The current scholarship on the question of whether God exists might seem on the surface to have little in common with the thought of Thomas Aquinas as articulated in his Summa Theologiae q.2 a.3. From the perspective of the current debate, the thought of Thomas could seem esoteric, unnecessary, and inapplicable. The recent work by Fiona Ellis offers a complex contemporary approach to the question of God. Her work indicates the shifting ground of the debate and the use of an explicit articulation of methodology. The current conversation on the existence of God appears separated from the thought of Thomas because of both the content and the methodology.Footnote 1 This essay briefly highlights one important methodological distinction that might make it possible to relate the thought of Thomas to the current context. It could be possible to introduce the thought of Thomas into the current discussion because the subtle methodological distinctions found in the Summa contra Gentiles (SCG) can be combined with the Summa Theologiae q.2 a.3 reply to objection 2.
The methodology behind the current discussion on the existence of God is influenced by several significant factors.Footnote 2 The historical circumstances that stimulate the current discussion of the existence of God are numerous. These influences partially account for the detachment between the thought of Thomas and the current state of the question on the existence of God. In the history of philosophy, there is the development of modal logic, modern uses of epistemology, Kant, Descartes, Frege, existentialism, and hermeneutics.Footnote 3 The rapid industrialization, democratization, technologization, and globalization of society has been spurred by a belief in the progress of science. A modern conception of science, a reductionist scientism, has been used by people like Richard Dawkins to argue against the existence of God. More seriously, variations of scientism has been used by philosophers, such as Bertrand Russell and the members of the Vienna Circle. It is possible to glean from this brief survey that many influential thinkers, schools of thought, and movements promoted methodological debates because of the philosophical principles supported by an interpretation of science.
The thought of Thomas is philosophical and theological. The question of God can be addressed by philosophers and theologians because the reality they are addressing is the same. Since the time of Thomas, in the history of the Roman Catholic Church and theology, some significant events are the Reformation, the Council of Trent, the French Revolution, the loss of the papal states, the encyclical Aeterni Patris, Vatican I, and Vatican II.Footnote 4 These radical developments seem to separate the thought of Thomas from the current discussion.Footnote 5 It is necessary to hold them in mind if it is going to be possible to introduce the thought of Thomas into the current discussion.
The public debate that was carried on by the “New Atheists” was a result of philosophical principles. One way to articulate the philosophical principles and methodology presupposed by the publicized debates is with the term naturalism.Footnote 6 Fiona Ellis says that a naturalist is “someone who ‘takes it that the universe is a natural realm, governed by nature's laws’, and who believes that ‘there is nothing supernatural in the universe – no fairies or goblins, angels, demons, gods or goddesses.’”Footnote 7 There are various subtle forms of naturalism. To name only two, a naturalist can be a scientific naturalist or an expansive naturalist. A scientific naturalist forces a choice “between either science or God” because she sees them as competing explanations.Footnote 8 There are variations of expansive naturalism. Expansive naturalists may or may not be a scientific naturalist because some expansive naturalists accept the possibility that science does not offer a complete description of reality. An expansive naturalist might allow for other forms of knowledge to play a part in understanding reality because of the fact of value; in other words, the “value enchantment” of reality.Footnote 9 An expansive naturalist might accept this expansion of value into their reality. Ellis uses this in her work because if it is possible for respected philosophers to admit that naturalism should not exclude value then perhaps it might be intellectually respectable to discuss God. Yet, they might still apply the methodology of scientific naturalism to the question of the existence of God. This distinction among expansive naturalists highlights the importance of methodology for the current conversation because it might be possible to engage a naturalist on the status of reality only when methodological assumptions are explicitly analyzed.
