Hostname: page-component-55f67697df-xlmdk Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-05-11T01:21:23.981Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Metaphysical Foundations for Natural Law

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2024

Owen Anderson*
Affiliation:
Arizona State University
*
Tempe, AZ 85287, Email: [email protected]

Abstract

Image of the first page of this content. For PDF version, please use the ‘Save PDF’ preceeding this image.'
Type
Original Articles
Copyright
© The Author 2006. Journal compilation © The Dominican Council/Blackwell Publishing Ltd 2006, 9600 Garsington Road, Oxford OX4 2DQ, UK and 350 Main Street, Malden, MA 02148, USA

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Article purchase

Temporarily unavailable

References

1 Natural Law and Human Nature: The Teaching Company. 2002Google Scholar.

2 This paper will use the term “eternal” to refer to that which is self-existent as opposed to dependent on another for existence. The eternal therefore has no beginning.

3 Copleston, Frederick. A History of Philosophy. Volume 1: Greece and Rome. Search Press, London. 1946: 323Google Scholar.

4 “With what category of being, then, is metaphysics especially concerned? With that of substance, which is primary, since all things are either substances or affections of substances. But there are or may be different kinds of substances, and with which kind does first philosophy or metaphysics deal? Aristotle answers that, if there is an unchangeable substance, then metaphysics studies unchangeable substance, since it is concerned with being qua being, and the true nature of being is shown in that which is unchangeable and self-existent, rather than in that which is subject to change.” Copleston, Vol 1: 291.

5 White, Michael. “The Problem of Aristotle's Nous Poietikos” Forthcoming in The Review of Metaphysics. 3.

6 Aristotle, . Nicomachean Ethics. Trans. Ross, W.D.. Encyclopedia Britannica, Inc. Chicago: 1952. 343Google Scholar.

7 Aristotle, . Metaphysics. Trans. Ross, W.D.. Encyclopedia Britannica, Inc. Chicago: 1952. 576CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

8 Metaphysics. 576.

9 Schaeffer, Francis A. The Complete Works of Francis A. Schaeffer: A Christian View of Philosophy and Culture.“Escape From Reason”. Crossway Books, Wheaton: 1982. 209.Google Scholar

10 Copleston. Vol 2: 399.

11 Ibid., Vol 2. 428.

12 Summa Theologica. Part 1 of the Second Part Q 109. A. 4.

13 Ibid., Vol 2. 366.

14 Copleston. Vol 1. 317.

15 Ibid., 315.

16 Summa Theologica. Part 1 of Second Part Q. 94. A. 4.

17 Ibid., Q. 95. A 2.

18 Ibid., Q. 96. A 1.

19 Ibid., Q. 109. A 2. Aquinas also asserts that without grace man cannot fulfil the law (Part 1 of Second Part Q. 109. A 4).

20 Copleston, Vol 1. 315.

21 Metaphysics. 599.

22 Copleston. Vol 2. 349.