Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-jn8rn Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-27T14:40:00.591Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The Immanent Potential of Economic and Monetary Integration: A Critical Reading of the Eurozone Crisis

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  08 June 2017

Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

The Eurozone crisis revealed fundamental flaws in the institutional architecture of the Economic and Monetary Union. Its lack of political steering capacity has demonstrated the need for a broad but seemingly unachievable political union with shared economic governance and a common treasury. Agreement on further measures has been difficult to achieve, as different actors have imposed divergent external criteria for the success of the Eurozone. As part of their heritage in Western Marxism, the critical theorists of the Frankfurt School sought to overcome such problems by identifying internal standards for social criticism. Building on their understanding of immanent critique, I argue that the Eurozone already contains the normative principles necessary to support greater political integration. While the citizens of Europe must provide the democratic legitimation necessary to realize this latent potential, the flaws revealed by the crisis are already pushing Europe towards greater transnational solidarity.

Type
Articles
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited.
Copyright
Copyright © American Political Science Association 2017

Starting in the fall of 2007 the world experienced the greatest economic downturn since the Great Depression. The so-called Great Recession began as a subprime mortgage crash in the United States, leading to the collapse of global financialized capitalism. By 2010 the contagion had shifted across two dimensions: what had started in the American private sector had moved across the Atlantic and into the public domain. Footnote 1 The result was a monetary, banking, and sovereign debt crisis among the member-states of the European Union (EU) that share its common currency, the euro.

Responsibility for the crisis of the Eurozone can be divided into three parts. Actors in the northern core, whose investors financed irresponsible borrowing and whose leaders sought to protect these interests, as well as in the southern periphery, which took advantage of low interest rates to bankroll unwise investments, share the blame for the proliferation of bad loans. The fact that this behavior took place within the faulty architecture of the Maastricht Treaty (1992), which created the Economic and Monetary Union (EMU) as a currency without a treasury and a common market without shared economic governance, turned these actions into a global crisis. Footnote 2

On a structural level, the inability of the southern states to devaluate a currency outside their control confronted them with the risk of sovereign default. In response to attacks by globalized financial markets, crisis-ridden governments were forced to adopt austerity to regain their competitiveness while facing ever-higher interest rates on their bonds. Successive infusions of capital—financed in part by taxpayers from the north—sought to lower interest premiums on southern bonds while protecting the investments of northern banks. However, this policy merely converted private liabilities into public debt. Footnote 3

The “flaws in the construction of the single currency”—combined with the international dynamics of financialized “casino capitalism”—brought on what Claus Offe calls “a crisis of crisis management.” Footnote 4 Instead of working together to address shared problems, “each country [has defended] its own interests while attempting to benefit from ‘free-rider’ tactics.” Footnote 5 Because policy repertoires have been recycled without addressing the underlying causes of the crisis, the citizens of the Eurozone trust neither national governments nor European authorities to address the problems of the euro.

The Eurozone crisis has also had a significant impact on the functioning of the EU. It has raised the profile of heads of governments and national parliaments, “highlighting the importance of domestic politics as a constraint to the creation of joint supranational transfer mechanisms.” By questioning the “permissive consensus” supporting integration and reinforcing its intergovernmental aspects, these events have threatened the EU as “an ongoing experiment with new forms of governance outside the nation-state.” Footnote 6

The increasing demand for fiscal transfers and the conditionality linking bailouts to reforms in domestic welfare policies has reinvigorated debates about Europe’s democratic deficit. Footnote 7 Recent events have revived traditional forms of Euroscepticism. They have also given rise to a new generation of what I call “euro-skeptics” seeking to repatriate control over monetary policy. Footnote 8 Unlike those who oppose integration based on emotion or ideology, opponents of the common currency contend that support for the EMU “should not derive from any theoretical or normative belief … but must be assessed on the basis of practical cost/gains analysis.” These critics do not oppose the euro or the EU as such, but rather “the ‘dogma’ of an ever closer union.” Footnote 9

In contrast to traditional Eurosceptics, who tend to draw on conservative and nationalistic principles, these new “euro-skeptics” hail from both the right and the left. Many of these empirical detractors of euro are political economists, who point to the fact that the EMU is not an optimum currency area. They argue that the Eurozone cannot benefit from a common monetary policy because it lacks both a political union with fiscal transfers and sufficient labor mobility to smooth out the differences in economic performance between the member-states. Footnote 10

Commenting on these events, Jürgen Habermas observes that the EU is “trapped in the dilemma between, on the one side, the economic policies required to preserve the Euro and, on the other, the political steps to closer integration.” Similarly, Offe notes that “the mismatch between what is economically necessary and what is politically feasible can be seen on both sides of Europe’s north-south divide.” Footnote 11 The crisis of the Eurozone thus presents the peoples of the continent with a choice: either dismantle the EMU by repatriating monetary policy to the member-states, or “significantly increas[e] the degree of political union” through “greater centralization and political unification.” Footnote 12

Using the approach to immanent critique developed by the Frankfurt School, I argue for the latter course of action. In order to overcome the resistance individuals feel to values that are imposed from the outside, the thinkers associated with the Institute for Social Research (Institut für Sozialforschung) developed a form of analysis that “immanently criticize[s] a given social order in terms of how adequately it measures up to the standards … it presupposes.” These critical theorists argue that when existing socio-political structures cease to function smoothly—as they have in the crisis of the Eurozone—the object of critique identifies itself as a social pathology. In the words of Theodor Adorno, “Immanent criticism is never solely purely logical but always concrete as well—the confrontation of concept and reality.” Footnote 13

I build on this approach to argue that further integration towards a banking and a fiscal union can help realize the underlying principles of the EMU. The euro was designed to limit the influence of a reunified Germany by replacing the continent’s dominant currency and central back—the Deutschmark and Bundesbank—with equivalents under joint European control. The EMU has failed spectacularly in fulfilling this normative objective, as the common currency regime has catapulted the Federal Republic “into the position of the undisputed great power in Europe as a whole.” Footnote 14

Drawing on the method of immanent critique, the Frankfurt School developed a two-step approach to critical theory that starts with a “crisis diagnosis” followed by “anticipatory-utopian” reflection on how social actors can emancipate themselves from the pathologies of the present. Footnote 15 Using this approach, I argue that the peoples of Europe must further their “experiment with new forms of governance outside the nation-state” in order to effectively confront powerful international markets that have been able to dictate policy to sovereign states by demanding ever-larger interest rates on government bonds. In order to do so the citizens of the EU will have to reassert their democratic authority vis-à-vis supranational and national elites, as well as international economic actors. Footnote 16

The argument starts by reflecting on the use of political theory as a way of analyzing contemporary developments. I then present a genealogy of immanent critique, showing how the thinkers of the Frankfurt School adapt this method to create a distinctive form of theoretical analysis. In this system, a critical “diagnosis of the times” (Zeitdiagnose) is followed by reflection on the social action necessary to overcome the problems identified. Footnote 17

The rest of the argument follows this two-step schema. In the third section, I therefore deploy immanent critique in its “explanatory-diagnostic” function. I engage in categorical critique to show how the problems of the Eurozone have pushed Europe towards a de facto political union in order to resolve the “contradiction[s] at the heart of the present.” Footnote 18 In addition to undermining the very concept of a common currency area, I also use normative critique to show that that the EMU has failed to fulfill its broader social goal of democratizing German power over its neighbors.

The gradual narrowing of the distance between the economically necessary and the politically possible has left Europeans in what G.W.F. Hegel calls “a state of unthinking inertia.” As a method of exposing internal contradictions in social praxis, immanent critique does not imply that social change is imminent. Instead, it provides the groundwork for combatting this complacency with “critical participation and appropriate action.” Footnote 19 In part four I therefore shift to the “anticipatory-utopian” stage of critique, arguing that Europe needs to create stronger institutions under the democratic control of the European public to fulfill the full potential of the EU as a postnational form of politics. Footnote 20 I conclude by reflecting on the dangers of relying too heavily on economic integration.

Political Theory, Integration, and “Real” Politics

It may seem strange or counterintuitive to use political theory to address issues that are usually discussed using economic terms. However, the crisis of the Eurozone touches on many of the most important theoretical questions in political science, including the relationship between politics and economics, the dynamics of democratic politics, the distribution of power within society and the decline of sovereignty in an age of globalization. The basic choice between further integration and retreat—though often framed in economic terms—is eminently political.

