Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-gbm5v Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-23T18:28:37.712Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

On Being a Thomist: Cornelius Ernst's Meta-Theology

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2024

Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Thomism is a contested category that exhibits considerable plasticity in its application. An examination of the role played by such invocations of proper names in contemporary theological discourse indicates the importance of textual accessibility and engagement. The role played by texts is examined in terms of an often-elided distinction between ‘intelligibility’ and ‘readability’, with the former aligned with propositional contents and the latter a more expansive attentiveness to the text's performative operations. The historical remoteness of Aquinas coupled with the importation into theology of secularised reading strategies is seen to have alienated the full readability of Aquinas's texts. Acting against Cartesian modes of reading, Cornelius Ernst's re-performance of Thomistic pedagogy as ‘engaged contemplation’ is concerned to enact a horizon of meaning within which Aquinas's texts retain enduring readability. This article develops Ernst's Thomistic meta-theology into an account of Thomism as ‘meta-reading’. On this account, authentic Thomism involves the intentional cultivation of a total human culture, within which the inherently theological discipline of textual engagement exercises a quasi-liturgical function.

Type
Original Article
Copyright
Copyright © 2021 Provincial Council of the English Province of the Order of Preachers

Proper names and their adjectival derivatives play an important constellating role in contemporary theological discourse.Footnote 1 By self-identifying as a ‘Thomist’Footnote 2— one committed to theologising ad mentem Thomae Aquinatis—a theologian simultaneously indicates their belonging to a particular community of scholarship, their likely commitment to various theological axioms, and the types of questions that they are likely to accredit as dogmatically significant. Nonetheless, the parameters of ‘Thomism’ are historically conditioned and contingent upon the contexts in which they are invoked. The designation ‘Thomist’ embraces diverse speculative and historical approaches, some Platonising and others thoroughly Aristotelian,Footnote 3 and is broad enough to cover (without much controversy) thinkers as divergent as Garrigou-Lagrange, de Lubac, Milbank and Rahner. The plasticity of ‘Thomism’ as a category is indicated by its easy conjunction with other proper names or qualifiers (‘Wittgensteinian-Thomism’ being but one apposite example). Indeed, the extent to which ‘Thomism’ implies commitment to particular dogmatic propositions is debated: for some, ‘Thomism’ implies commitment to certain doctrinal principles that secure the integrity of a theological worldview; for others, ‘Thomism’ is essentially a formal principle, designating a habit of mind that balances the integrity of both faith and reason. Yet this methodological commitment to the relationship of faith and reason is one aspect of a broader account of grace as perfecting nature. Consequently, form and content cannot be so easily dissociated: content implies form, and vice versa.

In a discipline marked by increasing fragmentation and inescapable politicisation, the use of such designations derived from proper names—with their promise of a sense of theological kinship—risks collapsing questions of truth into those of identity.Footnote 4 In contrast to some rather narrow understandings of Thomism, the intellectual tradition of the English Dominican province has tended to emphasise the importance of Aquinas's texts as providing a common theological grammar, but the ‘Thomists’ that it has produced are far from a homogenous group concerned to propagate a single definitive interpretation of the Angelic Doctor's thought. A common commitment to ‘Thomism’ has fostered ongoing conversation and facilitated generative disagreement.

This article offers a reading of Cornelius Ernst's proposed ontology of meaning as a contribution to an intellectual culture that safeguards such an orientation to Aquinas's texts. After arguing that name-invocation within theological discourse ought to depend upon the accessibility of a canon of texts, I propose a distinction between textual intelligibility and readability. On this analysis, ‘readability’ concerns the full performative efficacy of a text (understood in cultural-linguistic and psycho-spiritual terms), whereas ‘intelligibility’ concerns the reconstruction and translation of its cognitive-propositional contents. Cornelius Ernst's proposed ontology of meaning is then read as an attempt to secure the readability of Aquinas's texts, through strategies of reading that he describes as ‘engaged contemplation’ and ‘meta-theology’. So, for Ernst, who had a notable suspicion of ‘Thomism’ as a theological school,Footnote 5 the true meaning of ‘Thomism’ can only be rendered adverbially, as the convivial cultivation of a total human culture within which Aquinas's texts are rendered authentically readable.

Proper Names and the Readability of Texts

The tendency to invoke ‘Thomism’ is embedded within a much broader strategy of name-invocation within contemporary theological discourse, which is not unrelated to the popularity of genealogy as a hermeneutical strategy.Footnote 6 At least three factors contribute to the utility of proper names. Firstly, contemporary theological curricula lack a common textual framework (as might once have been provided by Lombard's Sentences or even by Aquinas's Summa Theologiae). Secondly (and not entirely unrelatedly), there is a marked lack of consensus concerning what constitutes a theological question (or, indeed, how the truth of such questions ought to be judged). As a discipline, theology is consequently marked by a methodological self-consciousness that is not reducible to a function of the interrogation of its epistemological foundations. Thirdly, within the contemporary academy, emerging scholars face a pragmatic need to demonstrate the impact of their work relative to identifiable and ongoing intellectual conversations.

A novice theologian is thus faced with an almost bewildering array of competing texts and interpretative communities. The impossibility of mastering such an enormous body of literature can be managed by learning a series of basic theological moves or impulses that are associated with the great architects of the theological tradition. In this way, a theologian can situate herself by invoking proper names as fixed points against which their own dogmatic movements can be triangulated through a kind of intellectual trigonometry. In such a conceptual topography, ‘Thomistic’ might indicate a particular view of the nature-grace relation, the negotiation of a course between fideism and rationalism, or a commitment to intellectualism; ‘Scotist’ might indicate voluntarism, a particular account of the divine infinity, an acceptance of the formal distinction, or a stance on the motives of the incarnation; ‘Barthian’ is suggestive of a Christocentric concentration and a critique of natural theology governed by the rejection of the analogia entis; and ‘Schleiermacherian’ understood as locating an Archimedean point for theology within a universal Gefühl, thereby attempting a completion of Kant's third critique. The names by which a theologian orientates herself are largely contingent upon the particular communities to which she belongs and within which she was formed.

