Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-s2hrs Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-10T01:10:14.906Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Constructing or Completing Physical Geometry? On the Relation between Theory and Evidence in Accounts of Space-Time Structure

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 April 2022

Martin Carrier*
Affiliation:
Department of Philosophy, University of Konstanz

Abstract

The aim of this paper is to discuss the relation between the observation basis and the theoretical principles of General Relativity. More specifically, this relation is analyzed with respect to constructive axiomatizations of the observation basis of space-time theories, on the one hand, and in attempts to complete them, on the other. The two approaches exclude one another so that a choice between them is necessary. I argue that the completeness approach is preferable for methodological reasons.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © 1990 by the Philosophy of Science Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

I wish to acknowledge the benefits of discussions with my colleague Claus Lämmerzahl (University of Konstanz) about the physical aspects of the problems addressed in this paper.

References

Bohr, N. and Rosenfeld, L. (1933), “On the Question of the Measurability of Electromagnetic Field Quantities”, in R. S. Cohen and J. T. Stachel (eds.), Selected Papers of Léon Rosenfeld. Dordrecht: Reidel, 1979 pp. 357400.Google Scholar
Carrier, M. (1986), “Wissenschaftsgeschichte, rationale Rekonstruktion und die Begründung von Methodologien”, Zeitschrift für allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 17: 201228.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carrier, M. (1989), “Circles without Circularity. Testing Theories by Theory-laden Observations”, in J. Brown and J. Mittelstrass (eds.), An Intimate Relation: Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science Presented to Robert E. Butts on his 60th Birthday. Dordrecht: Reidel, pp. 405428.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Coleman, R. A. and Korte, H. (1980), “Jet Bundles and Path Structures”, Journal of Mathematical Physics 21: 13401351.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ehlers, J., Pirani, F. A. E. and Schild, A. (1972), “The Geometry of Free Fall and Light Propagation”, in L. O'Raifeartaigh (ed.), General Relativity. Papers in Honour of J. L. Synge. Oxford: Clarendon, pp. 6384.Google Scholar
Ehlers, J. and Schild, A. (1973), “Geometry in a Manifold with Projective Geometry”, Communications in Mathematical Physics 32: 119146.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Einstein, A. (1920), “Remark”, Physikalische Zeitschrift 21: 662.Google Scholar
Einstein, A. [1949] (1970), “Autobiographical Notes/Remarks on the Essays Appearing in this Collective Volume”, in P. A. Schilpp (ed.), Albert Einstein. Philosopher-Scientist. La Salle, Illinois: Open Court, pp. 1–94, 663688.Google Scholar
Feigl, H. (1950), “Existential Hypotheses. Realistic versus Phenomenalistic Interpretations”, Philosophy of Science 17: 3562.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Friedman, M. (1983), Foundations of Space-Time Theories. Relativistic Physics and Philosophy of Science. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Glymour, C. (1977), “The Epistemology of Geometry”, Nous 11: 227251.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Grünbaum, A. (1973), Philosophical Problems of Space and Time. Dordrecht: Reidel.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Marzke, R. F. and Wheeler, J. A. (1964), “Gravitation as Geometry I. The Geometry of Space-Time and the Geometrodynamical Standard Meter”, in H.-Y. Chiu and W. F. Hoffman (eds.), Gravitation and Relativity. New York: Benjamin, pp. 4064.Google Scholar
Misner, C. W., Thorne, K. S. and Wheeler, J. A. (1973), Gravitation. San Francisco: Freeman.Google Scholar
Poincaré, H. [1902] (1968), La science et l'hypothèse. Paris: Flammarion.Google Scholar
Reichenbach, H. [1924] (1965), Axiomatik der relativistischen Raum-Zeit-Lehre. Braunschweig: Vieweg.Google Scholar
Reichenbach, H. [1928] (1965), The Philosophy of Space and Time. New York: Dover.Google Scholar
Reichenbach, H. [1938] (1966), Experience and Prediction. An Analysis of the Foundations and the Structure of Knowledge. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Sklar, L. (1977), “Facts, Conventions, and Assumptions in the Theory of Space-Time”, in J. Earman, C. Glymour, and J. Stachel (eds.), Foundations of Space-Time Theories (Minn. Stud. Philos. Sci. VIII). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, pp. 206274.Google Scholar
Stephani, H. (1980), Allgemeine Relativitätstheorie. Eine Einführung in die Theorie des Gravitationsfeldes. East Berlin: Deutscher Verlag der Wissenschaften.Google Scholar
Synge, J. [1960] (1971), Relativity: The General Theory. Amsterdam: North-Holland Publishing Company.Google Scholar
Weinberg, S. (1972), Gravitation and Cosmology. Principles and Applications of the General Theory of Relativity. New York: Wiley.Google Scholar