In addressing a political crisis by deploying the method of immanent critique, my argument is part of a broader move towards “problem-driven research” in political theory. The subfield’s traditional focus on the timeless questions of politics and its reluctance to address “questions of method and approach” have gradually given way to an interest in methodology and the connection between political developments and normative theory. Footnote 21 These trends have coalesced around the movement known as political realism, which seeks to “mak[e] a constructive contribution to politics.” Footnote 22

Political realists and other theorists pursuing problem-driven research have sought to take the “circumstances of politics” into account by focusing on institutions as the primary site of political action. Footnote 23 Although I share many of the goals of political realism, my analysis builds on the politically-engaged, problem-driven work of the Frankfurt School. The thinkers associated with this tradition draw on immanent critique to develop an approach to social criticism that proceeds from crisis diagnosis to practical reflections on the changes that are needed to create more emancipated forms of life.

Studies of the EU are particularly good examples of “the need for bridging empirical and normative analysis.” In addition to critical theory’s two-stage approach, there are many other ways to analyze the euro-crisis from a theoretical perspective. Footnote 24 For example, Alessandro Ferrara has adopted an approach based on John Rawls’s conception of public reason to show that the debates over the failed Constitutional Treaty displayed a nascent European identity capable of supporting further integration. Footnote 25

In a similar vein, Glyn Morgan has identified joint security as a legitimate justification for the EU. Such lines of inquiry have been spurred by the publication of an exchange of letters between Rawls, who takes a traditionally Eurosceptical position, and Philipp Van Parijs over whether the EU qualifies as a “realistic utopia.” Unfortunately, as Beate Sissenich points out, such Rawlsian approaches tend to “assum[e] away difference instead of engaging it.” Footnote 26

Pierre Manent, a noted skeptic of integration, criticizes the EU based on his reading of the history of political thought. Surveying the philosophical literature, Manent claims that there are only three stable forms of political community: the self-sufficient city, the sovereign state, and the universalistic empire. He sees the EU as a mixed polity forever caught between state and empire, between claims to sovereignty and aspirations to universalism. Footnote 27

Manent connects this conclusion to the contemporary crisis by arguing that Europe is experiencing a crisis of governance. He contends that a definitionally unstable polity like the EU can function neither as a sovereign government nor as an imperial metropolis. As a result, it ends up with “rules elaborated by an indefinite number of bodies and agencies responsible to no one.” As part of the crisis these technocratic bodies, which pride themselves on “their expertise and ‘competence,’” have become “rightly discredited” along with the “idea of governance” beyond the state. For Manent, solution is clear: “The illusions of ‘governance’ gone, government returns to its place” with the nation-state once again taking priority over supranational organizations. Footnote 28

In addition to Manent, one of the most forceful proponents of a return to the nation-state is Wolfgang Streeck, who proceeds from a sociological perspective that crosses the empirical/theoretical divide. In contrast to categories provided by Manent’s intellectual history, Streeck looks back to the lessons of the Wirtschaftswunder (“economic miracle”) and the trente glorieuses (“glorious thirty”) spanning the period from 1945 to 1975. This examination of Europe’s golden age leads Streeck to conclude that monetary policy must given back to the nation-states that enabled Europe’s postwar prosperity in the first place. Footnote 29

Streeck is a particularly interesting foil for my argument given his background in critical theory and his surprisingly rancorous public debate with Habermas. While Streeck and Habermas agree on their basic diagnosis of the problems of the euro, they disagree about whether this requires pulling back or pushing forward with integration. Footnote 30 Their approaches to this problem are also at odds. Whereas Habermas proceeds from an immanent critique of the present, Streeck argues for a return to the successful practices of the past.

My argument follows Habermas, both in style and substance. Compared with Streeck’s historical analysis and other external approaches to the “normative turn” in European Union Studies, immanent critique has two distinct advantages. Footnote 31 First, by evaluating social structures against their own standards, it avoids accusations that the criteria of judgment are “partial, reflecting the history and tradition of a particular society or group.” Second, by demonstrating to social actors that they are not living up to their own ideals, it is more likely to provide them “with some degree of motivation to follow [their own values] and to sanction compliance.” Footnote 32

Streeck’s position assumes that it is still possible to return to the practices of the postwar economic boom, where the nation-state was able to use its sovereign powers to exercise control over global market forces. However, there is much empirical evidence tracing the decline of sovereign power. Over the course of the twentieth century “the nation state has rapidly become an unnatural, even dysfunctional, unit … [with neither] the tools nor the political base to play an effective role.” Footnote 33 As a result, “the pattern of influence and decision-making that rules the world has an increasingly marginal connection with sovereignty.” Footnote 34

This “multifaceted erosion of sovereignty is a momentous change,” which has led to the search for new concepts to describe the decision-making capacity previously associated with this term. Footnote 35 Whereas political theorists increasingly think in terms of “legalization,” international lawyers have turned to “fragmentation” and “constutionalization” to capture this transformation. Footnote 36 Even when it is used, sovereignty has been redefined in functionalist terms. Instead of describing the Weberian “monopoly of the legitimate use of physical force within a given territory,” sovereignty now often refers to the state’s obligation to “preserve life-sustaining standards for its citizens.” Footnote 37

These changes “simply leav[e] no room for any valid notion of the state.” This trend is most pronounced in Europe. The creation of the EU as a supranational entity with independent decision-making powers that lie outside the constitutional infrastructure of the member-states has rendered the continental “nation-state hollow and its institutions meaningless.” Footnote 38 As a result, it is difficult to see the European state as the solution for reasserting the power of democratic popular sovereignty vis-à-vis international markets and globalized financial capital. Footnote 39

In the next section, I detail the Frankfurt School’s approach to immanent critique. I then apply this method to the crisis of the Eurozone. In contrast to Streeck, I argue that the only way to reassert the democratic power of the European peoples is to extend integration beyond the nation-state.

Critiquing from Within

Social criticism can be based on at least three distinct approaches: the normative discovery of objective standards, the constructivist invention of criteria or the hermeneutic interpretation of already accepted norms. Immanent critique crosses the boundaries of the latter two categories. As a form of reconstructive argument, it seeks to discover criteria for criticism through a constructivist interpretation of the internal norms of a social practice. The critic is thus “engaged in a form of critique that aims to employ normative potentials … [that] transcend the agreed-upon norms of a society, but are, in some way or another, nevertheless already ‘immanent’ in social reality.” Footnote 40

The critical theory developed by the Frankfurt School starts from the conviction that “apolitical reflections on praxis are unconvincing.” Despite their differences, thinkers such as Theodor Adorno, Max Horkheimer, and Herbert Marcuse agree that a critical social and political theory must maintain a commitment to what Habermas calls the “embedding of theoretical accomplishments in the practical contexts of their genesis and employment.” Footnote 41 This persuasion led the Frankfurt Circle to adopt immanent critique as a central pillar of their interdisciplinary research program.

Internal criticism has a rich genealogy. Although it has its origins in ancient Greece, where Socrates sought to show his fellow Athenians that their ideas were internally incoherent, it gained renewed salience in the aftermath of the French Revolution, “when situation-transcendent ideas for the first time became forces [capable of] spearheading the transformation of the existing state of society.” Footnote 42 Most importantly, Immanuel Kant drew on immanent critique in order to redirect “the liberal notions of freedom and equality which had emerged in response to the growth of state power against political domination and inter-state violence.” Footnote 43

A generation later, Hegel modified Kant’s “critical philosophy,” arguing that social reality becomes “immanently rational” when universal moral rules are actualized within concrete institutions. For Hegel, immanent critique ensured the relevance of theoretical reflection for the present:

The refutation must not come from the outside, that is, it must not proceed from assumptions lying outside the system in question and inconsistent with it … . The genuine refutation must penetrate the opponent’s stronghold and meet him on his own ground; no advantage is gained by attacking him somewhere and defeating him where he is not. Footnote 44

Building on Hegel, Karl Marx gave this form of critique a materialistic dimension by focusing on political economy and the contradictions in existing relations of production: “Remaining true to Hegel’s method of immanent critique, Marx … maintains that the historical process will generate its own critical standards.” He also turned immanent critique into a method of social change. Seyla Benhabib points out that for Marx, “the function of critique is not therapy and healing the wounds of the ethical as in Hegel’s case, but ‘crisis diagnosis’ enabling and encouraging future social transformation.” Footnote 45 This move gives immanent critique its practical bite.

The thinkers associated with the Frankfurt School inherited the praxis-oriented form of social criticism found in Marx’s early writings, which “delimits the field of radical social criticism and change, and at the same time posits criteria both for rationality of criticism and desirability of change, without reference to anything transcendent to history.” Given the value pluralism brought about by the onset of modernity and industrialization, the Frankfurt Circle seeks to “circumvent a skeptical spurning of value judgments without succumbing to normative dogmatism.” Horkheimer argues that this can be achieved “by relating social institutions and activities to the values they themselves set forth as their own standards and ideals.” Footnote 46

Unlike other modes of social criticism, which are based on external normative perspectives, immanent critique is rooted in social praxis: “On the one hand, critical theory and the critical theorist are rooted in, emerge out of, and are shaped by existing social reality; on the other hand, the critical theorist cannot accept existing social reality as it is but must instead critique and even condemn it.” Footnote 47 Instead of seeking an objective Archimedean point, the critic locates the transcendent within the immanent. Critical theory focuses on the pathologies of the present by recognizing that the “development of society itself gives rise to a problem situation objectively affording contemporaries privileged access to the structures of the social world.” Footnote 48 The Frankfurt School argues that the internal contradictions of the present are expressed not only through economic dysfunction, but also as “lived crises” experienced by concrete individuals. Footnote 49

As part of the broader movement known as Western Marxism, the first generation of the Frankfurt School interprets Marx as a critical thinker, not as the scientific economist whose theories served as the basis for Soviet (Eastern) Marxism. Footnote 50 This leads to a methodology that proceeds in two operational stages, demanding both “the analysis of the process of social reproduction with reference to systematic dysfunctions and antinomies, and also with reference to the dynamic possibility of a radical and historically progressive social transformation.” Critical theory therefore moves from an “analytico-theoretical” moment to a “critical-practical” (Márkus) stage that brings determinate social forces to “an understanding of their own situation from the standpoint of their ‘real’ interest and needs.” Footnote 51

In the first “explanatory-diagnostic” (Benhabib) phase, the theorist seeks to explain and diagnose the pathologies of the present. This involves categorical critique showing how the concepts used to explain the crisis undermine themselves in practice when they “are measured against their own objective content.” It also builds on normative criticism of the practices and norms governing the system as a whole. Thus, immanent critique is not just an analysis of the concepts of the social practice in question, but also an examination of its failure to achieve its broader social and political objectives, so that “the discrepancy between ideal and actuality becomes apparent.”

In order to fully engage with the problems of the present, social criticism must move to a second, “anticipatory-utopian” phase that “addresses the needs and demands expressed by social actors in the present, and interpret[s] their potential to lead toward a better and more humane society.” In its emancipatory capacity, critical theory reflects on how the pathologies diagnosed via immanent critique could be resolved through the action of concrete individuals and movements in the present. Footnote 52 However, the actual resolution of these problems requires that “the agents themselves … appropriate the interpretations, explanations and criticisms proposed by the theorist.” Footnote 53

The rest of my argument applies this approach to the crisis of the Eurozone. In the next section, I draw on categorical critique to show the “developmental pressure” the crisis has exerted on the Eurozone, pushing the member-states towards the kinds of supranational economic and political structures necessary for a functioning monetary union. Footnote 54 In addition to examining these internal, categorical contradictions, I also show how the EMU has failed to fulfill its internal normative goal of containing German power. In the penultimate section I proceed to the “anticipatory-utopian” stage of the argument, showing how the peoples of Europe can act to resolve the pathologies of the present by reasserting their popular sovereignty at a supranational level.

The Immanent Potential of the EMU

Conducting an immanent critique of the EMU requires a brief historical reconstruction of the euro’s effects on politics and economics within the Eurozone. After the introduction of the common currency at the turn of the second millennium the new member-states of Europe’s east and south took advantage of historically-low interest rates to make up for funds lost to budgetary consolidation. The crisis shut off the spigot, exposing large budget deficits that only grew as the governments of these states were forced to step in and cover the losses of large private enterprises. The result was catastrophic for the states on the periphery of the Eurozone.

A strategy based on recapitalization and backstopping might have calmed global financial markets if the leaders of the EU had acted quickly to ensure the stability and liquidity of their banking systems by making it clear that the core would not allow the periphery to default on its debt. However, German Chancellor Angela Merkel insisted that the guarantee against the default come from the individual member-states, not the EU as a whole. As panicked markets sought ever-higher interest rates to finance new loans, the crisis-ridden member-states of the east and south slid deeper and deeper into debt. Footnote 55 The crisis only abated when the president of the European Central Bank (ECB), Mario Draghi, made his institution into the de facto lender of last resort by declaring that Frankfurt would do “whatever it takes to preserve the euro.”

Public discourse in the north has focused on the “irresponsible” spending of the “lazy,” “work-averse” south. Southern calls for help were seen as an attempt to steal hard-earned northern money. The fact that German uses the same word for debt and guilt (Schuld) helped tie economic debates in the Federal Republic to moral wrongdoing by building on the linguistic connection between these two concepts. As David Graeber points out, “the difference between a ‘debt’ and a mere moral obligation…is simply that a creditor has the means to specify, numerically, exactly how much the debtor owes.” By making debt into a matter of “impersonal arithmetic,” the creditor states were able “to justify things that would otherwise seem outrageous or obscene” by distancing themselves from the suffering of people in the crisis-ridden member-states. Footnote 56

Southern calls for help were met with legalistic replies about the “no bailout” clause (art. 125 of the “Treaty on the Functioning of the European Union”). This position overlooks recent discussions about the possibility of renouncing “odious debt.” It also ignores the fact that the banks that lent money to the European periphery undertook a certain degree of risk—the same risk that they use to justify their profits. After all, “if a bank were guaranteed to get its money back, plus interest, no matter what it did, the whole system wouldn’t work.” Footnote 57

Although the northern insistence that southern debts be repaid in full helped placate voters in the north, it disregards the structural factors driving the financial collapse. What superficially appears to be a sovereign debt crisis is actually a currency and banking crisis. As Streeck points out, “it is not ‘our’ [‘northern’] money but that of the banks which is at stake, and not solidarity with the Greeks but with ‘the markets.’” Footnote 58

While some responsibility for the build up of sovereign debt lies with profligate elites in the European periphery, banks in the north financed this borrowing with open eyes. After the onset of the crisis these institutions argued that they were “too big to fail” to blackmail governments into repaying bad loans. This set off a vicious cycle between banks and the member-states, demonstrating that “sovereign debt markets can easily become a forum for both debtors and creditors behaving badly.” Footnote 59

The EU first recognized the “imperative to break the vicious circle between banks and sovereigns,” in a communiqué in June 2012 and repeated it following a European Council meeting in 2013. Breaking out of this pattern requires a banking union with increased supervisory authority, powers of debt resolution to negotiate the abrogation of liabilities generated by bad loans, and a deposit guarantee to protect the savings of individual citizens. However, such steps would have significant fiscal and political implications for the member-states.

Historically, successful currency unions have inevitably turned into political unions backstopped by sovereign authority. Although repatriating power back to the member-states is theoretically an option, it is untenable given that sovereignty has been “hollowed out” over the course of the twentieth century. Footnote 60 Resolving the crisis will therefore involve cross-border fiscal support for less competitive member-states, just as economically stronger states support weaker ones within the United States. This fiscal solidarity would also help address Germany’s current accounts surplus, which places “sever pressure” on the troubled economies of the south in violation of the EMU rules designed to maintain an internal balance between imports and exports within the Eurozone. Footnote 61

The political determination to keep the euro—summed up in Angela Merkel’s statement that “If the euro fails, Europe fails”—has not been matched by a readiness to accept the structural imperatives of a functioning currency area. Despite their protests and the public discourse blaming the debtors, the internal logic of the Eurozone and the economic necessities of a functioning monetary policy have gradually forced northern leaders to take steps towards banking, fiscal, and political union. The development of the crisis has demonstrated that common fiscal governance, the presence of a lender of last resort, and cross-border financial transfers are non-negotiable, internally-necessary principles of a monetary union.

This development is hardly surprising. In 2001 the president of the European Commission, Romano Prodi, told the Financial Times, “I am sure that the euro will oblige us to introduce a new set of economic policy instruments. It is politically impossible to propose that now. But some day there will be a crisis and new instruments will be created.” Footnote 62

Although they have always sought to do the bare minimum necessary to hold the system together, the progress of the EMU since 2010 has been astonishing, especially by the slow-moving standards of the EU. Upon closer analysis, the “community’s objective practices and institutions … contain … immanent normative potentialities,” a “realizable ‘ought’ which is immanent to the ‘is.”’ Footnote 63 In other words, the crisis has forced the realms of the politically possible and the economically necessary to gradually overlap.

The immanent potential of the EMU has acted as a “force towards opening up, learning and transformation in the concrete situation.” The general pattern of crisis management shows that the leaders of the northern creditor states have repeatedly been required to take up measures they had previously assured their constituents that they would never agree to. Footnote 64 The actions of Chancellor Merkel, dubbed the “master of crossing red lines” by the influential German weekly Der Spiegel, is the most glaring example. This is visible in her repeated violation of her own promises regarding fiscal support for Greece:

First she said Germany would not be sending a cent of aid to Greece. Then she assured Germans that Europe’s bailout funds would only be temporary. Finally, she denied that Greece’s first bailout package would soon be followed by a second one. Each time, she was forced to break her promises, and each time the amount of money the Germans are committing to support the euro became larger. Footnote 65

Despite repeatedly crossing red lines, Merkel has remained unwilling to do more than the minimum necessary to solve the problems facing the Eurozone on any given day. Instead of focusing on the big picture, she and the other northern states have addressed problems on an ad hoc basis. David Marsh refers to this phenomenon as “Merkel’s Law of Permanent Disappointment” because “the German cave-in is never complete enough to resolve the euro’s problems or to win more than grudging acknowledgement from supplicant states pleading poverty. But it nearly always goes too far for Merkel’s critics in Germany.” Footnote 66

The gradual resolution of the structural contradictions of the EMU is visible in the negotiations for a European-wide banking union with effective supervisory capacities, powers of debt resolution, and a deposit guarantee. Footnote 67 While Germany’s desire to protect its regional Landesbanken from centralized supervision has slowed progress on the first pillar, the European Council has reached an agreement allowing the ECB to perform oversight on Eurozone banks through the Single Supervisory Mechanism. This settlement has spurred negotiations on a Single Resolution Mechanism to complement joint supervision. Progress on the third pillar has stalled, but the “master of crossing red lines” may have to give in on this point also. Footnote 68

The increased interdependence created by the growing loans used to finance sovereign debt and the progress on common banking regulation is slowly pushing the nation-states of the Eurozone towards increased fiscal cooperation. Debt mutualization, most likely through Eurobonds issued on behalf of weaker members, will also probably have to be part of the equation. Joint bonds would have to be backstopped by the EU and the credit-worthiness of the stronger Eurozone member-states. This step would end the cycle of rising interest rates by allowing all members to share the same relatively low costs of borrowing. Footnote 69 Since it is hard to imagine any member-state agreeing to bear part of another’s debt without some form of fiscal oversight, a broader political union is on the horizon.

Up to this point, my use of immanent critique to understand the inner dynamics of the Eurozone crisis has been categorical, investigating how the practices of the Eurozone contradict the idea of a functioning currency union. In line with the “explanatory-diagnostic” phase of the Frankfurt School’s two-step approach to critical theory, this analysis must be supplemented by normative critique. Instead of focusing only on the internal contradictions visible within political economy, this move focuses on the broader norms governing the social system as a whole. Whereas categorical critique spotlights the internal problems generated by the concepts used to understand economics as a specific area of social life, internal normative criticism examines the basic goals of the practices and institutions in question.

The desire to contain Germany—which Henry Kissinger describes as “[t]oo big for Europe and too small for the world”—has a long history. During the postwar period, the division of Germany between the eastern Democratic Republic and the western Federal Republic served as a temporary solution to the “German problem.” Footnote 70 However, even in its divided state, the Deutschmark became Europe’s leading currency as a result of West Germany’s Wirtschaftswunder.

As Germany’s institutional “binding to the West” (Westbindung) made it less of a military threat to peace, the “German problem” shifted to the economic sphere. The member-states of the European Communities—the institutional forerunner of the EU—experienced inflation, devaluation, and monetary volatility as they struggled to keep up with the Federal Republic’s efficiency and productivity. Footnote 71 Their attempts to tie their monetary policies to those of the Bundesbank through elaborate exchange rate mechanisms gave birth to the idea of coopting the German Central Bank from the inside by replacing the D-Mark with a shared currency governed by joint institutions.

The opportunity to realize this project came with the end of the fall of the Berlin Wall in 1989. In exchange for allowing West German Chancellor Helmut Kohl to secure his place in history by reunifying Germany after 45 years of division, French President Mitterrand demanded “a European currency, with an immediate agreement in black and white, as a sign of German attachment to Europe.” Footnote 72 Tying reunification to the Federal Republic’s agreement to monetary union was meant to dilute German power. Mitterrand argued that “without a common currency, we are all of us … already subordinate to the Germans’ will… . The only way of having the right to speak is to establish a European Central Bank, where one will take decisions jointly.” Footnote 73

In the wake of the Eurozone crisis, it is clear that monetary union has failed to fulfill this goal. Instead of taming German power, the euro has actually increased the dependence of the other member-states on the economic decisions of the German hegemon. An institution originally designed to create equality between the member-states has actually threatened to create a permanent bifurcation between the core and the periphery, between northern creditors and southern debtors.

Leadership, Democracy, and the European Public

As a result of the crisis, “monetary union, initially conceived as a technocratic exercise … is now rapidly transforming the EU into a federal entity.” Footnote 74 Despite its increasing internal divisions, Europe may have to brace itself for another round of institutional deepening. The key question is whether increased integration will succeed in pushing democracy up to the European level or whether it will further alienate the people from a technocratic institution based on neo-liberal economic principles.

Most theorists have focused on the leaders of Europe as the actors who could rally the public to actualize immanent goals “by adopting [them] as a conscious aim.” Footnote 75 This is not the most appealing prospect. As the first cohort born after 1945 to take the reins of power, the leaders in office at the start of the twenty-first century lack the emotional connection created by memories of war and suffering shared by their predecessors. In Habermas’s words, they are “normatively disarmed” (normativ abgerüstet), “preoccupied with a short-winded approach to the day-to-day problems.” Footnote 76

Given the internal imperatives towards union, there is still hope that the crisis can push European leaders to adopt the economic measures necessary despite political resistance. This is also not necessarily a desirable outcome. While political leaders might be able to reach agreement “through the proven neo-functionalist model, without the participation—and possibly even against the will—of the populace,” such a development would further alienate European citizens from the EU. Footnote 77 Instead of following this path, Europe must generate greater popular legitimacy as it inserts itself into the fiscal and welfare policies, policy areas typically reserved for states.

As is often the case in such situations, political leaders have urged citizens and markets to be realistic about possible changes to the Eurozone. This kind of realism can easily slip into fatalism. As part of their conviction that “no facet of social reality could be understood … as final or complete in itself,” critical theorists have maintained that reason should seek to change social reality instead of accepting it as a given. Footnote 78

In order to think about how to confront a despondency that can block political action even in the face of obvious contradictions in existing social institutions, I have to switch to the “anticipatory-utopian” phase of critique, starting with the “require[ment] that a catalyst and agent of social transformation be specified.” This leads me to repose “the question of Who rules Whom?” Footnote 79 In modern societies, the answer to this query usually involves the identification of an office, position, or institution. Given the complex, quasi-federal supranational community model of the EU, the candidates include the leaders of the member-states, the European Council, the president of the European Commission, the president of the European Council, and the president of the European Parliament.

While this question is difficult in the abstract, “thanks to its economic might, Germany has been catapulted by the financial crisis and the crisis of the Euro into the position of the undisputed great power.” Any changes to structure of the Eurozone must have the support of Europe’s economic, financial and monetary hegemon. Ulrich Beck illustrates the key role that Germany plays in the euro-crisis with an example from February 2012, when Europe was considering the second rescue package for Greece. In reporting on the decision facing the EU, a journalist on the German radio reported that “today the German Bundestag will decide the fate of Greece.” Footnote 80

Instead of making decisions regarding the steps necessary to resolve the crisis jointly through the European Council or the European Parliament, the Bundestag has emerged as the primary check on democratic will-formation in Eurozone as a whole. This change has been driven by the Federal Republic’s Constitutional Court, which has used its powers of constitutional review to ensure that crisis measures negotiated between European leaders have to be voted on by the German Parliament. As a result, it has turned itself into the de facto legal arbiter for all of Europe. Much like the Bundestag, the Bundesverfassungsgericht has exercised its power over all of the member-states, despite only representing German interests.

These developments have exacerbated Europe’s democratic deficit. Much of the EU’s basic structure, such as its unelected executive commission, which is only partially responsible to an assembly of representatives from the nation-states, has existed since its inception in the 1950s. Footnote 81 Despite these problems, the EU has actually become more democratic over the course of its development, even in terms of popular sovereignty. The institutional deepening of integration since 1985 has accorded more and more power to the European Parliament. Since the inauguration of the European Council in 1974, the EU has also been able to draw more democratic legitimacy from leaders elected on the national level, because most important decisions have to be approved by heads of government with a domestic electoral mandate. Footnote 82

There are limits, however, to how far integration can go without developing its own freestanding democratic legitimacy through shared supranational practices of opinion- and will-formation. While many of the EU’s activities are technocratic and delegated even at the national level, this defense of the EU has lost its force as the Eurozone crisis has pushed Europe to expand its competencies into more democratically salient policy areas like fiscal policy. Footnote 83 The EU’s increasing tendency to act as a political union must also be complemented by more democratic decision-making procedures.