Positively, this constellating use of proper names potentially facilitates the advance of theological conversation: proper names function as a professional shorthand, derived from an engagement with an identifiable canon of texts. In this sense, the invocation of a proper name obviates the need to re-think the entire nexus mysteriorum from first principles in every conversation. Negatively, name-invocation easily collapses into exclusionary jargon and needless obfuscation, and quickly becomes detached from the detailed engagement with texts that it gestures towards. Indeed, as will be clear from the thumbnail sketches above, the constellating use of names depends upon a necessary lack of granularity, which is unavoidably reductive, homogenizing a huge degree of complexity within the polyvalence of the texts and the history of their reception.

Consequently, name-invocation risks collapsing into the use of names as a placeholder or remainder concept that substitutes for thought. The invocation of a proper name within a theological argument risks the endless generation of further discourse that is oblique to the task at hand. With the invocation of a name, the theologian immediately renders herself liable to the suggestion that she has misrepresented the ‘contents’ signified by that name. Problematically, such an objection can be entertained within a general agnosticism about the truth or falsehood of the position, considered apart from the question of interpretative fidelity. Conversely, the argument can usually proceed without accrediting the invocation as a faithful interpretation, but merely as a meaningful gesture towards a larger corpus of interpretative literature. Consequently, the ‘invocation’ comes to dominate the ‘name’, which is hollowed out (not unlike a beetle in a Wittgensteinian box)Footnote 7 so as to signify simply a communally negotiated consensus.

The integrity of the names within this gestural economy can only be secured relative to a canon of publicly accessible texts, through which theologians communally parse the data of revelation and orientate themselves relative to a broader nexus of texts, authors and interpreters. The good operation of name-invocation, then, depends upon the accessibility of these texts. However, the mediation of French post-structuralism to anglophone philosophy has drawn attention to an often-elided distinction between the readability of a text and the intelligibility of its contents.Footnote 8 Antecedent to the discussion of Derrida's (or Lacan's) intelligibility (not infrequently questioned)Footnote 9 is the prior question of whether their texts can be adequately accessed in translation. The explanatory framework needed to convey the dense allusions between différence and différance, with the polyvalent invocation of both differing and deferring, ultimately undermines the performative gesture of Derrida's subversion of a logocentric prioritisation of the spoken over the written. Likewise, that Lacan's nom-du-père is homophonic with the unspoken non-du-père always already invokes the intimate connection between the paternal prohibition and the ‘name’ that effects the symbolic castration.Footnote 10 The necessity of an explanatory framework forecloses the immediacy of the qualitative experience of an original textual disclosure.

Questions of translation and its limits are, of course, nothing new.Footnote 11 As a metaphysically undergirded ‘Catholicity of concepts’ is a necessary precondition for dogmatic definition, Catholic theology's commitment to the transcultural accessibility of certain texts will engender a more optimistic stance towards the possibilities of translation than would the deconstructive impulses of poststructuralism. Nonetheless, fresh attentiveness to the diverse ways in which texts function performatively (beyond simple information-communication) raises hermeneutically significant questions about the extent to which those texts are authentically readable. Resisting the collapse of ‘reading’ into ‘understanding’ demands a thicker description of texts, and an attentiveness to the different modes by which a text is engaged, both individually and communally. The question of what constitutes textual readability is, however, not unrelated to the contents of the text and its intelligibility: ‘reading’ here slips between both verbal and nominal significance (not unlike ‘faith’ invoking both fides qua and fides quae). Similarly, the concept of ‘authenticity’ can operate both adverbially and adjectivally, as designating fidelity to either form or content (or both): a ‘Thomism’ can be said to be authentic if it rearticulates the contents of Aquinas's text and/or if it re-performs the operations of the text.

The intelligibility of Aquinas's texts, which are marked by an intentional clarity of expression and a highly controlled poverty of style, can be established with comparatively little historical reconstruction.Footnote 12 Intelligibility does not, however, imply full readability, in the extended sense outlined above. Just as the contents of a highly corrupted manuscript might be adequately reconstructed under conditions of only partial legibility, so only a partial accessibility of a text is necessary to secure its intelligibility. The question of a text's readability, then, is both antecedent to and posterior to the question of its intelligibility: whereas intelligibility presupposes a degree of readability, significant knowledge of the text's cognitive content drives reflection on the extent of its readability, as the case of Derrida and Lacan demonstrates. Whereas the question of Derrida's readability tends to precede that of intelligibility, the opposite direction of questioning obtains in the case of Aquinas, where questions of readability are largely posterior to those of intelligibility. It is in its capacity to raise this posterior question of readability and to propose an ontological framework for the performative readability of Aquinas's texts—the adverbial authenticity of ‘Thomism’—that Cornelius Ernst's meta-theology makes a decisive contribution to the intellectual culture of the English Dominican province.

Cornelius Ernst and the Readability of Aquinas

Cornelius Ernst's use of Wittgensteinian ‘philosophical therapy’ to overcome the ‘congenital Cartesianism’ of his students, and his proposal of a new ontology of meaning to overcome latent extrinsicism, is well documented.Footnote 13 Ernst's constructive proposal, however, is explicitly concerned with an orientation to the texts of Aquinas. The readability of Aquinas's texts is compromised by their historical remoteness.Footnote 14 Although the analytic style of Thomistic argumentation takes ‘a little getting used to’, its dependence on ‘a web of concepts that haven't been acquired in any purely logical way’Footnote 15 points to a much more basic divergence of worlds. The recovery of a semantic horizon in which ‘the fundamental categories of thought and speech are the fundamental categories of the disclosed world’Footnote 16 can only be achieved through a vision that has been disciplined through serious philosophical therapy (an ‘exercise in historical sympathy’)Footnote 17 rather than by any ‘sort of infantile regression’.Footnote 18 The beginning of this therapy lies in ‘undergoing acute discontinuity between [Aquinas's] world and ours’,Footnote 19 recognising—and enduring—our alienation from Aquinas in the ‘trauma’ of his unreadability.

