No CrossRef data available.
Published online by Cambridge University Press: 01 January 2024
It would appear that there are few things in human life that have the power to override all other concerns. There are few things, that is, that seem to command our unconditional attention. Amongst such things we might include ‘matters of life and death’. Perhaps the most admirable aspects of the human spirit are often found in the setting of life and death situations. Self-sacrifice, life-threatening risks on behalf of others’ lives, self-denying and courage etc. What is it that motivates people to behave in these ways? A common response comes to mind in their defence: ‘it was a matter of life and death’. We all understand the priority of that appeal. At the scene of an accident, an observer runs to an occupied telephone kiosk - ‘please let me use the phone, it’s a matter of life and death...’ A businessman arrives an hour late for a meeting, ‘Excuse me for being late, I was caught up in an accident, I had to stop - it was a matter of life and death...’ Despite the potential rudeness of interrupting another’s telephone call, or the tardiness of the businessman’s entry, we are willing to excuse such behaviour on the grounds that ‘it was a matter of life and death’. Like a verbal skeleton key, it is a plea that demands (and usually obtains) the unconditional unlocking of doors or removal of obstacles.
The purpose of this brief preamble concerning the effect life and death situations’ seem to have upon our attitudes and actions, or more particularly, our perceptions of appropriate attitudes and action, is to focus our attention upon an assumption that will be forming part of this paper - that religion itself is a ‘matter of life and death’.
My thanks go to Gavin D'Costa for his comments on an earlier draft of this paper.
2 Hay, D., Religious Experience Today, (London: Mowbray, 1990), pp. 98,99Google Scholar.
3 Schleiermacher, F., The Christian Faith, Mackintosh, H.R. and Stewart, J.S., (eds), (Edinburgh, 1948), p.12Google Scholar.
4 L. Wittgenstein, extract from Culture and Value, Wright, G.H. von, (ed), Winch, P., trans., (Chicago: Chicago University Press, 1980)Google Scholar, reprinted in Oakes, E. T., (ed), German Essays on Religion, (New York: Continuum, 1994), p.226Google Scholar.
5 Hughes, E.J., 'How Subjectivity is Truth in The Concluding Unscientific Postscript', Religious Studies, Vol. 31, No. 2, June, 1995, p. 203CrossRefGoogle Scholar.
6 Johnson, R.H, The Concept of Existence in the Concluding Unscientific Postscript, (The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1972), p. 188CrossRefGoogle Scholar; cited in E.J Hughes, op. cit., p.206.
7 S. Kierkegaard, Journals, 22 (LA/75)
8 Christian, W.A. Sr., Meaning and Truth in Religion, (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1964, p.60f)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.
9 For an excellent discussion of the varieties within the pluralist stance see Byrne, P., Prolog Omena to Religious Pluralism: Reference and Realism in Religion, (London: Macmillan, 1995.)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
10 Smith, W. C., ‘The Christian in a Religiously Plural World’, Religious Diversity: Essays by Wilfred Cantwell Smith, Oxtoby, W. G., (ed), (New York: Harper and Row, 1976); reprinted in Hebblethwaite, B. & Hick, J., (eds), Christianity and Other Religions, (Fount, 1980), p.96Google Scholar.
11 P.F. Knitter, ‘Toward a Liberation Theology of Religions’ in P.F. Knitter & J. Hick, (eds), The Myth of Christian Uniqueness, (London: SCM Press, 1988), p.181.
12 For example, it seems that the priority of the ‘ethical/praxis’ imperative is revealed when Knitter claims that ‘the right practice of following Jesus and working for his kingdom is more important for Christian identity than is the right knowledge concerning the nature of God or of Jesus himself.’Ibid, p.195. Knitter is surely right to identify ‘right practice’ as an important concern, but I have argued that religion as ‘a matter of life and death’ is also about the unconditional, the ultimate concern, and (perhaps we might add) the truth about oneself. If this is so then obtaining ‘right knowledge’ about the nature of God, or ‘ultimate reality’, must come high on a religious priority list.
13 Tillich, P., [1949] The Shaking of the Foundations, (Penguin, 1963), p.95Google Scholar.
14 See for example R.B. Braithwaite's Eddington Memorial Lecture, An Empiricist's View of the Nature of Religious Belief, (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1955)Google Scholar; reprinted in Hick, J., (ed), The Existence of God, (London & New York: Collier Macmillan, 1964)Google Scholar.