Although important European leaders—represented by constellations such as Robert Schuman, Konrad Adenauer, and Jean Monnet, who spurred the creation of the first European Communities, as well as François Mitterand, Helmut Kohl, and Jacques Delors, who undertook Europe’s transition from Community to Union—answered the call for further integration in the previous century, leadership will not be able to resolve the problems of the EMU on its own. Far from pointing the way into the future, “politics seems to be holding its breath and dodging the key issues at the threshold leading from the economic to the political unification of Europe.” Since the EU has failed to deliver on its promises of prosperity, Europeans have “let themselves be bothered only by problems that emerge in day-to-day affairs” with an increasingly nationalist focus. Footnote 84

Despite Germany’s hegemonic position, the answer to the question of rule should center on the citizens of Europe. The crisis has shattered the myth of the EU as a technocratic organization that has little effect on the daily lives of its citizens. Footnote 85 Given its increasing influence on the welfare and fiscal policies of the member-states, it is now clear that the EU is immensely political and has huge effects on the everyday lives of Europeans.

One result of the new supranational powers the EU has developed over the course of the crisis is that the peoples of Europe are increasingly “address[ing] the same critically filtered issues and contributions at the same time.” Footnote 86 While national media still dominate, in this nascent transnational public sphere “European issues are debated as questions of common concern using similar frames of reference.” Footnote 87 This, at least, is a positive development pointing to the potential empowerment of the citizens of Europe.

It is still unclear whether the rise of a more unified European public sphere will engender the social solidarity necessary to promote fiscal policy across borders or whether it can shift continental processes of will-formation from national leaders to the directly-elected European Parliament with an EU-wide mandate. The citizens of Greece and Italy have already asserted their will against the desires of the European Council and financial markets by toppling the technocratic governments of Lucas Papademos and Mario Monti. Despite the difficulties, the citizens of Europe must maintain the belief that they can embrace their necessary role as the actors who should be exercising sovereignty over the EU. Footnote 88

The prospect of further integration also raises the question of a two- or even multi-speed Europe. On the one hand, such a move would merely reinforce existing trends. From its origins, different member-states have pursued different goals, ranging from cooperation in market liberalization for the United Kingdom to a genuine desire for “ever closer Union” within the Franco-German motor of integration. Footnote 89 States on the institutional margins have done so by opting out of certain policies, most notably Schengen and the euro, treating integration as a buffet from which they can pick and choose, rather than as a prix fixe menu. On the other hand, transforming the EMU into an optimum currency area would require a more formal acknowledgement of this trend, which would have important psychological and political consequences for relationships between the core and the periphery. This fact merely reinforces the need for citizen participation in such a transformation. Footnote 90

Beyond Economic Rationality

A politically active European citizenry that uses its popular sovereignty to assert its will through the supranational institutions of the EU is crucial for the future of Europe. The struggles of states to respond to the financial crisis, which was driven in large part by a regulatory race to the bottom, demonstrates the need for supranational cooperation on the level of economic, financial, and banking policy. It is now clear that “the democratic states of the capitalist world have not one sovereign, but two: their people, below, and the international ‘markets’ above.” Footnote 91

Despite the successes of the voters in Italy and Greece in overthrowing the technocratic leaders imposed on them by external forces, they have not been able to fight off the neo- and ordo-liberal policy prescriptions dictated by global financial markets and the leadership of the Federal Republic of Germany. This fact reveals the flaw in the “back to the state” arguments presented by scholars like Streeck. Footnote 92 In order reassert its power in an age of ever-increasing globalization, the popular sovereignty of the people will have to move above the nation-state. As Habermas points out, “it is only through such new transnational steering capabilities that the social forces of nature that have been unleashed at the transnational level—i.e., the systemic constraints that operate without hindrance across national borders, today especially those of the global banking sector—can also be tamed.” Footnote 93

Through an immanent critique of the Eurozone crisis, I have shown that the developmental pressure of the common currency is gradually pushing the EU towards completing the EMU through increasing banking, fiscal, and political unification. The debates spurred by the crisis have also led to the creation of a nascent European public sphere, which could potentially create the processes of opinion- and will-formation within civil society needed to support these increased supranational political capacities. As a result, there is reason to hope that “expanding Europe’s political capacity for action” may in fact “happen simultaneously with the expansion of the basis of legitimation of European institutions.” Footnote 94

This argument should not be seen as panglossian. It is up to the citizens to assert their will against the forces of globalized financial capital. Unfortunately, even before their recent loss of steering capacity, European nation-states showed little interest in taming international financial markets. Footnote 95 This process will be even harder if the divisions between creditor and debtor states persist. In that case the status quo inclinations of the German electorate could cancel out the will of more progressive voters in the European periphery.

Faced with an economic system that threatens to overwhelm the political steering capacities of individual states, European citizens will have to “push for further political integration in order to extend their control over quasi-natural economic forces [to] recover a democratic balance between politics and the market.” To do otherwise merely perpetuates “a fiction of sovereignty … convenient for Germany.” Footnote 96 While Germans may see themselves as Hegelian “knights of virtue” (Ritter der Tugend) trying to hold the other members of the Eurozone to their legal commitments and the moral imperatives against debt, they are actually ignoring the fact that their “current practices are practically self-defeating for the system as a whole.” Footnote 97

Whether the German voters will come around to this perspective is an open question. It is possible that a thicker European society built on an integrated continental public sphere could succeed in turning existing centrifugal forces into centripetal pressures that “promot[e] a European identity across social class groups.” Footnote 98 However, this would require the citizens of the northern member-states, who have managed to ride out the crisis so far, to express greater solidarity for the economic and social suffering recent events have caused individuals in the south.

As Europeans come into ever-greater contact with each other—in large part due to the creation of the Common Market—there is reason for hope. However, this conclusion also points to the fact that focusing on economic rationality will not be enough. At the tail end of the Great Depression in 1937, Horkheimer argued that “the economy is the first cause of wretchedness, and critique, theoretical and practical, must address itself primarily to it.” Footnote 99

As signaled by his use of the word primarily, Horkheimer was aware that economic critique alone was no longer sufficient to expose the inconsistencies within modern industrialized political communities. Other factors besides economics, including culture, society, and education, will also be crucial to the development a solidaristic European public capable of legitimating the EU with its communicatively-generated popular sovereignty. Europeans must resist the temptation to resign themselves to a tragic fate by building on the opportunities presented by the crisis to not only self-consciously appropriate and act on the principles contained within the Eurozone, but also to form the closer cultural, social, and economic bonds necessary for them to retake control of their lives vis-à-vis international markets.100

Footnotes

1 Trichet Reference Trichet2013; Lapavitsas Reference Lapavitsas2009, 114–48.

2 Sinn Reference Sinn2010, 20; Lizoane and Ecke Reference Lizoane and Ecke2013, 2.

5 Aglietta Reference Aglietta2012, 24.

6 Vilpišauskas Reference Vilpišauskas2013, 363; Sissenich, Reference Sissenich2008, 143; Haas Reference Haas2004; Smialek, Reference Smialek2013.

7 It has made the position of scholars who have sought to downplay democratic deficit much less tenable. See Moravcsik Reference Moravcsik2002, 603–24; Majone Reference Majone1998, 5–28; Rosanvallon Reference Rosanvallon2011.

8 Gifford Reference Gifford2014; Baimbridge Burkitt, and Whyman Reference Baimbridge, Burkitt and Whyman2006; Serricchio, Tsakatika and Quaglia Reference Serricchio, Tsakatika and Quaglia2013; Usherwood and Startin Reference Usherwood and Startin2013.

9 Leconte Reference Leconte2010, 5.

10 Krugman Reference Krugman2012, 443; Feldstein Reference Feldstein1997, 60–73.

11 Habermas Reference Habermas2013a, 5; Offe Reference Offe2013, 1.

14 Beck Reference Beck2013, 3.

15 Benhabib Reference Benhabib1986.

16 Sissenich Reference Sissenich2008, 143; Simon Reference Simon2014, 812; Vilpišauskas Reference Vilpišauskas2013, 370.

17 Honneth Reference Honneth and Rush2004, 345–52.

18 Aglietta Reference Aglietta2012, 22.

20 Although there is significant scholarly and political disagreement about the finalité of the EU, my argument proceeds from the assumption that the European project seeks to develop a new postnational form of politics. For other interpretations, see Morgan Reference Morgan2005 and Sangiovanni Reference Sangiovanni2013.

21 Shapiro Reference Shapiro2002, 596–619; Leopold and Stears Reference Leopold and Stears2008, 1; Swift and White Reference Swift, White, Leopold and Stears2008, 49–69; Mayhew Reference Mayhew2000, 192–3.

22 Geuss Reference Geuss2008, 42; Williams Reference Williams2005, 77.

23 Waldron Reference Waldron1999, 154–5.

24 Sissenich Reference Sissenich2008, 153; Galston Reference Galston2010, 393; Philp Reference Philp2007, 239; Bellamy and Castiglione Reference Bellamy and Castiglione2003, 7–34.