Consequently, Ernst's interest in the theological use of Wittgenstein and Heidegger is not purely speculative, but ab initio pedagogical, concerned to induct a particular group of students into a horizon of meaning in which ‘the world effortlessly shows itself to be what it is’,Footnote 20 thereby cultivating strategies that render Aquinas at least partially readable. This philosophical propaedeutic not only demonstrates the falsity of Cartesian intuitions, but aims to unmask the extent to which we are ‘held captive’ by what Wittgenstein called a ‘picture’Footnote 21 and Heidegger termed ‘inauthenticity’.Footnote 22 A straightforward disavowal of Cartesian anthropology is inadequate to the task of liberating the ‘modern mind’ from the nonsense generated by the metaphors into which we have been habituated by culturally-mediated linguistic prejudices. The value of the philosophy of Wittgenstein and Heidegger to Ernst's proposal resides not only in their common interest in meaning, but in their shared attentiveness to our existential self-bafflement.Footnote 23 The modern mind's predicament is not only one of intuitive philosophical error, but also one of auto-anaesthesia—a seemingly innate tendency to lose ourselves in the midst of our language—which both Sein und Zeit and the Philosophical Investigations seek to expose in their own distinctive ways.

These themes are alluded to in Ernst's characterisation of Aquinas's quinque viæ as demonstrations of ‘how we can go on speaking about God in the ordinary world’.Footnote 24 Ernst here attends to the integrity of language, community and forms of life, together with the classical Wittgensteinian-Heideggerian emphasis on the ‘every day’ or the ‘worldliness’ of language.Footnote 25 In short, our capacity for theological reading interacts with the constantly evolving dynamics of our given circumstances (a fact that gives rise to Aquinas's alienated readability in the first place). The point, here, is not only to reflect on the givenness of the Christian tradition (reflected in Ernst's talk of the Church as the ontological a priori of faith),Footnote 26 but on the embeddedness of the theologian within this givenness of world and Church. To invoke McDowell, there is no view over this givenness from ‘sideways on’:Footnote 27 the idea that the theologian can attain a synoptic and disinterested overview of theological language ab extra, strategizing about the possibility of God-talk as if the world were not already marked by such talk, is simply an illusion. This emphasises not only the inescapable finitude of language (and thus its inevitable eschatological provisionality), but rather the illusory artificiality of any picture of an outside from which to survey language. There is no place outside of our reading from which to determine our reading.

The prescription of an aggiornamento of Aquinas's strategy in the five ways by way of an ‘exploration of the genesis of meaning, understood as the manifestation of the real’Footnote 28 cuts to the heart of Ernst's constructive programme. The givenness of the world into which we are embedded is one that gives itself historically in meaning: reality simply is that which gives itself in an indeterminate number of future semantic manifestations. Consequently, meaning is not the mental event of representation, judgment or apprehension but the ‘process and praxis through which the world to which man belongs becomes the world that belongs to man’.Footnote 29 As Ernst puts it in an undeveloped footnote, ‘personal being is intrinsically communication’:Footnote 30 there is no standpoint outside of the dynamism of communication, because being itself is communicative.Footnote 31 Consequently, not only is the idea of surveying our theological language ‘sideways on’ a nonsense manufactured on Cartesian stoves, but so is the noetic ideal of a ‘sideways’ vantage point over the world. Ernst's proposal of new horizon for theology indicates a comprehensive metaphysical vision of the world in which there is no inert matter—no neutral ‘stuff’—that is not always already semiotically soaked (if not totally saturated) with the divine self-communication. ‘Reading’ then emerges as a mode of human indwelling of the world, marking a participative role in shaping the dynamic processes and praxes of communication that constitute worldliness, and thus a distinctively human way of belonging meaningfully to a meaningful world.

Although Ernst's acknowledgment of the difficulty of ‘continuing’ speaks to the felt sense of disciplinary precarity that haunts theology within the secular university,Footnote 32 it is equally indicative of a defect within dogmatics itself. The readability of Aquinas has been alienated through the adoption of secularised strategies of reading that prioritise only that which can be captured in the literal sense without remainder. Wittgenstein's suggestion that understanding is knowing how to perform the next move in a sequence, or to carry on with a task,Footnote 33 indicates that the perceived crisis of theology under the conditions of late modernity points not only to hostile circumstances, but to a crisis of theological understanding. The displacement of hostile philosophical conditions is consequently coterminous with the renewal of theology qua theology, through a discipline-specific pedagogy, marked by its own distinctive strategies of reading.Footnote 34 The question, for Ernst, was not to establish the basis upon which theological reading can get going, but rather to perform the continuance of ‘speaking about God in the ordinary world’.Footnote 35 Rather than evading responsibility to the world by a quasi-mystical escapism, the reading proper to the theological task is a sapiential discipline that looks at the world (albeit with lamentation) and sees more than can be narrated by a literal description.Footnote 36 The ontology of meaning—the proposal that the world be unified by the category of meaning—specifies the readability of the world, and the contribution that theology makes to the world by reading its unification in the divine logos.

Ernst's diagnosis of theology's philosophical malady indicates the determinative feature of theologically disordered strategies of reading: they collapse symbols into images.Footnote 37 To put the distinction somewhat crudely, whereas a symbol participates in the reality that it communicates, images point beyond themselves to the realities that they mirror by remote resemblance, without sharing in their reality.Footnote 38 Symbols are, notwithstanding their imperfect provisionality, performative embodiments of the meanings that they communicate. Adopting a strategy of reading that prioritises the imagistic over the symbolic essentially posits that ‘sideways’ vantage over meaning that Ernst's proposed semantic ontology problematises. In textual terms, collapsing the question of readability into that of intelligibility performs precisely such a reduction, by identifying the meaning of a text with the sense of its ‘contents’ alone. Indeed, the easy divisibility of form and content that the identification of meaning with ‘content’ performs is an implicit rendering of textuality in imagistic rather than symbolic terms. While both symbols and images exhibit semantic dependence upon another (from whence their meaning is received), the symbol's meaning is also partially intrinsic to its participatory constitution. A symbolic text thus exhibits within the structures of its own integrity an excessive surplus of meaning. Ernst's proposed ontology of meaning renders the world as a fundamentally symbolic reality,Footnote 39 in that it is an embodiment of meaning by way of participation in ultimate meaning. Reading the world imagistically, then, denies the transcendent excess of the world's intrinsic meanings and thus ‘secularises’ meaning through the mood of vital immanence. Ernst's semantic ontology thereby opens a horizon of reading within which such a secularized imagistic approach appears to be just as nonsensical as attempting to secure the meaning of a red traffic light entirely within the experience of the colour red.

