Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-lj6df Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-08T13:10:10.217Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Religious Liberty, Same-Sex Marriage and Public Accommodations

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  07 February 2018

Abstract

Against the legal recognition of same-sex marriage, many advocates of religious liberty argue that those who adhere to “traditional” understandings of marriage should not be forced to “recognize” same-sex marriages. This includes exempting individual business owners engaged in commercial activity from anti-discrimination laws. I argue that such exemptions overreach. Equal access to the commercial arena is an essential feature of life in America’s commercial republic, which means that public accommodations should not be given exemptions on religious grounds. Yet this does not require business owners to morally approve of same-sex marriage; nor does it require them to grant same-sex marriages “equal concern and respect.” Rather, it requires simple toleration, which is compatible with moral disapproval. Indeed, I argue that this is the very sort of toleration at the foundation of religious liberty in America. Efforts to grant religious exemptions to anti-discrimination laws invite the return of religious conflict and discrimination. Prohibiting discrimination on the basis of sexual orientation in public accommodations is necessary not only for equal citizenship, but to maintain the regime of toleration that undergirds religious liberty in a pluralistic democracy.

Type
Special Section: The Politics of Inclusion and Exclusion
Copyright
Copyright © American Political Science Association 2018 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

References

Allen, Danielle S. 2004. Talking to Strangers: Anxieties of Citizenship since Brown v. The Board of Education. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Amar, Akhil Reed. 1998. The Bill of Rights: Creation and Reconstruction. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Barber, Sotirios A. 2014. Constitutional Failure. Lawrence: University Press of Kansas.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bedi, Sonu. 2013. Beyond Race, Sex, and Sexual Orientation: Legal Equality without Identity. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Bedi, Sonu. 2014. “The Scope of Formal Equality of Opportunity: The Horizontal Effect of Rights in a Liberal Constitution” Political Theory 42(6): 716–38.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bejan, Teresa. 2015. “Evangelical Toleration.” Journal of Politics 77(4): 1103–14.Google Scholar
Bejan, Teresa. 2017. Mere Civility: Disagreement and the Limits of Toleration. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Bejan, Teresa M. and Garsten, Bryan. 2014. “The Difficult Work of Liberal Civility.” In Civility, Legality, and Justice in America, ed. Sarat, Austin. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Berlin, Isaiah. 2014. Political Ideas in the Romantic Age. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Brettschneider, Corey. 2012. When the State Speaks, What Should It Say? Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Brown, Wendy. 2006. Regulating Aversion: Tolerance in the Age of Identity and Empire. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Brown, Wendy and Forst, Rainer. 2014. The Power of Tolerance: A Debate. New York: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Butler, Judith. 2000. “Appearances Aside.” California Law Review 88(1): 5564.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Courtney, Paul Vincent. 2015. “Prohibiting Sexual Orientation Discrimination in Public Accommodations: A Common Law Approach.” University of Pennsylvania Law Review 163: 1497–537.Google Scholar
Davis, Heath Fogg. 2014. “Sex-Classification Policies as Transgender Discrimination: An Intersectional Critique” Perspectives on Politics 12(1): 4560.Google Scholar
Dworkin, Ronald. 1978. Taking Rights Seriously. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Elkin, Stephen L. 2006. Reconstructing the Commercial Republic: Constitutional Design after Madison. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Engel, Stephen M. 2015. “Developmental Perspectives on Lesbian and Gay Politics: Fragmented Citizenship in a Fragmented State” Perspectives on Politics 13(2): 287311.Google Scholar
Epstein, Richard A. 2014. “Public Accommodations Under the Civil Rights Act of 1964: Why Freedom of Association Counts as a Human Right.” Stanford Law Review 66: 1241–92.Google Scholar
Finn, John E. 2014. Peopling the Constitution. Lawrence, KS: University Press of Kansas.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fischel, Joseph J. 2016. “A Discussion of Macedo’s Just Married.” Perspectives on Politics 14(3): 793–94.Google Scholar