25 Ferrara Reference Ferrara2007, 315–331.

26 Morgan Reference Morgan2005; Rawls and Van Parijs Reference Rawls and Van Parijs2003, 7–20; Sissenich Reference Sissenich2007, 353.

27 Manent Reference Manent2006, ch. 4.

28 Manent Reference Manent2010, 179. This argument is related to the “no demos thesis,” which holds that the Europe must develop a sense of peoplehood (a demos) before it can aspire to become a political community. See Manent Reference Manent2001, 113; Moravscik Reference Moravcsik2002, 603–24; Bohman Reference Bohman2006, 191–212; Grimm Reference Grimm1995, 282–302. While theoretically interesting, this argument does not hold up to historical scrutiny, as political integration has usually preceded the creation of stable national identities. See Weber Reference Weber1976; Habermas Reference Habermas and Bellamy2006, 500–05.

29 Streeck Reference Streeck2014.

30 Habermas Reference Habermas2013c, 59–70; Streeck Reference Streeck2013, 75–92; Ronzoni Reference Ronzoni2015.

31 Bellamy and Castiglione Reference Bellamy and Castiglione2003, 7–34.

32 Kauppinen Reference Kauppinen2002, 483.

34 Koskenneimi Reference Koskenneimi2011, 63.

35 Mazower Reference Mazower2012, 421.

37 Weber Reference Weber1958, 78, emphasis original; Deng Reference Deng1996, xviii.

38 Nettl Reference Nettl1968, 561; Weiler Reference Weiler1999, 98.

40 Walzer Reference Walzer1987; Stahl Reference Stahl2013, 534.

41 Adorno Reference Adorno1969, 174, author’s translation; Löwenthal Reference Löwenthal1980, 77–79; Habermas Reference Habermas1992, 34; Marcuse Reference Marcuse1968.

42 Strydom Reference Strydom2013, 87.

43 Linklater Reference Linklater1998, 6.

45 Benhabib Reference Benhabib1986, 113, 109.

46 Márkus Reference Márkus1979, 268; Horkheimer Reference Horkheimer1941, 122, emphasis original.

47 Adorno quoted in Strydom Reference Strydom2013, 154.

48 Habermas 1984/1987, II: 403, emphasis added. See Cooke Reference Cooke2006, 39.

49 Benhabib Reference Benhabib1986, 155, emphasis original; Habermas Reference Habermas1984, 39–40; Frankel and Habermas Reference Frankel and Habermas1974, 44; Allen Reference Allen2012, 353.

50 Márkus Reference Márkus1982, 291–318.

51 Márkus Reference Márkus1980b, 12, 14; Márkus Reference Márkus1980a, 81.

52 Benhabib Reference Benhabib1986, 106–7, 226; Benhabib Reference Benhabib1982, 289–97.

54 Honneth Reference Honneth1995, 115.

55 Soros Reference Soros2012, 113.

56 Graeber Reference Graeber2012, 14.

58 Streeck Reference Streeck2012b, 65.

59 Lienau Reference Lienau2014, 232.

60 Giddens Reference Giddens2013, 25; Tooze Reference Tooze2014, 5.

61 U.S. Department of the Treasury 2013, 25. Also Wren-Lewis Reference Wren-Lewis2014.

62 Quoted in Baimbridge Burkitt, and Whyman Reference Baimbridge, Burkitt and Whyman2006, 66.

64 Strydom Reference Strydom2013, 102. For a complete timeline of the crisis see Sinn Reference Sinn2010, appendix, “Chronology of the Financial Crisis.”

65 Spiegel 2013.

66 Marsh Reference Marsh2013, 8.

67 Sinn Reference Sinn2010, 271.

68 Giddens Reference Giddens2013, 22.

69 Stiglitz Reference Stiglitz2013.

70 Meiers Reference Meiers2015, 118.

71 Blyth Reference Blyth2013, 75–6.

72 van Middelaar Reference van Middelaar2013, 185.

73 Quoted in Marsh Reference Marsh2011, 141.

74 Streeck Reference Streeck2012b, 67.

75 Benhabib Reference Benhabib1986, 7.

76 Habermas Reference Habermas2010, author’s translation; Habermas Reference Habermas and Cronin2012, 124; and Verovšek Reference Verovšek2014.

77 Streeck Reference Streeck2012b, 66.

78 Jay Reference Jay1973, 54.

79 Held Reference Held1980, 395; Arendt Reference Arendt1969, 15.

80 Beck Reference Beck2013, 3, 1.

81 Chevènement Reference Chevènement2006; Milward, Reference Milward1992, 336; Featherstone Reference Featherstone1994, 149–70.

