Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-vdxz6 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-24T19:50:19.377Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The Churchlands on Methodological Solipsism and Computational Psychology

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 April 2022

Ausonio Marras*
Affiliation:
Department of Philosophy, University of Western Ontario

Abstract

This paper addresses a recent argument of the Churchlands against the “linguistic-rationalist” tradition exemplified by current cognitive-computational psychology. Because of its commitment to methodological solipsism–the argument goes–computational psychology cannot provide an account of how organisms are able to represent and “hook up to” the world. First I attempt to determine the exact nature of this charge and its relation to the Churchlands' long-standing polemic against ‘folk psychology’ and the linguistic-rationalist methodology. I then turn my attention to the Churchlands' account of what it is for computational psychology to be methodologically solipsistic. I argue that there is no reason to suppose that methodological solipsism commits one to a purely syntactic theory of the mind (of the kind that Stephen Stich has recently advocated): the formality constraints that methodological solipsism imposes on psychological explanation do not exclude ‘essential’ reference to the representational content of mental states, as long as this content is construed in the ‘narrow’ sense. I conclude by raising a problem for computational psychology that may provide some real cause for concern.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © 1985 by the Philosophy of Science Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

An earlier and shorter version of this paper was read at the APA Western Division Meetings held in Chicago in April 1983. Titled “Taming the Wild Epistemic Engine,“ the paper was a reply to Patricia S. Churchland and Paul M. Churchland's symposium paper, “Stalking the Wild Epistemic Engine” (1983). I am grateful to the Social Sciences and Humanities Research Council of Canada for support in this research. The paper underwent some minor revisions prompted by a referee's comments, for which I am grateful. I have also benefited from helpful comments provided by William Demopoulos and Edward Stabler, Jr.

References

Churchland, Patricia S. (1980), “A Perspective on Mind-Brain Research”, The Journal of Philosophy 77: 85207.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Churchland, Paul M. (1979), Scientific Realism and the Plasticity of Mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Churchland, Paul M. (1981), “Eliminative Materialism and the Propositional Attitudes”, The Journal of Philosophy 78: 6790.Google Scholar
Churchland, Patricia S, and Churchland, Paul M. (1983), “Stalking the Wild Epistemic Engine”, Noûs 17: 518.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cummins, Robert (1980), “Causes and Representations”, The Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3: 76.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dennett, Daniel C. (1975), “Intentional Systems”, in Brainstorms. Cambridge: The MIT Press/A Bradford Book.Google Scholar
Fodor, Jerry (1975), The Language of Thought. New York: Thomas Y. Crowell.Google Scholar
Fodor, Jerry (1978), “Computation and Reduction”, in Perception and the Philosophy of Science, Savage, C. Wade (ed.). Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science. Vol. 9. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. Reprinted in Fodor (1981a).Google Scholar
Fodor, Jerry (1980), “Methodological Solipsism Considered as a Research Strategy in Cognitive Psychology”, The Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3: 6373. Reprinted in Fodor (1981a).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fodor, Jerry (1981a), Representations. Cambridge: The MIT Press/A Bradford Book.Google Scholar
Fodor, Jerry (1981b), “Introduction: Something on the State of the Art”, in Fodor (1981a).Google Scholar
Fodor, Jerry (forthcoming), “Narrow Content and Meaning Holism”.Google Scholar
Fodor, Jerry, and Block, Ned (n.d.), “Cognitivism and the Analogue-Digital Distinction”. Manuscript.Google Scholar
Kosslyn, S. (1975), “Information Representation in Visual Images”, Cognitive Psychology 7: 341–70.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Loar, Brian (1981), Mind and Meaning. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Marr, D. (1980), Vision. San Francisco: W. H. Freeman.Google ScholarPubMed
Minsky, M. (1981), “A Framework for Representing Knowledge”, in Mind Design, Haugeland, J. (ed.). Cambridge: The MIT Press.Google Scholar
Putnam, Hilary (1975), “The Meaning of ‘Meaning‘”, in Language, Mind and Knowledge, Gunderson, Keith (ed.). Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science. Vol. 7. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Pylyshyn, Zenon (1980a), “Computation and Cognition: Issues in the Foundations of Cognitive Science”, The Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3: 111–32.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pylyshyn, Zenon (1980b), “Cognitive Representations and the Process-Architecture Distinction”, The Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3: 154–69.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pylyshyn, Zenon (1983), “Whereof One Cannot Speak … Or, What's Really in Your Mind?”, Presidential Address to the Society for Philosophy and Psychology, London, Ontario. Published in the Technical Memorandum Series, The University of Western Ontario Centre for Cognitive Science. Cogmem #3, February 1983.Google Scholar
Pylyshyn, Zenon (1984), Cognition and Computation: Toward a Foundation of Cognitive Science. Cambridge: The MIT Press/A Bradford Book.Google Scholar
Schank, R., and Ableson, R. (1977), Scripts, Plans, Goals and Understanding. Hillsdale, NJ: Laurence Earlbaum Associates.Google Scholar
Stich, Stephen (1981), “On the Ascription of Content”, in Thought and Object, Andrew Woodfield. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Stich, Stephen (1983), From Folk Psychology to Cognitive Science: The Case Against Belief. Cambridge: The MIT Press/A Bradford Book.Google Scholar
Winograd, Terry (1976), “Artificial Intelligence and Language Comprehension”, in Artificial Intelligence and Language Comprehension. Washington DC: National Institute of Education.Google Scholar