Hostname: page-component-7bb8b95d7b-pwrkn Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-10-02T12:55:35.402Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Effort and Grace: On the Spiritual Exercise of Philosophy by Simone Kotva, Bloomsbury, London, 2020, pp. xv + 226, £80.00, hbk

Review products

Effort and Grace: On the Spiritual Exercise of Philosophy by Simone Kotva, Bloomsbury, London, 2020, pp. xv + 226, £80.00, hbk

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2024

Oliver James Keenan OP*
Affiliation:
Blackfriars, Oxford
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Type
Reviews
Copyright
Copyright © 2021 Provincial Council of the English Province of the Order of Preachers

Those convinced of the auto-anaethesia of the late modern subject have often prescribed therapeutics of attentiveness: to riff as anti-mystical a thinker as Richard Rorty, attending to the contingency of our final vocabularies unmasks economies of power concealed behind concepts, bringing us to see something that is, perhaps, much too simple to say. Yet as anyone who has attempted Husserlian epoché (or vipassanā-śamatha, for that matter) can attest, ‘simply perceiving’ is a rather difficult business. However the state of attentiveness is described using motifs of receptivity (tranquillity, theoria, contemplatio, detachment, etc.), such passivity can only be preserved through the disciplined practice of an intense form of intellectual activity, which it is the work of philosophy to safeguard and cultivate. It is this paradox—never finally resolved—that Kotva's extraordinary work interrogates, finding, in a way simultaneously reminiscent of Blondel's analysis of action and Pierre Hadot's account of philosophy as a way of life, that effort and grace exist in a kind of perichoretic fusion, and that this immanent dynamic captures the essentially asymptotic character of philosophy (even whilst it is the infinitely receding horizon of a world that vanishes into God that gives rise to this dynamic itself).

Among the most salutary features of Kotva's account of philosophy as a spiritual exercise is its (sadly necessary) apologetic for introspection: a renewal of a metaphysics of the absolute can emerge from a disciplined cultivation of interiority (as Janicaud indicated). Those schooled in the anti-Cartesian theology of the twentieth century might well baulk at this, having often perceived the latent heresy of modernity to be Gnosticism, with its dualistic degradation of bodily goodness and identification of the ‘true self’ with the thinking ‘I’ of privileged interiority. Yet, as Kotva shows (complementing John Macmurray on this point), introspection is itself a bodily action (with ‘bodily’ and ‘action’ being necessarily stressed with equal vigour). Omnipresent in Kotva's analysis is Stoicism and the Stoic revival: evidently influenced by Christopher Brooke's magnificent Philosophic Pride, there are hints that the heart of Kotva's implicit genealogy of modernity is not so much resurgent Manichaeism as an inauthentic, secularised and secularising, Stoicism. Her prescription is, then, not an excision but an authentication and intensification, both of the Stoic and of the introspective, such that Kotva's authentic Stoicism is, in fact, Christianity. Given Augustine's notoriously complicated relationship to his Stoic patrimony (and its incomplete baptism in his thought), this impulse has profound implications for Western theology more generally; perhaps it is the unsubdued Stoical element that prevents an Augustinian synthesis from regressing into systematicity. Nonetheless, the basically Augustinian character of the introspective discipline that Kotva thematises is clear (finding Weil to have integrated Augustinian anthropology and French spiritualism in her account of attentiveness as ‘negative effort’): affirming action need in no way court Pelagianism.