82 See Pensky Reference Pensky2008; Bellamy and Kröger Reference Bellamy and Kröger2014, 437–457.

83 See Moravcsik Reference Moravcsik2002; Rosanvallon Reference Rosanvallon2011.

84 Habermas Reference Habermas and Cronin2012, 7; Habermas Reference Habermas2010, author’s translation.

85 Habermas Reference Habermas2014b, 184–5.

86 Habermas Reference Habermas and Cronin2009, 53; Trenz and Eder Reference Trenz and Eder2004, 5–25.

87 Risse Reference Risse2010, 5; Delanty and Rumford Reference Delanty and Rumford2005, 79.

88 Streeck Reference Streeck2013, 91; Biebricher and Vogelmann Reference Biebricher and Vogelmann2014, 8.

89 Fabbrini Reference Fabbrini2015.

90 Levy, Pensky and Torpey Reference Levy, Pensky and Torpey2005.

92 See Biebricher and Vogelmann Reference Biebricher and Vogelmann2014.

93 Habermas Reference Habermas and Cronin2012, 10, emphasis original.

94 Habermas Reference Habermas2001, 99–100.

95 Biebricher and Vogelmann Reference Biebricher and Vogelmann2014, 6.

97 Bernstein Reference Bernstein2010.

98 Fligstein Reference Fligstein2008, 18.

99 Horkheimer quoted in Benhabib Reference Benhabib1986, 155, emphasis added.

References

Adorno, Theodor W. 1969. Stichworte: Kritische Modelle 2. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp.Google Scholar
Adorno, Theodor W., et al. . 1976. The Positivist Dispute in German Sociology. Trans. Adey, Glyn and Frisby, David. New York: Harper Torchbooks.Google Scholar
Aglietta, Michel. 2012. “The European Vortex.” New Left Review 75: 1536.Google Scholar
Allen, Amy R. 2012. “The Unforced Force of the Better Argument: Reason and Power in Habermas’ Political Theory.” Constellations 19(3): 353–68.Google Scholar
Arendt, Hannah. 1969. “Reflections on Violence.” Journal of International Affairs 23(1): 135.Google Scholar
Baimbridge, Mark, Burkitt, Brian, and Whyman, Philip, eds. 2006. Implications of the Euro: A Critical Perspective from the Left. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Beck, Ulrich. 2012. Das deutsche Europa: Neue machtlandschaften im Zeichen der Krise. Berlin: Suhrkamp.Google Scholar
Beck, Ulrich. 2013. German Europe. New York: Polity.Google Scholar
Bellamy, Richard and Kröger, Sandra. 2014. “Domesticating the Democratic Deficit? The Role of National Parliaments and Parties in the EU’s System of Governance.” Parliamentary Affairs 67(2): 437–57.Google Scholar
Bellamy, Richard and Castiglione, Dario. 2003. “Legitimizing the Euro-‘polity’ and its ‘Regime’: The Normative Turn in EU Studies.” European Journal of Political Theory 2(1): 734.Google Scholar
Benhabib, Seyla. 1982. “The Development of Marx’s Thought and the Hermeneutics of Critique: Comments on George Markus’ ‘Four Forms of Critical Theory: Some Theses on Marx’s Development.’” Thesis Eleven 5/6(1): 289–97.Google Scholar
Benhabib, Seyla. 1986. Critique, Norm, and Utopia: A Study of the Foundations of Critical Theory. New York: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Bernstein, J. M. 2010. “Hegel on Wall Street.” New York Times, October 3.Google Scholar
Biebricher, Thomas and Vogelmann, Frieder. 2014. “Die Zukunft Europas zwischen Demokratie und Kapitalismus.” Politische Vierteljahresschrift 55(1): 117.Google Scholar
Blyth, Mark. 2013. Austerity: The History of a Dangerous Idea. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Bohman, Jonathan. 2006. “The European Union Democratic Deficit: Federalists, Skeptics, and Revisionists.” European Journal of Political Theory 5(2): 191212.Google Scholar
Celikates, Robin. 2009. “Recognition, System Justification and Reconstructive Critique.” In Reconnaissance. Identité et intégration sociale., ed. Lazzeri, Christian and Nour, Soraya. Paris: Presses Universitaires de Paris Ouest.Google Scholar
Chevènement, Jean-Pierre. 2006. La faute de M. Monnet: La république et l’Europe. L’idée républicaine. Paris: Fayard.Google Scholar
Cooke, Maeve. 2006. Re-Presenting the Good Society. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Crouch, Colin. 2004. Post-Democracy. Cambridge: Polity.Google Scholar
Crouch, Colin. 2013. Making Capitalism Fit for Society. Cambridge: Polity Press.Google Scholar
Delanty, Gerard and Rumford, Chris. 2005. Rethinking Europe: Social Theory and the Implications of Europeanization. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Deng, Francis M. 1996. Sovereignty as Responsibility: Conflict Management in Africa. Washington: Brookings Institution.Google Scholar
Fabbrini, Sergio. 2015. Which European Union? Europe after the Euro Crisis. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Featherstone, Kevin. 1994. “Jean Monnet and the ‘Democratic Deficit’ in the European Union.” Journal of Common Market Studies 32(2): 149–70.Google Scholar
Feldstein, Martin. 1997. “EMU and International Conflict.” Foreign Affairs 76(6): 6073.Google Scholar
Ferrara, Alessandro. 2007. “Europe as a ‘Special Area for Human Hope.’” Constellations 14(3): 315–31.Google Scholar
Fligstein, Neil. 2008. Euro-Clash: The EU, European Identity, and the Future of Europe. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Frankel, Boris and Habermas, Jürgen. 1974. “Habermas Talking: An Inteview.” Theory and Society 1(1): 3758.Google Scholar
Galston, William A. 2010. “Realism in Political Theory.” European Journal of Political Theory 9(4): 385411.Google Scholar
Geuss, Raymond. 1981. The Idea of a Critical Theory: Habermas and the Frankfurt School. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Geuss, Raymond. 2008. Philosophy and Real Politics. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Giddens, Anthony. 2013. Turbulent and Mighty Continent: What Future for Europe?. Cambridge: Polity.Google Scholar
Gifford, Chris. 2014. The Making of Eurosceptic Britain. Burlington: Ashgate.Google Scholar
Goldstein, Judith, Kahler, Miles, Keohane, Robert O., and Slaughter, Anne-Marie. 2001. Legalization and World Politics. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Graeber, David. 2012. Debt: The First 5,000 Years. Brooklyn: Melville House.Google Scholar
de Grauwe, Paul. 2011. “The Governance of a Fragile Eurozone.” CEPS Working Document, May 4. Brussels: Centre for European Policy Studies.Google Scholar
Grimm, Dieter. 1995. “Does Europe Need a Constitution?” European Law Journal 1(3): 282302.Google Scholar
Guéhenno, Jean-Marie. 1995. The End of the Nation-State. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Haas, Ernst B. 2004. The Uniting of Europe: Political, Social, and Economic Forces, 1950–1957. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.Google Scholar
Habermas, Jürgen. 1984 “What Does Crisis Mean Today? Legitimation Problems in Late Capitalism.” Social Research 51(1/2): 3964.Google Scholar
Habermas, Jürgen. 1984/1987. The Theory of Communicative Action. Trans. McCarthy, Thomas A.. Boston: Beacon Press.Google Scholar
Habermas, Jürgen. 1992. Postmetaphysical Thinking: Philosophical Essays. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Habermas, Jürgen. 2001. “The Postnational Constellation and the Future of Democracy.” In The Postnational Constellation: Political Essays. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Habermas, Jürgen. 2006. “Remarks on Dieter Grimm’s ‘Does Europe Need a Constitution?’” In Constitutionalism and Democracy, ed. Bellamy, Richard. Aldershot: Ashgate.Google Scholar
Habermas, Jürgen. 2008. “The Constitutionalization of International Law and the Legitimation Problems of a Constitution for World Society.” Constellations 15(4): 444–55.Google Scholar
Habermas, Jürgen. 2009. Europe: The Faltering Project. Trans. Cronin, Ciaran. Cambridge: Polity Press.Google Scholar
Habermas, Jürgen. 2010. “Wir brauchen Europa!” Die Zeit, 20 Mai.Google Scholar
Habermas, Jürgen. 2012. The Crisis of the European Union: A Response. Trans. Cronin, Ciaran. Cambridge: Polity Press.Google Scholar
Habermas, Jürgen. 2013a. “Democracy, Solidarity and the European Crisis.” Social Europe Journal.Google Scholar
Habermas, Jürgen. 2013b. “Germany Dozes on a Volcano.” Spiegel, September 8.Google Scholar
Habermas, Jürgen. 2013c. “Demokratie Oder Kapitalismus? Vom Elend Der Nationalstaatliehen Fragmentierung in Einer Kapitalistisch Integrierten Weltgesellschaft.” Blätter Für Deutsche Und Internationale Politik 58(5): 5970.Google Scholar
Habermas, Jürgen. 2014a. “Plea for a Constitutionalization of International Law.” Philosophy & Social Criticism 40(1): 512.Google Scholar
Habermas, Jürgen. 2014b. Zur Prinzipienkonkurrenz von Bürgergleichheit und Staatengleichheit im supranationalen Gemeinwesen. Eine Notiz aus Anlass der Frage nach der Legitimität der ungleichen Repräsentation der Bürger im europäischen Parlament. Der Staat 53(2): 167–92.Google Scholar
Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich. 1965. Hegel’s Philosophy of Right. Trans. Knox, T. M.. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich. 1969. Hegel’s Science of Logic. Trans. Miller, A. V.. London: G. Allen & Unwin.Google Scholar
Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich. 1977. Phenomenology of Spirit. Trans. Miller, Arnold V., ed. Findlay, J. N.. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Held, David. 1980. Introduction to Critical Theory: Horkheimer to Habermas. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Honneth, Axel. 1995. The Struggle for Recognition: The Moral Grammar of Social Conflicts. Cambridge: Polity Press.Google Scholar
Honneth, Axel. 2004. “A Social Pathology of Reason.” In The Cambridge Companion to Critical Theory, ed. Rush, Fred L.. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Horkheimer, Max. 1941. “Notes on Institute Activities.” Studies in Philosophy and Social Science 9(1): 121–3.Google Scholar
Horkheimer, Max and Adorno, Theodor W.. 2002. Dialectic of Enlightenment: Philosophical Fragments. Trans. Noerr, Gunzelin Schmid. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.Google Scholar
Horsman, Mathew and Marshall, Andrew. 1994. After the Nation-State: Citizens, Tribalism, and the New World Disorder. London: HarperCollins.Google Scholar
Jay, Martin. 1973. The Dialectical Imagination: History of the Frankfurt School and the Institute of Social Research, 1923–1950. Boston: Little, Brown and Company.Google Scholar
Kauppinen, Antti. 2002. “Reason, Recognition, and Internal Critique.” Inquiry 45(4): 479–98.Google Scholar
Klabbers, Jan, Peters, Anne, and Ulfstein, Geir. 2009. The Constitutionalization of International Law. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Koskenneimi, Matti. 2011. “What Use for Sovereignty Today?” Asian Journal of International Law 1(1): 6170.Google Scholar
