Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-rdxmf Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-22T15:39:21.592Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Grammaticality, response-dependence and the ontology of linguistic objects

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  22 December 2008

Jussi Haukioja
Affiliation:
Department of Philosophy, University of Turku, 20014, Finland. E-mail: [email protected]
Get access

Abstract

The problem of explaining the knowledge possessed by a native speaker of a natural language and the philosophical problem of rule-following are juxtaposed, and the former is seen to be an instance of the latter. A recent solution to the rule-following problem is reviewed, with special attention to the consequences that the solution has for the nature of those concepts acquired from exemplars. The concept of a grammatical sentence is one of these. Finally, it is shown that, as a consequence, we can see the grammaticality of a sentence to be an abstract property, which is simultaneously objective and tied to the responses of competent speakers. Thus, we gain a better understanding of some central questions in the philosophy of linguistics.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2000

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

REFERENCES

Blackburn, S. 1993. Circles, Finks, Smells and Biconditionals. Philosophical Perspectives 7: Language and Logic, 259279.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Boghossian, P. A. 1989. The Rule-Following Considerations. Mind 98, 507549.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chomsky, N. 1976. Problems and Mysteries in the Study of Human Language. In Kasher, A. (ed.), Language in Focus: Foundations, Methods and Systems. Dordrecht: Reidel, 281357.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chomsky, N. 1980. Rules and Representations. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chomsky, N. 1986. Knowledge of Language. New York: Praeger.Google Scholar
Chomsky, N. 1987. Reply. Mind and Language 2, 178197.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
George, A. 1987. Review of Chomsky (1986). Mind and Language 2, 155164.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
George, A. 1989. How Not to Become Confused about Linguistics. In George, A. (ed.), Reflections on Chomsky. Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 90110.Google Scholar
Higginbotham, J. 1991. Remarks on the Metaphysics of Linguistics. Linguistics and Philosophy 14, 555566.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Itkonen, E. 1978. Grammatical Theory and Metascience. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.Google Scholar
Itkonen, E. 1983a. Causality in Linguistic Theory. London: Croom Helm.Google Scholar
Itkonen, E. 1983b. Review of Katz (1981). Lingua 60, 238244.Google Scholar
Itkonen, E. 1996. Concerning the Generative Paradigm. Journal of Pragmatics 25, 471501.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Itkonen, E. 1997. The Social Ontology of Linguistic Meaning. SKY: The Yearbook of the Linguistic Association of Finland 1997, 4980.Google Scholar
Itkonen, E., & Haukioja, J. 1997. A Rehabilitation of Analogy in Syntax (and Elsewhere). In Kertész, A. (ed.), Metalinguistik im Wandel: Die ‘kognitive Wende’ in Wissenschaftstheorie und Linguistik. Frankfurt: Peter Lang, 131177.Google Scholar
Johnston, M. 1989. Dispositional Theories of Value. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 63, 139174.Google Scholar
Johnston, M. 1993. Objectivity Refigured: Pragmatism without Verificationism. In Haldane, J. & Wright, C. (eds), Reality, Representation, and Projection. New York: Oxford University Press, 85130.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Katz, J. 1981. Language and Other Abstract Objects. Totowa: Rowman & Littlefield.Google Scholar
Katz, J. J., & Postal, P. M. 1991. Realism vs. Conceptualism in Linguistics. Linguistics and Philosophy 14, 515554.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kripke, S. 1982. Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Language. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
Langacker, R. W. 1987. Foundations of Cognitive Grammar I: Theoretical Prerequisites. Stanford: Stanford University Press.Google Scholar
Luntley, M. 1989. On the Way the World Is Independently of the Way We Take It to Be. Inquiry 32, 177194.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Peacocke, C. 1992. A Study of Concepts. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Pettit, P. 1990. The Reality of Rule-Following. Mind 99, 121.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pettit, P. 1991. Realism and Response-Dependence. Mind 100, 587626.Google Scholar
Pettit, P. 1993. The Common Mind: An Essay on Psychology, Society, and Politics. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Pettit, P. 1999. A Theory of Normal and Ideal Conditions. Philosophical Studies 96, 2144.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pullum, G. 1996. Theoretical Linguistics and the Ontology of Linguistic Structure. Paper presented at the symposium “Tacit Assumptions in Linguistics”, organized by the Linguistic Association of Finland in Helsinki, 09 2–4, 1996.Google Scholar
Pullum, G. K., & Scholz, B. C. 1997. Theoretical Linguistics and the Ontology of Linguistic Structure. SKY: The Yearbook of the Linguistic Association of Finland 1997, 2547.Google Scholar
Putnam, H. 1975. The Meaning of ‘Meaning’. In Philosophical Papers 2: Mind, Language and Reality. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 215271.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Soames, S. 1991. The Necessity Argument. Linguistics and Philosophy 14, 575580.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wittgenstein, L. 1968. Philosophical Investigations (3rd edition). Oxford: Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
Wright, C. 1989. Wittgenstein's Rule-Following Considerations and the Central Project of Theoretical Linguistics. In George, A. (ed.), Reflections on Chomsky. Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 233264.Google Scholar
Wright, C. 1992. Truth and Objectivity. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar