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Maynard Smith, John (1982), Evolution and the Theory of Games. New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Maynard Smith, John and Price, G.R. (1973), “The Logic of Animal Conflict”, Nature 146: 1518.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nash, John (1950), “The Bargaining Problem”, Econometrica 18: 155162.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pinker, Stephen (1994), The Language Instinct. New York: HarperCollins.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pinker, Stephen and Bloom, Paul (1992), “Natural Language and Natural Selection”, in Barkow, Jerome, Cosmides, Leda, and Tooby, John (eds.), The Adapted Mind: Evolutionary Psychology and the Generation of Culture. New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 451494.Google Scholar
Railton, Peter (1978), “A Deductive-Nomological Model of Probabilistic Explanation”, Philosophy of Science 45: 206226.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Railton, Peter (1981), “Probability, Explanation, and Information”, Synthese 48: 233256.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Skyrms, Brian (1994), “Sex and Justice”, The Journal of Philosophy 91: 305320.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Skyrms, Brian (1996a), Evolution of the Social Contract. New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Skyrms, Brian (1996b), The Social Contract Naturalized. MBS 96–31, Institute for Mathematical Behavioral Sciences Technical Report Series. Irvine: University of California, Irvine.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smale, S. (1980), “What is Global Analysis?”, in The Mathematics of Time: Essays on Dynamical Systems, Economic Processes, and Related Topics. New York: Springer-Verlag, pp. 8489.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sober, Elliott (1993), Philosophy of Biology. Boulder, CO: Westview Press.Google Scholar
Stephens, D.W. and Krebs, J.R. (1986), Foraging Theory. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Sterelny, Kim (1992), “Evolutionary Explanations of Human Behavior”, Australian Journal of Philosophy 70, 2 (June): 156173.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sterelny, Kim (1995), “Review of ‘The Adapted Mind‘”, Biology and Philosophy. 10, 3: 365380.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Symons, Donald (1979), The Evolution of Human Sexuality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Tooby, John and Cosmides, Leda (1992), “The Psychological Foundations of Culture”, in Barkow, Jerome, Cosmides, Leda, and Tooby, John (eds.), The Adapted Mind: Evolutionary Psychology and the Generation of Culture. New York: Oxford University Press, 19136.Google Scholar
Turke, Paul and Betzig, Laura (1985), “Those who can, do: Wealth, Status, and Reproductive Success on Ifaluk”, Ethology and Sociobiology 6: 7987.CrossRefGoogle Scholar