15 Williams, B., Morality, (Penguin, 1972), p.48Google Scholar.
16 E. Cousins, in F. Whaling, (ed), Religion in Today's World, p.330.
17 Nicholls, W., in Nicholls, W. (ed). Religion and Modernity (Waterloo/Ontario, 1987) p.177Google Scholar.
18 E. Cousins, op. cit., p.334.
19 That is, it is when incompatible truth‐claims are held with passion ‐ or as ‘matters of life and death’ ‐ that disagreements become real rather than purely notional.
20 This somewhat endorses a similar point made recently by Gavin D'Costa who claims that the logical structure of pluralism is in fact exclusivistic. He argues that ‘all pluralists are committed to holding some form of truth criteria and by virtue of this, anything that falls foul of such criteria is excluded from counting as truth (in doctrine and in practice). Thus, pluralism operates within the same logical structure of exclusivism and in this respect pluralism can never really affirm the genuine autonomous value of religious pluralism for, like exclusivist it can only do so by tradition specific criteria of truth.’“The Impossibility of a Pluralist View of Religions”, Religious Studies, Vol.32, No.2, June 1996, pp.225Google Scholar, 226. (Hick has responded to D'Costa with ‘The Possibility of Religious Pluralism: A Reply to Gavin D'Costa’, Religious Studies, Vol. 33, No.2, June, 1997.Google Scholar)
21 Braybrooke, M., ‘Religious Studies and Interfaith Developments’, in King, U., (ed), Turning Points in Religious Studies, (Edinburgh: T & T Clark, 1990), p.140Google Scholar.
22 Hick, J., An Interpretation of Religion, (London: Macmillan, 1989) pp.235‐236CrossRefGoogle Scholar.
23 Ibid, p.246.
24 See S. Heim, Mark, 'The Pluralistic Hypothesis, Realism and Post‐Eschatology, Religious Studies, Vol.28, No.2, June,1992.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
25 See D'Costa, Gavin, ‘John Hick and Religious Pluralism: Yet Another Revolution’ in Hewitt, H., (ed.), Problems in the Philosophy of Religion: Critical Studies of the Work of John Hick, (London: Macmillan, 1991).Google Scholar
26 See Hick, J., The Rainbow of Faiths, (London: SCM Press, 1995)Google Scholar esp. ch.3
27 See in particular the closing remarks of Hick in ‘A Personal Note’. Disputed Questions in Theology and the Philosophy of Religion, (London: Macmillan, 1993)Google Scholar, esp. pp.144‐145.
28 Hick, J., The Second Christianity, (London: SCM Press, 1983), p.89Google Scholar.
29 Hick, J., ‘The Possibility of Religious Pluralism: A Reply to Gavin D'Costa’, Religious Studies, Vol.33, No.2, June, 1997, p.163CrossRefGoogle Scholar.
30 Ibid.
31 For example, Braybrooke expresses the need for the pluralistic vision to have a significant influence: ‘The hardest task of the interfaith movement is not to establish co‐operation between some members of each religion, but to effect inner change within each religion’. M. Braybrooke, op.cit, p 140
32 Hick, J., ‘Rational Theistic Beliefs Without Proofs’ in Badham, P., (ed) A John Hick Reader, (London: Macmillan, 1990), p.54Google Scholar. [First appeared in Hick, J., Arguments for the Existence of God, (London: Macmillan, 1971)Google Scholar]
33 Hick, J., [1963] Philosophy of Religion, (Prentice Hall International 1990, 4th Ed.), p. 96Google Scholar.
34 Hick argues for the cognitivity of religious language. For example, see “Theology and Verification”, Theology Today, Vol.27, No.l, April, 1960; reprinted in Hick, The Existence of God.
35 J. Hick, The Second Christianity, p.90. Those familiar with Hick, J., (ed), The Myth of God Incarnate, (London: SCM Press, 1977)Google Scholar will appreciate how the pluralist view effects ‘change’ with regard to a central feature of the Christian faith.
36 J. Hick, The Rainbow of Faiths, p.30 37. Ibid, p.136. 38. Nicholson, R.A., [1950] Rumi: Poet and Mystic, (London: Allen & Unwin, 1978), p.166Google Scholar. Cited in Hick, Interpretation of Religion, p.233.