Textuality and the Operations of Symbolic Reading

Ernst's ontological prioritisation of the symbolic indicates a particular understanding of textuality as more than the stenographic record of ideas. The process of theological self-understanding (Selbstverständnis) that a text embodies, although necessarily involving articulation, is always more than a discursive product. The discursivity of a text is grounded in an antecedent Vorverständnis, a kind of unspecifiable pre-apprehension or ‘prophetic insight’ that ‘resides in something deeper and more basic than the conscious mind’.Footnote 40 Elsewhere, Ernst describes Christian faith as the consecration of the ‘genetic moment of Christianity’ located in the Neuheitserlebnis of the resurrection.Footnote 41 A similar relationship obtains between texts the ‘prophetic insights’ that texts stabilise: texts serve to consecrate across time the prophetic insights of their authors, thus representing moments in which the generally symbolic character of the world is intensified through the artificiality of the text's frame. Texts, then, have an intrinsically symbolic character on account of their embodiment of these ‘prophetic insights’, which are located both in and beyond their discursive codification.

Within Ernst's thought, at least two particular semantic operations are integral to the strategy of symbolic reading that corresponds to this account of textuality. The first extends a fundamentally Christian tension between universalism and particularism into an account of the relationship between logos and language. Christianity locates within the particularity of the person of Christ the ultimate universal meaning of Being.Footnote 42 Universal meaning is, to borrow from Przywara,Footnote 43 in-and-beyond Christ, in two senses. Firstly, in a sense indicated by the extra Calvinisticum, the assumption of Jesus's humanity as the ‘embodiment’ of the divine word does not indicate an absolute ‘containment’ of it. Secondly, the significance of Christ's life can only be fully apprehended in its transfiguration and integration of the entire world of meaning. Consequently, any attempt at a descriptive reading of Christ's life, in its irreducible particularity, demands that more than Christ's life be described; any attempt to close Christ off from the broader world of meaning will ipso facto violate the integrity of Christ himself (by performing an imagistic ‘sideways’ reading). Transposed into linguistic terms, the ontology of meaning acknowledges the presence of ultimate meaning (logos) in-and-beyond language (logoi). This ‘dynamic transcendence’Footnote 44 characterises symbolic strategies of reading more generally: symbolic texts are marked by a relational transcendence that in no way compromises immanence. Similarly, texts are possessed of semi-permeable boundaries; symbolic readings acknowledge textual meanings to be both inside-and-beyond those boundaries in a non-contrastive sense.

The porosity of semantic boundaries is a crucial feature of the second linguistic operation that characterises symbolic reading, located in metaphor.Footnote 45 Whilst noting the ways in which Aquinas identifies the categories of ‘symbol’ and ‘metaphor’,Footnote 46 Ernst differentiates metaphor from symbol by reading it as a semantic praxis, ‘the mental operation proper to symbolism’,Footnote 47 which ‘carries meaning over’ from one semantic domain to another. Although the semantic transfer of metaphor can involve the ‘translation’ of meanings within the same semantic domain, it more properly refers to the transference of meanings between the sensible-material domain and the higher order of the immaterial-intelligible, through the semantic mediation of some aspect of sensible reality.Footnote 48 As Marie-Dominique Chenu observes in his account of the symbolist mentality of the middle ages, ‘metaphor is obedient to the necessities imposed by transcendent realities’:Footnote 49 metaphor is not, then, a simple projection of immanent human meanings, but rather these human meanings labouring under the intense pressure of determination by the transcendent object that they communicate. The catachresis of metaphor pushes at the limits of our words, making them more communicatively capacious; symbolic reading likewise recognises the overdetermined character of texts. According to Ernst, metaphor is not reducible to predication, nor sharply differentiated from literal speech.Footnote 50 Likewise, metaphor is not primarily understood as a decorative feature of language that indicates only an aesthetic excess over intelligibility. Rather, metaphor refers to a skilful practice by which an intelligent agent negotiates their semantic habitat by way of ‘reading’: metaphor simply corresponds to the symbolic character of reality.

Of particular importance to Ernst is the category of ontological metaphor. His most extensive use of the concept is found in a version of his ‘Meaning and Metaphor’ essay that was not included in Multiple Echo, but was subsequently published in New Blackfriars in 1980.Footnote 51 Linguistically, ontological metaphors represent an abstract and intangible reality (like an emotion or an activity) in terms of something that is concrete and tangible (like an object or person).Footnote 52 For example, the question ‘how did you get into systematic theology?’ uses spatial language, derived from experience of containers, to articulate the process of becoming interested in the otherwise abstract concept of the discipline of systematics. These sorts of ontological metaphors are deeply intuitive to a native speaker and might only be recognised as metaphors after philosophical reflection.Footnote 53 Indeed, many ontological metaphors are concealed within quotidian patterns of expression. The statement ‘there was much joy’, for instance, uses quantifiers drawn from experience of extended objects to narrate the intensity of an experience that has no physical extension per se (but which does have proportionate affects within the observable world). The essence of an ontological metaphor, then, is to communicate an unboundaried reality by the use of a mediating, boundaried, reality that is drawn from empirically observable actuality. As such, texts are themselves ontologically metaphoric: the reading of a text embraces the limitation of its boundaries to reach towards the horizon of infinite meaning that asymptotically recedes behind it.

The suggestion that Ernst's work be taken to illustrate a concern for readability (albeit in an existentially extended sense) might seem ironic, given his reputation for a certain stylistic opacity. To use examples drawn solely from the ranks of his brethren, Ernst's writing has been described as ‘contorted’,Footnote 54 riddled by ‘over-complexification’Footnote 55 and even as simply ‘pretentious’.Footnote 56 Anachronistically, Ernst's writing often approximates a style associated more with Radical Orthodoxy than with the ‘house style’ of a Province that has cherished shorter sentences and unambiguous clarity. Nonetheless, this criticism has, perhaps, been overstated. Although there are certainly moments when Ernst's prose struggles to yield a straightforward meaning, there are also moments of lucidity: if his essay on ‘Theological Method’ is an example of his most prolix and obscure, his book on grace and the essay on metaphor are clearly written and communicative, even if at times poetic. In essence, however, Ernst's style corresponds to the account of language that he develops; his texts are performative with respect to the new horizon of meaning that he seeks to open for his students. Ernst's writing, in all of its density, exposes the potency of language in its dynamic transcendence and ontological metaphoricity. Ernst's analysis of language seeks not only to demonstrate the ways in which God-talk places creaturely discourse under an intense pressure that pushes at the boundaries of its intelligibility, but to expose the mysteric (because intrinsically theological) character of all language, even the most quotidian. The density of Ernst's prose, then, corresponds to the ontological depths that he finds within meaning, which is not simply read off the world as brute propositions entirely expressible in the language of literal description. Just as the givenness into which we are embedded pro- and e-vokes our semantic activity, so Ernst's texts can be engaged only through a kind of cognitive grappling. Here, Ernst is concerned—to used Heideggerian terms—to push beyond ‘ontic concretions’Footnote 57 into the realm of the truly ontological, refusing to substitute a description of entities and their behaviours in place of an ontological analysis of its mode of being.

Thomistic Pedagogy: Reading and/as Engaged Contemplation

If Ernst's approach to reading and writing is indeed animated by these performative concerns, his thought is best conceived as a re-enactment of Thomistic pedagogy in semantic idiom. The question of faithfulness is then partially transferred from the mediation of content to the fidelity of performance. Ernst inherited an awareness of Aquinas as a pedagogue from Victor White, for whom the Summa Theologiæ was not primarily a textbook for students (as it had customarily been taken to be), but a manual for teachers of introductory theology courses, helping them to anticipate and provoke discussion and debate.Footnote 58 The dialogical character of the Summa indicates an isomorphism with Wittgenstein's Philosophical Investigations, in which Wittgenstein's engagement with his interlocutors serves to elicit a response from the reader that exposes the concealed ‘deep logic’ of their thought. A faithful reading of the Investigations entails both the rendering intelligible of an argument as well as the uncovering of impulses that generate the ‘picture’ that holds us captive.

Ernst's re-performance of Thomistic pedagogy constitutes theology as the discipline of ‘engaged contemplation’ or ‘contemplative engagement’Footnote 59 in service of the divine logos.Footnote 60 The extended sense of reading that Ernst cultivates is not only engaged in this sense of enacting a relationship of a text to the world, but also engaging of its practitioners, involving the whole human person in the paradoxical hyper-activity of contemplation.Footnote 61 Reading as ‘engaged contemplation’ means learning to repeatedly allow ourselves—with all of our personal history, frailty and affective idiosyncrasy—to be confronted, through the vehicle of a text, with the question of ultimate meaning, and thus with the theological interpretation of the meaning of our own lives. Such a strategy of reading can be sustained only within the context of a life lived in the presence of the ultimate answer,Footnote 62 a semantic horizon that points beyond itself and extends into infinity. Reading within the horizon of ultimate meaning thus awakens us more and more deeply to the ontological depths of reality, containing within itself a pre-apprehension of the radical inadequacy of any human articulations of it.

Similarly, the Summa guides and resources the teacher (on White's account) in the development of a praxis of theology that engages the student with questions and solicits from them a response. That Aquinas explicitly considered such questions of pedagogy is clear, not only from the historical record of his experimental ‘studium personale’ in Rome,Footnote 63 but equally from the text of the Summa Theologiæ itself. The prologue of the prima pars speaks of the true Catholic teacher as one who takes the student by the hand, leading them (manuductio) through a theological journey into beatitude.Footnote 64 The intellectual itinerary of the summa emerges as a kind of intellectual exercise, which is inaugurated with two questions that establish the inescapable ontological horizon within which this disciplina operates:Footnote 65 the first, on sacra doctrina, establishes the presence of ultimate meaning (through the mediation of a subalternated science);Footnote 66 the second, on the five ways, establishes the unity of the world of meaning in the divine logos.Footnote 67 The Neoplatonic exitus-reditus structure, identified by Ernst's sometime correspondent M.-D. Chenu,Footnote 68 not only determines in a general way the ‘emergence’ of creation as ordained to final consummation, but also indicates the theologian's own journey into truth, performed in their theological reading and eschatologically consummated in Christ.Footnote 69

In an authentic reading of the Summa, then, training in theological argumentation and formation in the craft of Christian holiness are somewhat coextensive: the theological life and the communication of truth are both brought into the service of the life of sanctifying grace.Footnote 70 Indeed, this formative function is reflected not only in the macrostructure of the Summa, but equally in the microstructure of the Summa’s basic unit, the article.Footnote 71 Framed as a theological question using the particle utrum, the article is constituted by a call-and-response of objections and their answers. This indicates a further isomorphism with Wittgenstein's Investigations, which contain a vast array of questions, many rhetorical or aporetic, confused and confusing.Footnote 72 Whereas Wittgenstein seems largely to use questions to move us from ‘unobvious nonsense to obvious nonsense’Footnote 73 by indicating the ways in which our questions are non-sensical or misplaced, Aquinas's questions are pre-refined—though they sometimes undergo further purification by way of distinguishing their meaning. Questions serve Aquinas in giving overall shape and dynamism to the structure of his Summa. Importantly, the invocation of proper names (whether appeals to authorities or intellectual adversaries) is always nested within these questions, so that the aporiai within the canon of texts are exposed and resolved by reference to the truth or falsity of a question: it is the question which drives reading, and name-invocation that serves this movement.

In the Dominican context in which Aquinas taught, the rhythmic backwards and forwards motion that characterises each article is evocative of the antiphonal character of the chanted liturgy. Likewise, Aquinas's eclectic use of sources that were also deployed in the liturgy would have evoked a rich penumbra of memories and associations. The respondeo—Aquinas's conclusion or resolution—is not located at the end of the article, but in the middle, and therefore does not bring the motion of reading to a point of rest. The response of the teacher does not end the dialogue and leave the student satisfied that they now know the ‘correct’ answer, but rather propels the student to return (in almost every case) to the objections and find, in responding to them, the full implications of the respondeo itself. Similarly, the theologian is only able to read the Christian meaning of time through discernment of the Christian meaning of their own times;Footnote 74 the light of the logos is seen only as it illumines and integrates the logoi of the present moment.

‘Thomism’ as Meta-Reading

As has become clear, theology cannot read the theological meanings entertained by the Christian tradition and its texts without itself being an instance of that tradition and of those meanings.Footnote 75 Consequently, theological reading only ever exists as a kind of culture, in which ‘prophetic insight’ (Vorverständnis) is cultivated and disciplined into a theological ‘competence’ that is productive of discursivity. The commitment to cultivating such a disciplined culture of convivial reading is self-involving and invokes dynamics of apprenticeship and formation. For better or for worse, engaged contemplation retains the highly self-conscious methodological preoccupations of contemporary theology more broadly. Nonetheless, if ‘Thomism’ has any meaningful sense within the horizon of Ernst's proposed ontology, it is as the cultivation and elicitation of a shared context within which Aquinas's texts have an enduring readability. There is, of course, no sense that only one intellectual culture can provide for the readability of Aquinas—not every Thomist needs to live the ‘significant life’Footnote 76 of a Dominican house of studies—but any such culture will be meaningful and intelligible to any other such culture: so ‘Thomism’ retains its plasticity.

Part of the strength of the English Dominican province's ‘Thomism’ has been the cultivation of an ecology of reading, within which multiple ‘Thomisms’ have flourished in mutually intelligible (and interrogative) coexistence. The extent to which Ernst contributed to the formation of such an ecology of reading is hard to adjudicate, but he hints towards it in his development of an account of engaged contemplation as ‘meta-theology’.Footnote 77 The contents of the ‘meta’, here, are specified by the epistemological correlates of his theological ontology. Theology can only thrive when it is consciously conducted coram God as the ‘meaning of meaning’ and when possessed of an ineliminable wonder at the mystery of its own being.Footnote 78 Ernst acknowledges that, in his own time, there were only ‘anticipations’ of such a meta-theology;Footnote 79 it is difficult to know where he would look for such a theology in the decades after his death. Nonetheless, three features of this anticipated meta-theology are clear and can usefully contribute to the development of a practice that might be termed ‘meta-reading’. Firstly, meta-theology involves a movement beyond ‘theologies’ to an integrative and unitive ‘Theology’: in other words, a relativisation of the gestural economy of name-invocation. This process involves reflection upon the historical reality of theological development and the emergence of theological opposition, thereby raising the question of the meaning of the history of dogma and the meaning of fractured plurality. Theological readings of this dogmatic diffusion should be performatively ontologically metaphoric, in seeking to sacramentally realise the re-unification (by transfiguration) of this diversity in Christ. Secondly, meta-theology is attuned to the intentional cultivation of the symbolic and metaphoric within in the mediated operations of dynamic transcendence. Whilst the definitive ‘ontic’ answer to theological questioning is available solely in Jesus Christ, the ontological meaning of this is worked out by proceeding through what Ernst terms ‘the starting point of the logos-eikōn-mustērion’.Footnote 80 In other words, our particular practices of reading are ultimately to be nested within the Ur-Text of Christ. Thirdly, this meta-theology is realized only as a ‘total human culture’,Footnote 81 that is, as a progressive communal discovery of a common identity in Jesus Christ, in ways that necessarily elude total specification.

In the meta-reading that is informed by such a meta-theology, the ‘meta’ is specified not only by the mystical elements of Ernst's Neoplatonism and its horizon of meaning, but by a commitment to rather mundane communal practices of symbolic reading, as indicated above. ‘Thomism’ in this Ernstian mode signals a performative recovery of Augustine's wonder at encountering Ambrose's silent reading. The fact that we read (and not only that we can read) is itself an eikon of the mustērion of Christ—and the continuation of that reading the urgent task of the theologian. This mystery of reading has often been taken for granted, commodified by a quantitative rendering of what is to be gained from (rather than through) reading and a consequent quasi-idolatrous desire to master vast swathes of material (a desire indulged—but never satisfied—by name-invocation). In the film Derrida, the philosophe himself was asked if he had read all the books in his library: ‘only three or four’, he replied, ‘but those three or four really, really well’.

Attentiveness to the unspecifiable coefficient of meta-reading ought not undermine the obvious fact that Aquinas's texts are intentionally intelligible, and that information-communication is a significant (perhaps sometimes predominant) mode of their operation. Meta-reading is still reading in the conventional sense of the term, albeit reading that indwells the ‘meta-’ so as to expose and disrupt the presuppositions that animate the imagistic strategies of reading that contribute to our self-bafflement. Meta-reading exposes the enormous artificiality of reading for information alone. The contribution that the ‘meta’ makes to theological reading resembles (perhaps uncomfortably for some) the monastic practice of lectio divina. As has been noted elsewhere in respect to Simone Weil's reading-for-attentiveness, the type of attention cultivated by these strategies of reading hints towards the reverential.Footnote 82 Indeed, it is notable that some of Ernst's most helpful resources in the development of a theological meta-reading are located in his treatment of worship and sacramental liturgy.

Like the proposed meta-reading, Ernst understands liturgy in terms of an active constituting of the subjective conditions for theological knowledge. In his essay ‘how to see an angel?’ (a question that Barth thought was stupid),Footnote 83 Ernst explicitly deals with the liturgy as the enacted locus for certain types of knowledge. Liturgy ‘creates a special kind of state’,Footnote 84 in which there is a ‘transformation of the visible world into something fulfilled that we can call invisible’.Footnote 85 The question of seeing an angel is not stupid, but only because in the liturgy an event is performed in which the human and the angelic share a community with one another. This community is determined by an acknowledgment of a shared practice, that of praising the triune glory. This liturgical knowledge is mediated by ecstasis, by being-with (Mitsein), and it is this mode of being-with that the liturgy enacts in an intensified form. To put this in terms of meta-reading: ‘Thomism’ demarcates a semantic locus in which we are able to be-with Aquinas's texts by way of sharing a task, that of the rhythmic and self-involving quest for ultimate truth in our reditus (with Christ) to God.

Crucially, it is a pre-requisite of Ernst's account of liturgical knowledge by being-with that the subject does something: viz. ‘create a dimension of life that wasn't there until we actually elicited it, by actually doing something by performing something historically’.Footnote 86 Two important insights are buried within this laconic phrase. Firstly, the choice of verb—‘elicited’, rather than, say, ‘constructed’—indicates a metaphysical limit on the human contribution: the presupposition, unsurprisingly, is of an antecedent givenness, an action or state of affairs, upon which the action of worship (or meta-reading) depends. Secondly, the description of the activity performed as ‘historical’ contains within it two notions that are essential to historicity. The first is that of embodiment. The action of worship or meta-reading that is performed and enacted is a bodily activity, the disciplines of attentiveness embedded within them are just as bodily as they are intellectual. The second contained notion is that of sociality:Footnote 87 as historical, bodily, creatures, Ernst understands us to be always already enmeshed in webs of relationships, bound together in the histories that we make and share. As historical, then, the liturgical assembly is necessarily a community, possessed of a certain structured conviviality.

So where does this leave the economy of name-invocation as a means of stabilising rhizomatic theological pluralism? Only a commitment to sustaining the readability of texts can prevent such an economy collapsing into mere gesture. The best contribution that we can make, then, lies in the disciplined cultivation of meta-reading, (re-)performing ‘a dimension of life that wasn't there until we actually elicited it, by actually doing something historically’. Thomism thus understood is a far more demanding task than understanding and manipulating dogmatic axioms. Nonetheless, a Thomism so-conceived better explains why generations of English Dominicans have found that the texts of Aquinas do not leave them alone.

References

1 Richard Rorty suggested that proceeding in terms of proper names rather than propositions differentiates ‘continental’ philosophy from analytic approaches, see: Contingency, Irony, and Solidarity (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1989), 81 fn 3.Google Scholar

2 On the complexities of Thomist self-identification, see: Lauder, Robert E., “On Being or Not Being a Thomist,” The Thomist 55, no. 2 (1991): 301-19CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

3 Ventimiglia, Giovanni, Aquinas after Frege (London: Palgrave Macmillan, 2020), 1-32.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

4 Cf., Braaten, Carl E and Jenson, Robert W., In One Body Through the Cross: The Princeton Proposal for Christian Unity (Grand Rapids: Eerdmans, 2003), 41-42.Google Scholar

5 Ernst, Cornelius, Multiple Echo: Explorations in Theology, ed. Radcliffe, Timothy and Kerr, Fergus (London: Darton, Longman Todd, 1979), 11Google Scholar. Hereafter cited as ‘ME’.

6 Cunningham, Conor, Genealogy of nihilism : philosophies of nothing and the difference of theology, Radical orthodoxy series Y (London: London : Routledge, 2002).Google Scholar

7 PI. §293

8 Butler, Judith, “Introduction,” in Of Grammatology, ed. Derrida, Jacques (2016), vii-xxiv.Google ScholarPubMed

9 Scruton, Roger, Fools, Frauds and Firebrands (London: Bloomsbury, 2015)Google Scholar.

10 Evans, Dylan, An Introductory Dictionary of Lacanian Psychoanalysis (London: Routledge, 1996), 119.Google Scholar

11 Benjamin, Walter, ‘The Task of the Translator’, in Illuminations: Essays and Reflections, ed. Arendt, Hannah (Boston: Mariner, 1968), 11-25.Google Scholar

12 See, for instance, Chenu, Marie-Dominique, Toward Understanding St Thomas, trans. Landry, A. -M. (Chicago: Regnery, 1964)Google Scholar.

13 Roy, Louis, ‘Cornelius Ernst's Theological Seeds’, New Blackfriars 85, no. 998 (2004): 459-70CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Kerr, Fergus, ‘Ansombe, Ernst and McCabe: Wittgenstein and Catholic Theology’, Josephinum 15, no. 1 (2008): 128-48Google Scholar; Williams, Rowan, The Edge of Words: God and the Habits of Language (London: Continuum, 2014), Ch. 1Google Scholar; Keenan, Oliver James, ‘Sacrament of the Dynamic Transcendence of Christianity: Cornelius Ernst on the Church’, New Blackfriars 94, no. 1052 (2013): 396-414.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

14 ME, 7.

15 ME, 9.

16 ME, 10.

17 ME, 11.

18 ME, 12.

19 ME, 11.

20 ME, 11.

21 Egan, David, ‘Pictures in Wittgenstein's Later Philosophy’, Philosophical Investigations 34, no. 1 (2011): 55-76.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

22 Mills, Jon, ‘The False Dasein’, Journal of Phenomenological Psychology 28, no. 1 (1997): 42-65.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

23 Egan, David, The Pursuit of an Authentic Philosophy: Wittgenstein, Heidegger and the Everyday (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2019)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

24 ME, 74.

25 ME, 142.

26 ME, 139.

27 McDowell, John, ‘Non-Cognitivism and Rule Following’, in Wittgenstein: To Follow a Rule, ed. Holtzman, Stephen and Leich, Christopher M. (London: Routledge, 1981), 141-72.Google Scholar

28 ME: 74.

29 Ernst, Cornelius, The Theology of Grace (South Bend: University of Notre Dame Press, 1974), 68.Google Scholar

30 ME, 106.

31 For similar examinations of the intrinsically diffusive and communicative character of being, see: Hemmerle, Klaus, Theses Towards a Trinitarian Ontology, trans. Churchyard, Stephen (Brooklyn: Angelico Press, 2020)Google Scholar; Ulrich, Ferdinand, Homo Abyssus, trans. Schindler, D. C. (Washington DC: Humanum Press, 2018)Google Scholar.

32 ME: 8.

33 PI, §151-155.

34 Cf Webster, John Bainbridge, ‘Theological Theology’, in Confessing God: Essays in Christian Dogmatics (London: T&T Clark, 2005), 11-32.Google Scholar

35 ME, 74. The logic of the ‘ordinary world’ is explored at ME, 142.

36 ME, 26.

37 See ME, 63-65.

38 ME, 64.

39 Rahner, Karl, ‘The Theology of the Symbol’, in Theological Investigations Vol 4 (1966), 221-52Google Scholar; Fields, Stephen M., Being as Symbol: On The Origins and Development of Karl Rahner's Metaphysics (Washington DC: Georgetown University Press, 2000).Google Scholar

40 ME, 84.

41 ME, 215.

42 ME, 32.

43 Przywara, Erich, Analogia Entis: Metaphysik (München: Kösel, 1932).Google Scholar

44 See ME, 32 and 13-27.

45 Ernst, Cornelius, ‘Metaphor and Ontology in Sacra Doctrina’, The Thomist 38(1974): 422-25CrossRefGoogle Scholar; ‘Truth and Verification in Theology’, New Blackfriars 40, no. 468 (1959): 100-11CrossRefGoogle Scholar; ‘Meaning and Metaphor in Theology’, New Blackfriars 61, no. 718 (1980): 100-12.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

46 ME, 64.

47 ME, 68.

48 ME, 67.

49 Chenu, Marie-Dominique, Nature, Man and Society in the Twelfth Century (Chicago: Chicago University Press, 1968), 138.Google Scholar

50 ME, 71-74.

51 Ernst, Meaning and Metaphor.

52 As Boers puts it, developing the typology presented by Lakoff and Johnson, ‘ontological metaphors allow us to conceive of abstract concepts as concrete entities’, see: Spatial Prepositions and Metaphor (Tübingen: Gunter Narr Verlag, 1996), 21Google Scholar. The literature on ‘ontological metaphors’ is now vast. See: Lakoff, George and Johnson, Mark, Metaphors We Live By, 2nd ed. (Chicago: Chicago University Press, 2003), 25CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Cazeaux, Clive, Metaphor and Continental Philosophy (New York: Routledge, 2007), 197.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

53 See Williams, Donald C., ‘The Myth of Passage’, Philosophy 48, no. 15 (1951): 457-72.Google Scholar

54 Tugwell, Simon, ‘Cornelius Ernst OP’, New Blackfriars 59(1978): 2-4.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

55 Nichols, Aidan, ‘Catholic Theology in Britain’, online: http://www.christendom-awake.org/pages/anichols/theolog1.htmlGoogle Scholar

56 Hill, Edmund, ‘Cornelius Ernst OP: Multiple Echo’, Fergus Kerr, OP and OP, Timothy Radcliffe (eds.),” The Thomist 46, no. 4 (1982): 631-36.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

57 Slaby, Jan, ‘Ontic’, in The Cambridge Heidegger Lexicon, ed. Wrathall, Mark A. (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2021), 542-46.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

58 White, Victor, Holy Teaching: The Idea of Theology According to St. Thomas Aquinas (London: Blackfriars Publications, 1958).Google Scholar

59 ME, 151. Graham Ward has recently developed an account of theology as ‘engaged systematics’. Ernst would have had considerable sympathy with Ward's proposals, but would avoid, given his understanding of Aquinas as a thematic thinker, have preferred not to deploy the term ‘systematics’. ‘Contemplation’ more precisely evokes the perspective of meaning that Ernst is seeking to develop. Ward's proposals, meanwhile, are embedded within the first volume of his systematics (something Ernst's sporadic approach to writing could not have sustained). See: Ward, Graham, How the Light Gets In (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2016)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

60 Ernst's notion of ‘servanthood of the Word’ has been taken up into the 2016 Edition of the Order of Preachers’ Ratio Formationis Generalis.

61 For an exploration of these themes, see: Kotva, Simone, Effort and Grace: On the Spiritual Exercise of Philosophy (London: Bloomsbury, 2020)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

62 ME, 152.

63 Torrell, Jean-Pierre, St Thomas Aquinas: The Person and His Work, trans. Royal, Robert (Washington DC: Catholic University of America Press, 1996), 142-59Google Scholar; See also: Boyle, Leonard E., ‘The Setting of the Summa Theologiae’, in Aquinas's Summa Theologiae: Critical Essays, ed. Davies, Brian (Oxford: Rowman & Littlefield, 2006), 1-24.Google Scholar

64 This point has been made forcefully by Candler, Peter M., Theology, Rhetoric, Manuduction: Or Reading Scripture Together on the Path to God, Radical Traditions (London: SCM Press, 2006).Google Scholar

65 On qq. 1 and 2 of the prima pars, see: Kerr, Fergus, After Aquinas: Versions of Thomism (Oxford: Blackwells, 2002), 52-72CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Bauerschmidt, Frederick Christian, Thomas Aquinas: Faith, Reason and Following Christ (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2013), 41-82, 91-106CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Preller, Victor, Divine Science and the Science of God (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1967), 108-79Google Scholar; Kerr, Fergus, ‘Real Knowledge or ‘Enlightened Ignorance: Eric Mascall on the Apophatic Thomisms of Victor Preller and Victor White’, in Grammar and Grace, ed. Stout, Jeffrey and MacSwain, Robert (London: SCM Press, 2004), 103-23.Google Scholar

66 ME, 9.

67 ME, 7-8.

68 Chenu, Marie-Dominique, ‘Le plan de la somme théologique de saint Thomas’, Revue Thomiste 47(1939): 93-107.Google Scholar

69 The connection between sanctification, theosis and the discipline of theology has been articulated by Ryan, Fáinche, Formation in Holiness: Thomas Aquinas on Sacra Doctrina (Utrecht: Thomas Instituut/Peeters Leuven, 2007)Google Scholar; Williams, Anna Ngaire, ‘Deification in the Summa theologiae: A Structural Interpretation of the Prima Pars’, The Thomist 61, no. 2 (1997): 219-55CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

70 Cf., ME, 121.

71 Bird, Otto, ‘How to Read an Article of the Summa’, New Scholasticism 27, no. 2 (1953): 129-59.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

72 Egan, Authentic Philosophy, 224-26.

73 PI, §464.

74 ME, 108.

75 ME, 79.

76 ME, 149-157.

77 ME, 76-86, particularly 85.

78 For an examination of this theme from a phenomenological perspective, see: DeLay, Steven, Before God: Exercises in Subjectivity (London: Bloomsbury, 2019).Google Scholar

79 ME, 85.

80 ME, 85.

81 ME, 84.

82 Zaretsky, Robert, The Subversive Weil. (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2021): Ch. 2.Google Scholar

83 CD III/3: 477.

84 ME, 198.

85 ME, 199.

86 ME, 201.

87 ME, 27-28, 79.