Kotva's work operates on a number of levels, achieving a rare combination of vision in her programmatic proposal concerning the nature of philosophy with the detail-focussed character of her sustained and intense exegesis of a particular corpus of texts (hitherto rather neglected by Anglophone theologians). The arc of the book moves towards an account of Simone Weil's encounter with the paradox of attention, establishing Weil as a crucial figure in the modern reception philosophy as a spiritual discipline, in a way that has not yet been adequately recognised. To achieve this end, Kotva provides, almost en passant, the most compelling interpretation of French Spiritualism yet offered in the English language. Kotva's Weil is situated within the historical milieu of late French Spiritualism (mediated by her teacher Alain), at the site of a conflict (largely now forgotten) between Bergsonian revivalists and the emergence of new phenomenologies. Embedding Weil within the particularities of this historical horizon allows Kotva to trace with acute insight the complex relationship of Weil's thought to her predecessors and contemporaries, thereby allowing Kotva to unfold Weil's unique contribution with fresh clarity and power. Weil's ‘negative effort’ qualifies Bergson's valorisation of action, intensifies Ravaisson's destabilisation of effort, moderates Maine de Biran's quest for self-knowledge, integrates the Stoicism of ‘Alain’ with a non-identical repetition of Biran's effort-grace equivocation, all within the long shadow cast by Fénelon's raids on both Augustine and Descartes (as for the latter, Kotva avoids convenient stereotypes and instead channels something close to Jean-Luc Marion's reading of Descartes's passive thought). Crucial to this reading of Weil is the willingness to conceive of the possibility of a philosophical mystic (even if not a mystical philosophy?), influenced by John of the Cross and (in a more latent form) Fénelon. But what relationship does Weil's ‘negative effort’ have to the ‘negative capability’ of Keats (and, for that matter, W. R. Bion)? Kotva-Weil reflect not so much on the (in)capacities of the subject as on the identity of the grace-effort paradox with the spiritual life itself, and thus ‘negative effort’ is performed by the dance of both subject and object in synergy.

Effort and Grace will inevitably invite comparison with Pierre Hadot's Philosophy as a Way of Life, and such a comparison would certainly not be sterile. Nonetheless, those who read Kotva as contributing to a discourse generated by Hadot's work will do the book a fairly serious disservice. As Kotva indicates, Weil and Hadot emerge from the same generative moment of French intellectual history: Kotva's excavation of the voice of Weil, Hadot's elder peer, presents an alternative trajectory to that offered by Hadot. Hadot's study of Stoicism by way of Ignatian spirituality differs from Weil's Carmelite-influenced Augustinianism, by prioritising ‘tension’ over ‘relaxation’. If Weil can be said to intensify Ravaisson by a critical qualification of Bergsonianism, Hadot's approach is inverted, intensifying Bergson's prioritisation of effort whilst downplaying the Epicurean elements of Ravaisson's repose.

The alternative Kotva-Weil trajectory is likely to have theological resonances absent from (or perhaps concealed by) Hadot. Nonetheless, the genealogical strategy that is essential to the establishment of this trajectory ultimately obscures some of Kotva's own programmatic vision, where the enclosure of effort by grace renders philosophy and theology coextensive. The reader has to attend to the skill of Kotva's interpretation, harvesting her own insights from the use she makes of others. Relatively little is made of Ravaisson's Christocentrism, for instance, nor is Weil's emphasis on natural and intuitive action interrogated in terms of connaturality (or virtue more generally, perhaps with the help of Ravaisson and Biran on intellectual habits). Consequently, the conclusion is largely suggestive and slips the bonds of the earlier chapters, particularly as it reaches towards Sallie McFague and theologies of the environment. Yet these are quibbles in a book that exercises such control over an enormously wide-range of material.

The endorsements of Kotva's book are laudatory but not hyperbolic: ‘brilliant […] compelling’ (Sherman); ‘pioneering’ (Pickstock); ‘excellent and absorbing’ (Milbank). Perhaps the greatest compliment is to raise a question that would be unfair to many lesser works: whither ontology? On the one hand, it is the object of attention—God ‘receding endlessly from comprehension’ (p.173)—that determines the effort-grace paradox, but elsewhere a theologised subject whose effort, bracketed by grace on both sides, dominates. Indeed, the flux of paradox seems to be a structuring principle of Kotva's ontology, but it is unclear whether this indicates openness to process thought or a hint towards Maximus the Confessor's ontology of repose, systolē and diastolē. The latter is suggested by the approval of phusike theoria (p.175, suggesting an openness to Christos Yannaras's extended apophaticism) but in the end the former seems most likely, as Kotva hints towards a reconfiguration of divine simplicity: ‘it is no longer possible to leave weakness and vulnerability out of a description of God’ (p.130). But without the absoluteness of infinite simplicity, can paradox overcome nihilism? To this end, Christ appears in Kotva's index, but God is absent. Or perhaps God is the index?