Fish, Stanley. 1999. The Trouble with Principle. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Fleming, James E., Barber, Sotirios A., Macedo, Stephen, and McClain, Linda C.. 2016. Gay Rights and the Constitution. New York: Foundation Press.Google Scholar
Galston, William A. 2002. Liberal Pluralism: The Implications of Value Pluralism for Political Theory and Practice. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Koppleman, Andrew. 2006. Same-Sex, Different State. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Laycock, Douglas, Berg, Thomas, Blakenhorn, David, Failinger, Marie, and Gaffney, Edward. 2015. “Brief in Support of Petitions in Obergefell v. Hodges.”Google Scholar
Leiter, Brian. 2012. Why Tolerate Religion? Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Lilla, Mark. 2007. The Stillborn God: Religion, Politics, and the Modern West. New York: Knopf.Google Scholar
Locke, John, 2003. Two Treatises of Government and A Letter Concerning Toleration. Ed. Shapiro, Ian. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Macedo, Stephen. 2000. Diversity and Distrust: Civic Education in a Multicultural Democracy. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Macedo, Stephen. 2015. Just Married: Same-Sex Couples, Monogamy and the Future of Marriage. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
McConnell, Michael W. 2000. “Believers as Equal Citizens.” In Obligations of Citizenship and the Demands of Faith: Religious Accommodation in Pluralist Democracies ed. Rosenblum, Nancy L.. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
McConnell, Michael W 2013, “Why Protect Religious Freedom?” Yale Law Journal 123: 770.Google Scholar
Rawls, John. 1999. The Law of Peoples. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Rosenblum, Nancy L. 2000 “Amos: Religious Autonomy and the Moral Uses of Pluralism.” In Obligations of Citizenship and the Demands of Faith: Religious Accommodation in Pluralist Democracies, ed. Rosenblum, Nancy L.. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sandel, Michael J. 1996. Democracy’s Discontent: American in Search of a Public Philosophy Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Sandel, Michael J. 2005. Public Philosophy: Essays on Morality and Politics. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Singer, Joseph William. 1996. “No Right to Exclude: Public Accommodations and Private Property” Northwestern Law Review 90: 1283.Google Scholar
Singer, Joseph William. 2015. “We Don’t Serve Your Kind Here: Public Accommodations and the Mark of Sodom” Boston University Law Review 95: 938.Google Scholar
Smith, Steven B. 1997. Spinoza, Liberalism, and the Question of Jewish Identity. New Haven: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Story, Joseph. 1987. Commentaries on the Constitution of the United States. Durham, NC: Carolina Academic Press.Google Scholar
Taylor, Charles. 2007. A Secular Age. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Thomas, George. 2015. The Founders and the Idea of a National University: Constituting the American Mind. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Tocqueville, Alexis de. 2000. Democracy in America. Trans. and ed. Mansfield, Harvey C. and Winthrop, Delba. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Waldron, Jeremy. 2003. God, Locke, and Equality: The Christian Foundations of John Locke’s Political Thought. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Waldron, Jeremy. 2012. The Harm in Hate Speech. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Walzer, Michael. 1997. On Toleration. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Williams, Melissa S. and Waldron, Jeremy, eds. 2008. “Introduction.” In Toleration and Its Limits. New York: NYU Press.Google Scholar
Bell v. Maryland , 378 U.S. 226 (1964)Google Scholar
Bureau of Labor and Industries (BOLI), State of Oregon, In the matter of Sweetcakes by Melissa, Case Numbers 44–14 and 45–14Google Scholar
Civil Rights Cases 109 U.S. 3 (1883)Google Scholar
Elane Photography v . Vanessa Willock, No. 33, 687 (NM 2013)Google Scholar
Heart of Atlanta Motel v . U.S., 379 U.S. 241 (1964)Google Scholar
Katzenbach v. McClung , 379 U.S. 274 (1964)Google Scholar
Obergefell v. Hodges , 576 U.S. ___ (2015), slip opinion.Google Scholar
Bell v. Maryland , 378 U.S. 226 (1964)Google Scholar
Bureau of Labor and Industries (BOLI), State of Oregon, In the matter of Sweetcakes by Melissa, Case Numbers 44–14 and 45–14Google Scholar
Civil Rights Cases 109 U.S. 3 (1883)Google Scholar
Elane Photography v . Vanessa Willock, No. 33, 687 (NM 2013)Google Scholar
Heart of Atlanta Motel v . U.S., 379 U.S. 241 (1964)Google Scholar
Katzenbach v. McClung , 379 U.S. 274 (1964)Google Scholar
Obergefell v. Hodges , 576 U.S. ___ (2015), slip opinion.Google Scholar