Krugman, Paul. 2012. “Revenge of the Optimum Currency Area.” NBER Macroeconomics Annual 27: 439–48.Google Scholar
Lapavitsas, Costas. 2009. “Financialised Capitalism: Crisis and Financial Expropriation.” Historical Materialism 17(2): 114–48.Google Scholar
Leconte, Cécile. 2010. Understanding Euroscepticism. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Leopold, David and Stears, Marc, eds. 2008. Political Theory: Methods and Approaches. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Levy, Daniel, Pensky, Max, and Torpey, John C.. 2005. Old Europe, New Europe, Core Europe: Transatlantic Relations after the Iraq War. London: Verso.Google Scholar
Lienau, Odette. 2014. Rethinking Sovereign Debt: Politics, Reputation, and Legitimacy in Modern Finance. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Linklater, Andrew. 1998. The Transformation of Political Community: Ethical Foundations of the Post-Westphalian Era. Columbia: University of South Carolina Press.Google Scholar
Lizoane, David and Ecke, Matthias. 2013. “European Youth Need a Change from a New German Government.” Social Europe Journal, November 14.Google Scholar
Löwenthal, Leo. 1980. Mitmachen wollte ich nie: Ein autobiographisches Gesprach mit Helmut Dubiel. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp.Google Scholar
Majone, Giandomenico. 1998. “Europe’s ‘Democratic Deficit’: The Question of Standards.” European Journal of Law 4(1): 528.Google Scholar
Manent, Pierre. 2001. Cours familier de philosophie politique. Paris: Fayard.Google Scholar
Manent, Pierre. 2006. A World Beyond Politics? A Defense of the Nation-State. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Manent, Pierre. 2010. “The Greatness and Misery of Liberalism.” Modern Age 52(3): 176–83.Google Scholar
Marcuse, Herbert. 1968. One Dimensional Man: Studies in the Ideology of Advanced Industrial Society. Boston: Beacon Press.Google Scholar
Márkus, György. 1979. “Practical-Social Rationality in Marx: A Dialectical Critique.” Dialectical Anthropology 4(4): 255–88.Google Scholar
Márkus, György. 1980a. “Four Forms of Critical Theory: Some Theses on Marx’s Development.” Thesis Eleven 1(1): 7893.Google Scholar
Márkus, György. 1980b. “Practical-Social Rationality in Marx: A Dialectical Critique, Part 2.” Dialectical Anthropology 5(1): 131.Google Scholar
Márkus, György. 1982. “Western Marxism and Eastern Societies.” Dialectical Anthropology 6(4): 291318.Google Scholar
Marsh, David. 2011. The Euro: The Battle for the New Global Currency. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Marsh, David. 2013. Europe’s Deadlock: How the Euro Crisis Could be Solved, and Why It Won’t Happen. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Mayhew, David R. 2000. “Political Science and Political Philosophy: Ontological Not Normative.” PS: Political Science and Politics 22(2): 192–3.Google Scholar
Mazower, Mark. 2012. Governing the World: The History of an Idea. New York: Penguin Press.Google Scholar
Meiers, Franz-Josef. 2015. Germany’s Role in the Euro Crisis: Berlin’s Quest for a More Perfect Monetary Union. New York: Springer.Google Scholar
Milward, Alan S. 1992. The European Rescue of the Nation-State. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Moravcsik, Andrew. 2002. “In Defense of the ‘Democratic Deficit’: Reassessing Legitimacy in the European Union.” Journal of Common Market Studies 40(4): 603–24.Google Scholar
Morgan, Glyn. 2005. The Idea of a European Superstate: Public Justification and European Integration. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Nettl, J. P. 1968. “The State as a Conceptual Variable.” World Politics 20(4): 559–92.Google Scholar
Offe, Claus. 1976. “‘Crisis of Crisis Management’: Elements of a Political Crisis Theory.” International Journal of Politics 6(3): 2967.Google Scholar
Offe, Claus. 1984. Contradictions of the Welfare State. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Offe, Claus. 2013. “Europa in der Falle.” Blätter für deutsche und internationale Politik 58(1): 6780.Google Scholar
Ohmae, Kenichi. 1995. The End of the Nation State: The Rise of Regional Economies. New York: Free Press.Google Scholar
Pensky, Max. 2008. The Ends of Solidarity: Discourse Theory in Ethics and Politics. Albany: State University of New York Press.Google Scholar
Philp, Mark. 2007. Political Conduct. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Piris, Jean-Claude. 2012. The Future of Europe: Towards a Two-Speed EU? Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Postone, Moishe. 2004. “Critique, State, and Economy.” In The Cambridge Companion to Critical Theory. ed. Rush, Fred Leland. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Rawls, John and Van Parijs, Philipp. 2003. “Three Letters on the Law of Peoples and the European Union.” Revue de philosophie économique 7: 720.Google Scholar
Risse, Thomas. 2010. A Community of Europeans? Transnational Identities and Public Spheres. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Ronzoni, Miriam. 2015. “How Social Democrats May Become Reluctant Radicals: Thomas Piketty’s Capital and Wolfgang Streeck’s Buying Time.” European Journal of Political Theory, September 10.Google Scholar
Rosanvallon, Pierre. 2011. Democratic Legitimacy: Impartiality, Reflexivity, Proximity. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Rush, Fred Leland. 2004. “Conceptual Foundations of Early Critical Theory.” In The Cambridge Companion to Critical Theory., ed. Rush, Fred Leland. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Sangiovanni, Andrea. 2013. “Solidarity in the European Union.” Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 33(2): 213–42.Google Scholar
Serricchio, Fabio, Tsakatika, Myrto, and Quaglia, Lucia. 2013. “Euroscepticism and the Global Financial Crisis.” JCMS: Journal of Common Market Studies 51(1): 5164.Google Scholar
Shapiro, Ian. 2002. “Problems, Methods, and Theories in the Study of Politics, or What’s Wrong with Political Science and What to Do About It.” Political Theory 30(4): 596619.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Simon, Joshua. 2014. “The Americas’ More Perfect Unions: New Institutional Insights from Comparative Political Theory.” Perspectives on Politics 12(4): 808–28.Google Scholar
Sinn, Hans-Werner. 2010. Casino Capitalism: How the Financial Crisis Came about and What Needs to be Done Now. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Sissenich, Beate. 2007. “Justification and Identity in European Integration: Comments on Morgan and Ferrara.” Constellations 14(3): 347–54.Google Scholar
Sissenich, Beate. 2008. “Postnational Rulemaking, Compliance, and Justification: The New Europe.” Perspectives on Politics 6(1): 143–57.Google Scholar
Smialek, Jeanna. 2013. “IMF Chief Lagarde Calls Merkel ‘Unchallenged Leader’ in Germany.” Bloomberg, April 10.Google Scholar
Soros, George. 2012. Financial Turmoil in Europe and the United States. New York: Public Affairs.Google Scholar
Spence, Michael. 2011. “Five Steps to Fix the World.” Newsweek, January 31.Google Scholar
Spiegel, Der . 2013. “Bitter Euro Truths: Crisis Could Damage Merkel’s Campaign.” August 27.Google Scholar
Stahl, Titus. 2013. “Habermas and the Project of Immanent Critique.” Constellations 20(4): 533–52.Google Scholar
Stiglitz, Joseph. 2013. “An Agenda to Save the Euro.” Social Europe Journal, December 5.Google Scholar
Streeck, Wolfgang. 2011. “The Crises of Democratic Capitalism.” New Left Review 71: 529.Google Scholar
Streeck, Wolfgang. 2012a. “Interview with Wolfgang Streeck.” The Current Moment, January 3.Google Scholar
Streeck, Wolfgang. 2012b. “Markets and Peoples: Democratic Capitalism and European Integration.” New Left Review 73: 6371.Google Scholar
Streeck, Wolfgang. 2013. “Vom DM-Nationalismus zum Euro-Patriotismus? Eine Replik auf Jürgen Habermas.” Blätter für deutsche und internationale Politik 58(9): 7592.Google Scholar
Streeck, Wolfgang. 2014. “Small-State Nostalgia? The Currency Union, Germany, and Europe: A Reply to Jürgen Habermas.” Constellations 21(2): 213–21.Google Scholar
Strydom, Piet. 2013. Contemporary Critical Theory and Methodology. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Swift, Adam and White, Stuart. 2008. “Political Theory, Social Science, and Real Politics.” In Political Theory: Methods and Approaches, eds. Leopold, David, Stears, Marc. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Tooze, Adam. 2014. The Deluge: The Great War and the Remaking of Global Order, 1916–1931. London: Allen Lane.Google Scholar
Trenz, Hans-Jörg and Eder, Klaus. 2004. “The Democratizing Dynamics of a European Public Sphere: Towards a Theory of Democratic Functionalism.” European Journal of Social Theory 7(1): 525.Google Scholar
Trichet, Jean-Claude. 2013. “The State of the Euro.” Presented at the Center for European Studies, Harvard University, Cambridge, MA, October 16.Google Scholar
U.S. Department of the Treasury, Office of International Affairs. 2013. “Report to Congress on International Economic and Exchange Rate Policies.” October 30.Google Scholar
Usherwood, Simon and Startin, Nick. 2013. “Euroscepticism as a Persistent Phenomenon.” JCMS: Journal of Common Market Studies 51(1): 116.Google Scholar
van Middelaar, Luuk. 2013. The Passage to Europe. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Verovšek, Peter J. 2014. “Memory and the Euro-Crisis of Leadership: The Effects of Generational Change in Germany and the EU.” Constellations 21(2): 239–48.Google Scholar
Vilpišauskas, Ramūnas. 2013. “Eurozone Crisis and European Integration: Functional Spillover, Political Spillback?” Journal of European Integration 35(3): 361–73.Google Scholar
Waldron, Jeremy. 1999. The Dignity of Legislation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Walzer, Michael. 1987. Interpretation and Social Criticism. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Weber, Eugen. 1976. Peasants into Frenchmen: The Modernization of Rural France, 1870–1914. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.Google Scholar
Weber, Max. 1958. From Max Weber: Essays in Sociology. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Weiler, J. H. H. 1999. The Constitution of Europe: “Do the New Clothes Have an Emperor?” and Other Essays on European Integration. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Williams, Bernard. 2005. In the Beginning Was the Deed: Realism and Moralism in Political Argument. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Wren-Lewis, Simon. 2014. “Why the Eurozone Suffers from a Germany Problem.” Social Europe Journal, October 27.Google Scholar