In another methodological undertaking, Ellis intentionally engages with Christian theologians in order to distinguish between the disciplines of philosophy and theology and ultimately to reach a methodological conclusion.Footnote 10 Philosophers should not be scientific naturalists. A philosopher can still be an expansive naturalist but not an expansive naturalist who excludes God.Footnote 11 Ellis is offering her work as an example of the methodological relationship between philosophy and theology. It is an example of an expansive naturalistic work of philosophy that is not afraid of engaging with theologians on the question of the existence of God.Footnote 12
In order to articulate this particular form of expansive naturalism, Ellis has to argue that the relationship between philosophy and theology is possible because of particular methodological and ontological clarifications. Ontologically God is not another thing among things, like a ghost or one possible god or goddess among many.Footnote 13 Since God is not in ontological competition with nature, God is not “dualistically opposed to anything within the natural/empirical realm.”Footnote 14 Methodologically, this means that science and God are not “explanatory competitors.”Footnote 15 Science, philosophy, and theology have their own methodologies. The mutual relationship between God and nature/theology and philosophy is not “closed off at the outset by the imposition of a framework which excludes theism.”Footnote 16 For example, physics or the philosophy of mathematics have their own principles and methodologies which are free from theological implications.Footnote 17 A physicist, a chemist, or someone who does abstract mathematics can methodologically exclude the question of God from their calculations. In a particular sense, if they are following the principles of their discipline then they should exclude the questions of theism. In this sense, it is important for each discipline to respect its own ontological and methodological limitations. The ability to respect the limitations of each discipline does not necessitate a denial of theism.
This subtle articulation of methodology is one point of meeting between Thomas and the current debate about God and naturalism. As Thomas articulates it in the SCG, there is a philosophical order as distinguished from the theological consideration of the believer.Footnote 18 In the philosophical work, On being and essence, Thomas articulates the existence of God as the source of being/existence because the essence of God is being/existence.Footnote 19 Differing from the Summa Theologiae, this articulation of the being/existence of God is not presented in a theological work.Footnote 20 Thomas on God in On being and essence is a perfect example of the philosophical methodology articulated in the SCG. In the current context, this methodology can be called naturalistic because it “considers creatures in themselves and leads us from them to the knowledge of God, the first consideration is about creatures; the last, of God.”Footnote 21 In other words, the philosopher is a naturalist in a methodological sense because “the philosopher takes his argument from the proper causes of things; the [theologian] believer, from the first cause.”Footnote 22 The methodology in the SCG for philosophy partially corresponds with the conclusion offered by Ellis.
In the SCG, Thomas is articulating a constructive methodology. While, in the Summa Theologiae, q.2 a.3 objection 2, Thomas presents the methodological limitations of a naturalistic methodology. Relying only on the SCG, the relationship between Ellis and Thomas is not exact because of the distinction in Ellis between scientific naturalism and expansive naturalism. In the Summa Theologiae, examined below, it might be possible to find what might be called a scientific naturalist methodology in q.2 a.3 objection 2. This is important for the relevance of Thomas's methodological thought on the current debate. Because Ellis is arguing that a scientific naturalist can become an expansive naturalist and that a expansive naturalist could allow for the world to be God-involving. As Ellis says,
“I am a naturalist, but I am not a scientific naturalist because I see no reason for concluding that science is the sole measure of reality. I am not denying, of course, that it is a measure and an exceedingly important one at that. The naturalism I endorse is not co-extensive with atheism. It has room for God. This does not mean that God is a mere part of the world, nor is it a decisive proof for His existence. No such proofs are to be had. It does mean, however, that we must question the assumption that the naturalist disengages from the theist's ground of debate, a welcome conclusion given that this ground is inescapable.”Footnote 23
The expansive naturalist philosopher who does not accept scientific naturalism's limitation of method and reality can be led from considerations from within philosophical disciplines to questions about the knowledge of God (theism). In other words, for both Thomas and Ellis, it is possible for the philosopher to have a specific naturalistic method because it is proper to the realm of philosophy without being isolated from theism.
Ellis is also claiming that the expansive naturalist philosopher is open to theological considerations of theism. Ellis says, the expansive naturalist can “enter into dialogue with the theologian. … After all, [the expansive naturalist] offers the prospects for demonstrating that belief in God is intellectually respectable, and that this conclusion can be appreciated by those who have taken on board the lessons of the best naturalistic philosophy of our time.”Footnote 24 Thomas says, “But any things concerning creatures that are considered in common by the philosopher and the believer are conveyed through different principles in each case.”Footnote 25 The philosopher following the principles of expansive naturalism can demonstrate that the claim that God exists can be intellectually respectable in light of and not contrary to naturalistic philosophy. In the words of Thomas, “Hence, also, [the doctrine of the faith] ought to be called the highest wisdom, since it treats of the highest Cause; … human philosophy serves [the highest wisdom] as the first wisdom. Accordingly, divine wisdom sometimes argues from principles of human philosophy.”Footnote 26 The articulation of the methodological relationship between philosophy and theology in Thomas and Ellis shares a great deal in common. Their methodological similarities become clearer when the Summa Theologiae is incorporated. This provides the final piece which indicates that the methodological understanding of Thomas is apt for the current conversation about the existence of God.
The Summa Theologiae is an example of how Thomas, as a Catholic theologian, addressed the question of the existence of God as it arises in the “divine science” of theology. In q.2 a.3, Thomas articulates a methodological and ontological objection to the existence of God. Keeping in mind the methodological distinctions from the SCG and the argument from On being and essence, Thomas says,
“Obj. 2: Further, it is superfluous to suppose that what can be accounted for by a few principles has been produced by many. But it seems that everything we see in the world can be accounted for by other principles, supposing God did not exist. For all natural things can be reduced to one principle which is nature; and all voluntary things can be reduced to one principle which is human reason, or will. Therefore there is no need to suppose God's existence. Reply to Obj. 2: Since nature works for a determinate end under the direction of a higher agent, whatever is done by nature must needs be traced back to God, as to its first cause. So also whatever is done voluntarily must also be traced back to some higher cause other than human reason or will, since these can change or fail; for all things that are changeable and capable of defect must be traced back to an immovable and self-necessary first principle, as was shown in the body of the Article.”
The first important point to notice is how Thomas uses the term nature. The use of nature in this objection is, “all natural things can be reduced to one principle which is nature … therefore there is no need to suppose God's existence,” compared with the SCG, “For the philosopher takes his argument from the proper causes of things; the believer, from the first cause.”Footnote 27 The philosopher can argue from the proper causes of natural effects concerning natural causes. This is methodological naturalism. Objection two states that “we explain natural effects by natural causes.”Footnote 28 This is the objection of scientific naturalism.
Thomas does not contradict scientific naturalism as the methodology that is properly applied to “everything we observe in the world.” Instead, in the reply to the objection, Thomas alters the terms of the debate. The move is from “everything we can see in the world” and “all natural things” to nature or the natural itself as a whole. In the reply, it is nature that “acts/works” towards a definite end. Thomas is not considering the effects of natural things and their causes but transitions to a metaphysical consideration of the world. In other words, the methodology of scientific naturalism can apply to “everything we observe in the world,” just as, “the philosopher considers such things as belong to them by nature.”Footnote 29 But the limits of a naturalistic methodology have been reached when considering the totality of “nature” as an abstracted whole.Footnote 30 The whole of nature cannot rely upon itself as its own source.Footnote 31 The principles and methodology proper to understanding natural things and their causes cannot be used to consider the entirety of nature. This important methodological distinction is presupposed by Thomas in his methodological distinction is presupposed by Thomas in his reply to objection 2.
The question of the existence of God has implications for philosophy and theology. The current discussion has gravitated towards a methodological debate. This debate fueled by the distinction between disciplines and the developments of science can becomes misleading when assumptions of methodology lead to partial conclusions. The work of Fiona Ellis is helpful for comprehending recent explicit articulations of methodology. The expansive naturalist position which accepts a value-enchanted and God-enchanted worldview has some similarities to the methodological understanding of Thomas. When the methodology of SCG, On being and essence, and Summa Theologiae q.2 a.3 reply to objection 2 are combined then it is possible to comprehend how the methodological distinctions employed by Thomas can be related to the current conversation about the existence of God. This study could benefit from a more profound explanation of the current debate, a detailed explanation of assumptions in Thomas, the theological debate about the relationship between the natural and supernatural, and a more detailed and wider survey of analyzed material. A detailed survey of the history of the thought of Ellis would help to expound on the value of her work in relation to the work of other recent philosophers, such as some of those mentioned in passing in the footnotes. While Ellis relies on the work of some theologians, she does not reference Thomas directly. There could be many reasons for this. It would be interesting to see if the methodological similarities between Thomas and Ellis could result in a direct engagement between Thomas and Ellis, between Thomas and the current debate as articulated by Ellis, and between Thomas and the current debate of which Ellis is only one voice. That being said, this paper highlights the methodological subtleties in the thought of Thomas which are intellectually respectful enough to be introduced into the current conversation on the existence of God.