Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-l7hp2 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-25T09:09:21.257Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Moral Conscience and the Experience of God

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  28 February 2024

Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Extract

Core share and HTML view are not available for this content. However, as you have access to this content, a full PDF is available via the ‘Save PDF’ action button.

I am making a systematic theological point about the relationship between moral conscience and the experience of God. While the same theme may be taken up as a moral theological question, my intention is to explicate in part the meaning of ‘God’ as implied by the Christian witness of faith, and so I am approaching the theme as a systematic theologian and not from the perspective of moral theology. That is, I intend to ask primarily about the significance of moral conscience for understanding our experience of God, and not vice versa.

Clearly the phrase ‘the experience of God’ is systematically ambiguous, and I will argue that the term ‘moral conscience’ or ‘dictates of conscience’ is also systematically ambiguous, and that recognition of this ambiguity helps us resolve a cluster of philosophical and theological problems that accompany any assertion that moral conscience is a mode of the experience of God. (‘The experience of God’ is also grammatically an ambiguous phrase, of course. Here I will be using it as an objective genitive unless otherwise indicated.)

My central hypothesis is that the experience of moral conscience is a primary mode of the experience of God, if not the most important mode. This hypothesis is hardly without controversy: at least since the beginning of the nineteenth century, when D.F. Schleiermacher argued against any simple identification of moral conscience and religious experience, it has been recognized to be complex and problematic. Schleiermacher wrote in 1799 that religion ‘must be something different from a mixture of opinions about God and the world, and of precepts for one life or for two. Piety cannot be an instinct craving for a mess of metaphysical and ethical crumbs’ (Schleiermacher, 31).

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © 1989 Provincial Council of the English Province of the Order of Preachers

References

Works Cited

Aquinas, Thomas. Summa Theologiae.Google Scholar
Flannery, Austin P., ed. Documents of Vatican II. Grand Rapids, Michigan: Eerdmans Press, 1975.Google Scholar
Niebuhr, H. Richard. Radical Monotheism und Western Culture. New York: Harper & Row, 1960.Google Scholar
Ogden, Schubert M. The Point of Christology. San Francisco: Harper & Row, 1982.Google Scholar
Oman, John. Vision und Authoriry. Cambridge University Press, 1958.Google Scholar
Rahner, Karl. ‘Intellectual Honesty and Christian Faith.’ In Theologicul Investigutions, VII. Translated by Bourke, David. New York: Seabury Press, 1977.Google Scholar
Schleiermacher, David Friedrich. On Religion: Speeches to Its Cultured Despisers. Translated by Oman, John. New York: Harper and Row, 1958.Google Scholar
Tillich, Paul. Systematic Theology, 3 volumes in one. University of Chicago Press, 1967.Google Scholar
Whitehead, Alfred North. Modes of Thought. New York: Macmillan Publishing Co., Inc., 1966.Google Scholar