Hostname: page-component-7bb8b95d7b-dtkg6 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-09-18T14:06:42.425Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Anti‐Foundationalism and Radical Orthodoxy

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2024

Extract

It has often been claimed in the history of philosophy that great thinkers have been badly served by their disciples. Plato’s genuine doctrines don’t resemble the historical construction known as “Platonism”, Aquinas is a more subtle and rigorous thinker than the Thomists, Hume more interesting than the positivists and so on. This claim is cuirendy deployed for certain thinkers who collectively bear the signifier “Postmodern”. It’s held that Derrida, Foucault, Deleuze et al., are more subtle, deep and dialectically agile than their disciples. In particular, those who regard these thinkers as philosophers maintain that the use to which they are put in other disciplines—literary theory, cultural studies, sociology, and so on, fails to convey the depth of the echt thinker.

Be that as it may, it is true that philosophical ideas percolate into other disciplines and have profound general cultural impact, and this is especially true of the so-called postmodern ideas. Theologians in particular have responded with a certain degree of alacrity to the postmodern clarion (probably because modernism proved barren ground for most of them). The kind of views articulated in theology serve also as a model of the way postmodernist views have been used in general in the humanities and social sciences. It’s not unusual for theologians to latch onto the latest philosophical fashion and use it with skill and ingenuity. The medieval theologians of Paris reacted to Aristotle and developed some of the most enduring intellectual works of the western tradition. The Cartesian revolution led to sustained theological reflection—a position still appearing as a bogey for novice theologians to sharpen their dialectical teeth on, or for more senior ones to dramatically unmask in their opponents.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © 2000 Provincial Council of the English Province of the Order of Preachers

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 The group produced a collection of essays under the title Radical Orthodoxy London: Routledge, 1998Google Scholar. I won't deal with that material in this paper. I discuss it in a review in Religious Studies (January 2000).

2 New Blackfriars Vol.79, no.931, Sept. 98, p. 393.

3 ibid. p.395.

4 Problems in the Philosophy of Religion, Hewitt, H. (ed.) Macmillan, 1990 p. 183Google Scholar.

5 Theology and Contemporary Critical Theory, Macmillan, 1996, p. 25Google Scholar.

6 Radicals and the Future of the Church, SCM Press, 1989 p. 43Google Scholar.

7 ibid. p. 39.

8 See The Raft and the Pyramid: coherence versus foundations in the theory of knowledge”, in Sosa, E., Knowledge in Perspective, Cambridge University Press, 1991CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

9 See for example Writing and Difference Routledge, 1978, p. 151152Google Scholar.

10 See Principles of Human Knowledge, section 8.

11 Radicals and the Future of the Church, SCM Press, 1989, p. 37Google Scholar.

12 Theology and Social Theory, Blackwell, 1990, p. 343Google Scholar.

13 The Logical of Scientific Discovery, section 25.

14 See his The Structure of Empirical Knowledge, Cambridge, 1985Google Scholar.

15 See her Evidence and Inquiry, Blackwell, 1993Google Scholar.

16 For example the indefatigable work of Michael Devitt who carefully responds to various kinds of anti‐realism. See his Realism and Truth, 2nd edn, Princeton, 1997Google Scholar.

17 See Hyman ibid. p. 402.

18 Milbank ibid. p.330.

19 Hyman ibid. p. 400

20 Hyman ibid. p. 392

21 “On the very idea of a conceptual scheme” in Inquiries into Truth and Interpretation, Oxford, 1984Google Scholar.

22 See Word and Object, MIT Press, 1960, p. 59Google Scholar

23 Milbank ibid. p. 342.

24 Milbank ibid. p. 343 my italics.

25 Aristotle Metaphysics 1006a12–15.