Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-rcrh6 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-25T01:41:09.205Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

A Consumer-Based Teleosemantics for Animal Signals

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2022

Abstract

Ethological theory standardly attributes representational content to animal signals. In this article I first assess whether Ruth Millikan's teleosemantic theory accounts for the content of animal signals. I conclude that it does not, because many signals do not exhibit the required sort of cooperation between signal-producing and signal-consuming devices. It is then argued that Kim Sterelny's proposal, while not requiring cooperation, sometimes yields the wrong content. Finally, I outline an alternative view, according to which consumers alone are responsible for conferring representational status and determining content. I suggest that consumer-based teleosemantics reconstruct the content of both cooperative and noncooperative signals and explain how a given trait can mean different things to different consumers.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Philosophy of Science Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

Ruth Millikan, David Papineau, Nicholas Shea, and Peter Godfrey-Smith provided valuable comments on the manuscript. I am also thankful for the responses of audiences at Pittsburgh, Bristol, Hannover (Germany), and Leeds, where different versions of this article were given. The generous support of the British Academy (PDF and OCG), the PSA, and the Arts Faculty of the University of Bristol is gratefully acknowledged.

References

Allen, Colin, and Bekoff, Marc (1997), Species of Mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Allen, Colin, and Hauser, Marc (1992), “Communication and Cognition: Is Information the Connection?”, in Hull, David, Forbes, Micky, and Okruhlik, Kathleen (eds.), PSA 1992: Proceedings of the 1992 Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association, Vol. 2. East Lansing, MI: Philosophy of Science Association, 8191.Google Scholar
Barnard, Chris (2004), Animal Behaviour: Mechanism, Development, Function and Evolution. Harlow, U.K.: Pearson, Prentice-Hall.Google Scholar
Bradbury, Jack W., and Vehrencamp, Sandra L. (1998), Principles of Animal Communication. Sunderland, MA: Sinauer.Google Scholar
Dretske, Fred (1988), Explaining Behavior: Reasons in a World of Causes. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Godfrey-Smith, Peter (1989), “Misinformation”, Misinformation 19 (4): 533550..Google Scholar
Godfrey-Smith, Peter (1992), “Indication and Adaptation”, Indication and Adaptation 92:283312.Google Scholar
Godfrey-Smith, Peter (1996), Complexity and the Function of Mind in Nature. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gyger, M., and Marler, Peter (1988), “Food Calling in the Domestic Fowl, Gallus gallus: The Role of External Referents and Deception”, Food Calling in the Domestic Fowl, Gallus gallus: The Role of External Referents and Deception 36:358365.Google Scholar
Krebs, John R., and Davies, Nicholas B. (1993), An Introduction to Behavioural Ecology. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Lloyd, James E. (1975), “Aggressive Mimicry in Photuris Fireflies: Signal Repertoires by Femmes Fatales”, Aggressive Mimicry in Photuris Fireflies: Signal Repertoires by Femmes Fatales 187:452453.Google ScholarPubMed
Marler, Peter, and Evans, Christopher S. (1996), “Bird Calls: Just Emotional Displays or Something More?”, Bird Calls: Just Emotional Displays or Something More? 138:2633.Google Scholar
Maynard Smith, John, and Harper, David (2003), Animal Signals. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
McGregor, Peter K. (2005), “Communication”, in Bolhuis, Johan J. and Giraldeau, Luc-Alain (eds.), The Behavior of Animals: Mechanisms, Function, and Evolution. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Millikan, Ruth G. (1984), Language, Thought and Other Biological Categories. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Millikan, Ruth G. (1989), “Biosemantics”, Biosemantics 81 (6): 281297..Google Scholar
Millikan, Ruth G. (2004), The Varieties of Meaning. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
M⊘ller, Anders P. (1988), “False Alarm Calls as a Means of Resource Usurpation in the Great Tit Parus major”, False Alarm Calls as a Means of Resource Usurpation in the Great Tit Parus major 79 (1): 2530..Google Scholar
Papineau, David (2003), “Is Representation Rife?”, Is Representation Rife? 16:107123.Google Scholar
Seyfarth, Robert M., and Cheney, Dorothy L. (2003), “Signalers and Receivers in Animal Communication”, Signalers and Receivers in Animal Communication 54:145173.Google ScholarPubMed
Shea, Nicholas (2007), “Consumers Need Information: Supplementing Teleosemantics with an Input Condition”, Consumers Need Information: Supplementing Teleosemantics with an Input Condition 75 (2): 404435..Google Scholar
Slater, Slater Peter James (1983), “The Study of Communication”, in Halliday, Tim R. and James Bramwell Slater, Peter (eds.), Communication. Oxford: Blackwell, 942.Google ScholarPubMed
Sober, Elliott (1994), “The Primacy of Truth-Telling and the Evolution of Lying”, in Sober, Elliott (ed.), From a Biological Point of View. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 7192.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sterelny, Kim (1990), The Representational Theory of Mind. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar