Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-dzt6s Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-23T00:54:37.726Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Belief and Propositions

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  14 March 2022

Arthur Pap*
Affiliation:
Yale University

Extract

The repudiation of propositions as “obscure entities” which is prevalent among logicians and philosophers of “nominalistic” persuasion, is frequently justified by pointing out that no agreement seems ever to have been reached about the identity-condition of propositions. And if we cannot specify, so they argue, under what conditions two sentences express the same proposition, then we use the word “proposition” without any clear meaning. Quine, for example, feels far less uneasy about quantification over class-variables than about quantification over attribute-variables and propositional variables, because there is a clear criterion for deciding whether we are dealing with two classes or with only one class referred to by different predicates: two classes are identical if they have the same membership. And such a criterion of identity is alleged to be lacking for intensions.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © 1957, The Williams & Wilkins Company

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1. Carnap, R., Meaning and Necessity, Chicago 1947.Google Scholar
2. “On Belief Sentences”, reply to Alonzo Church, in Philosophy and Analysis, ed. M. Macdonald, Oxford 1954.Google Scholar
3. “Semantics, Empiricism and Ontology”, in Linsky (ed.), Semantics and the Philosophy of Language, Urbana (Ill.), 1952.Google Scholar
4. “Testability and Meaning”, in Philosophy of Science 1936/1937.Google Scholar
5. Goodman, N., “On a Pseudo Test of Synonymy”, Philosophical Studies, Dec. 1952.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
6. Hempel, C. G., Fundamentals of Concept Formation in Empirical Science, Int. Encyclopedia of Unified Science, vol. II, no. 7.Google Scholar
7. “A logical appraisal of operationism”, Scientific Monthly, Oct. 1954.Google Scholar
8. Linsky, L., “Some notes on Carnap's concept of intensional isomorphism and the paradox of analysis”, Philosophy of Science 1949.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
9. Mates, B., “Synonymity”, in Linsky (ed.), loc. cit. (see (3)).Google Scholar
10. Pap, A., “Belief, Synonymity and Analysis”, Philosophical Studies, Jan. 1955.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
11. “Necessary Propositions and Linguistic Rules”, in Semantica (Archivio di Filosofia, Rome 1955).Google Scholar
12. “Reduction Sentences and Disposition Concepts”, forthcoming in The Philosophy of Rudolf Carnap (Library of Living Philosophers, ed. A. Schilpp).Google Scholar
13. “Reduction Sentences and Open Concepts”, Methodos vol. V, no. 17.Google Scholar
14. Quine, W. V., “Designation and Existence”, in Feigl and Sellars, Readings in Philosophical Analysis.Google Scholar

A correction has been issued for this article: