Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-mkpzs Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-23T08:38:53.934Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The order-K-ification monads

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  21 December 2023

Huijun Hou
Affiliation:
School of Mathematics, Hunan University, Changsha, Hunan, China
Hualin Miao
Affiliation:
School of Mathematics, Hunan University, Changsha, Hunan, China
Qingguo Li*
Affiliation:
School of Mathematics, Hunan University, Changsha, Hunan, China
*
Corresponding author: Qingguo Li; Email: [email protected]
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Monads prove to be useful mathematical tools in theoretical computer science, notably in denoting different effects of programming languages. In this paper, we investigate a type of monads which arise naturally from Keimel and Lawson’s $\mathbf{K}$-ification.

A subcategory of $\mathbf{TOP}_{\mathbf{0}}$ is called of type $\mathrm{K}^{*}$ if it consists of monotone convergence spaces and is of type $\mathrm K$ in the sense of Keimel and Lawson. Each such category induces a canonical monad $\mathcal K$ on the category $\mathbf{DCPO}$ of dcpos and Scott-continuous maps, which is called the order-$\mathbf{K}$-ification monad in this paper. First, for each category of type $\mathrm{K}^{*}$, we characterize the algebras of the corresponding monad $\mathcal K$ as k-complete posets and algebraic homomorphisms as k-continuous maps, from which we obtain that the order-$\mathbf{K}$-ification monad gives the free k-complete poset construction over the category $\mathbf{POS}_{\mathbf{d}}$ of posets and Scott-continuous maps. In addition, we show that all k-complete posets and Scott-continuous maps form a Cartesian closed category. Moreover, we consider the strongness of the order-K-ification monad and conclude with the fact that each order-K-ification monad is always commutative.

Type
Paper
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2023. Published by Cambridge University Press

1. Introduction

Non-determinism is an important semantic concept in Theoretical Computer Science and domain theory. This concept offers new insights in designing more powerful programming languages. Pioneering mathematical, in particular, domain-theoretic models considered for non-determinism were due to Plotkin and Smyth in Plotkin (Reference Plotkin1976) and Smyth (Reference Smyth1976). In order to capture the possibilities of multiple outputs in non-deterministic computations, concrete powerdomains have been introduced by Hennessy and Plotkin in (1979), and each of these constructions gives rise to a monad. Nowadays, it has been routine to use monads to give denotational semantics to computational effects like non-determinism, and different powerdomain constructions have been proposed, for example, the Hoare, Plotkin, Smyth and Probabilistic powerdomain constructions in domain theory, to name a few.

Generalizing Hennessy and Plotkin’s work, in Schalk (Reference Schalk1993), Andrea Schalk studied the Hoare power construction on the category $\mathbf{DCPO}$ of all dcpos and Scott-continuous maps, a general and versatile setting for denotational semantics. She proved that for a dcpo D, the Hoare powerdomain $\mathcal H(D)$ of D, comprised of all Scott closed subsets of D under set inclusion, is the free inflationary semilattice of D and useful in modeling the so-called angelic non-determinism.

The Hoare powerdomain construction itself, seemingly being order-theoretic, can be factored through its topological counterpart $\mathcal H_t$ . For a topological space X, $\mathcal H_t(X)$ is the set of all closed subsets of X equipped with the lower Vietoris topology. The construction $\mathcal H_t$ is restricted to an endofunctor on the category $\mathbf{MCS}$ of monotone convergence spaces, and then, $\mathcal H$ can be realized as the composite $\Omega \circ \mathcal H_t \circ \Sigma$ , where $\Sigma$ assigns to each dcpo L the topological space $(L, \sigma (L))$ ( $\sigma (L)$ is the Scott topology on L), and $\Omega$ assigns to each monotone convergence space X the dcpo $(X, \leq)$ with $\leq$ being the specialization order on X. Both $\Sigma$ and $\Omega$ leave morphisms intact. It is easy to see that $\Sigma$ is left adjoint to $\Omega$ .

It is interesting to see that many other constructions in domain theory actually arise in a similar fashion. For example, replacing $\mathcal H_t$ by the sobrification monad $\mathcal S_t$ on $\mathbf{MCS}$ (this makes sense as all sober spaces are monotone convergence spaces), the composite $\Omega \circ \mathcal S_t \circ \Sigma$ gives the so-called order-sobrification monad $\mathcal S$ on $\mathbf{DCPO}$ (Ho et al. Reference Ho, Goubault-Larrecq, Jung and Xi2018). While $\mathcal H$ is useful in denotational semantics, $\mathcal S$ is employed heavily in giving a satisfactory answer to the Ho-Zhao problem by Ho et al. (Reference Ho, Goubault-Larrecq, Jung and Xi2018). That useful application also motivated Jia to systematically investigate the order-sobrification monad $\mathcal S$ in Jia (Reference Jia2020).

Canonical categorical reasoning tells us that for each monad $\mathcal T$ on $\mathbf{MCS}$ , the composite $\Omega \circ \mathcal T \circ \Sigma$ actually gives rise to a monad on the category $\mathbf{DCPO}$ . In this paper, we mainly investigate the monads of this specific form, with $\mathcal T$ a reflector on the category $\mathbf{MCS}$ . As the sobrification functor is a reflector on $\mathbf{MCS}$ , the order-sobrification monad considered in Ho et al. (Reference Ho, Goubault-Larrecq, Jung and Xi2018) and Jia (Reference Jia2020) will be subsumed under our work. Indeed, inspired by the reflectivity of SOB in $\mathbf{TOP}_{\mathbf{0}}$ , reflectors on $\mathbf{TOP}_{\mathbf{0}}$ or equivalently, reflective subcategories of $T_0$ topological spaces have been studied extensively in domain theory. In particular, it was Keimel and Lawson who first tried to find a class of reflective subcategories in a unified form. They identified in Keimel and Lawson (Reference Keimel and Lawson2009) the following four properties and proved that each subcategory $\mathbf K$ of $\mathbf{TOP}_{\mathbf{0}}$ satisfying them is actually reflective (the objects of $\mathbf K$ are called $\mathbf{K}$ -spaces).

( $K_1$ ) Homeomorphic copies of $\mathbf{K}$ -spaces are $\mathbf{K}$ -spaces.

( $K_2$ ) All sober spaces are $\mathbf{K}$ -spaces.

( $K_3$ ) In a sober space S, the intersection of any family of $\mathbf{K}$ -subspaces is a $\mathbf{K}$ -space.

( $K_4$ ) Continuous maps $f: S\rightarrow T$ between sober spaces S and T are $\mathbf{K}$ -continuous, that is, for every $\mathbf{K}$ -subspace K of T, the inverse image $f^{-1}(K)$ is a $\mathbf{K}$ -subspace of S.

Later, Xu focused on the subcategories satisfying $(K_2)$ , proposed the concept of adequateness, and proved that each adequate category $\mathbf K$ is reflective in $\mathbf{TOP}_{\mathbf{0}}$ (Xu Reference Xu2020). More recently, Ershov raised the concept of wide categories and defined $\mathbf K$ -completions in them, in which he also introduced the notion of ample $\mathbf K$ -precompletion. He proved that each wide category admitting an ample $\mathbf K$ -precompletion is reflective in $\mathbf{Top}_{\mathbf{0}}$ (Ershov Reference Ershov2022). Then, the existence of D-completions (Ershov Reference Ershov1999; Wyler Reference Wyler1979), $\mathbf D_b$ -completions (Keimel and Lawson Reference Keimel and Lawson2009), and WF-completions (Liu et al. Reference Liu, Li and Wu2020; Wu et al. Reference Wu, Xi, Xu and Zhao2020) can be realized as corollaries to the aforementioned results. Actually, we will see that the properties of being wide and of possessing an ample $\mathbf K$ -precompletion are not only sufficient conditions for a full subcategory $\mathbf K$ to be reflective but also the necessary ones. Indeed, different completions considered by Keimel and Lawson (Reference Keimel and Lawson2009), Xu (Reference Xu2020) and Ershov (Reference Ershov2022) are equivalent.

Given a reflective subcategory $\mathbf K$ of $\mathbf{TOP}_{\mathbf{0}}$ , the corresponding reflector $\mathcal K_t$ , sending each $T_0$ topological space X to its $\mathbf{K}$ -ification (many authors also call it the $\mathbf{K}$ -space completion), is a monad on $\mathbf{TOP}_{\mathbf{0}}$ (modulo post-composing with the obvious inclusion functor). The $\mathbf{K}$ -ification proves to be useful in denotational semantics, for example, Jia, Lindenhovius, Mislove, and Zamdzhiev employed $\mathbf{K}$ -ifications to construct commutative probabilistic monads for probabilistic programming languages, solving a long-standing open problem in denotational semantics (Jia et al. 2021).

Starting with a monotone convergence space, however, it is not always the case that $\mathcal K_t$ would return a monotone convergence space (see Xu et al. Reference Xu, Shen, Xi and Zhao2020 for example); hence, $\mathcal K_t$ cannot be restricted on $\mathbf{MCS}$ in general, nor $\Omega \circ \mathcal K_t \circ \Sigma$ can be well-defined. To avoid that, we consider full subcategories satisfying $(K_1), (K_2)$ and Xu’s adequateness that are also contained in MCS to ensure that the resulting reflectors return monotone convergence spaces, and call such categories of type $\mathrm K^*$ . Now $\mathcal K_t$ induces a monad $\mathcal K$ on $\mathbf {DCPO}$ , which is called order- $\mathbf K$ -ification monad. It can also be seen that the monad $\mathcal K$ refines $\mathcal H$ , in the sense that for a dcpo D, $\mathcal K$ actually picks a certain subdcpo of $\mathcal H(D)$ , according to the given category of type $\mathrm K^*$ . Hence, like the Hoare powerdomain monad $\mathcal H$ , monad $\mathcal K$ may also find its uses in semantics.

In this paper, we systematically investigate the order- ${\mathbf K}$ -ification monads induced by categories of type $\mathrm K^*$ . For each category of type $\mathrm K^*$ , we characterize the Eilenberg-Moore algebras of the resulting $\mathcal K$ and the corresponding algebraic homomorphisms, from which we obtain that the Eilenberg-Moore category is precisely $\mathbf{KCPO}$ of k-complete posets and k-continuous maps. In addition, we find that each category $\mathbf{KCPO}_{\sigma}$ consisting of all k-complete posets and Scott-continuous maps is Cartesian closed; thus, it could be a model for the $\lambda$ -calculus. We also verify that $\mathcal{K}$ is always a commutative monad. Hence, each monad $\mathcal K$ in this form on the category of dcpos serves as a $\lambda_c$ -model in the sense of Moggi (Reference Moggi1989). In particular, when the category of type $\mathrm K^*$ is chosen to be $\mathbf{SOB}$ , our order- $\mathbf{SOB}$ -ification monad is exactly the order-sobrification monad $\mathcal{S}$ proposed in Ho et al. (Reference Ho, Goubault-Larrecq, Jung and Xi2018), and all of our results generalize that of Jia in (2020).

2. Preliminaries

Let us introduce the concepts and notions to be used in this paper.

Let P be a poset. A subset A of P is called an upper set (resp., a lower set) if $A = {\uparrow}A$ (resp., $A = {\downarrow}A$ ), where ${\uparrow}A = \{x\in P: x\geq a\ \mathrm{for \ some}\ a\in A\}$ (resp., ${\downarrow}A = \{x\in P: x\leq a\ \mathrm{for \ some}\ a\in A\}$ ). A nonempty subset D of P is said to be directed if for each finite subset $F\subseteq D$ there exists some $d\in D$ such that $F\subseteq {\downarrow}d$ . Then P is directed complete (or a dcpo) if every directed subset D of P has a least upper bound, that is, $\sup D$ exists in P. Let $\sigma(P)$ denote the Scott topology on P, where every U in $\sigma(P)$ , called Scott open, satisfies $U = {\uparrow}U$ and for any directed subset D for which supD exists, supD $\in U$ implies $D\cap U \neq \emptyset$ . Correspondingly, $A\subseteq P$ is Scott closed if A = $\downarrow$ A and for any directed subset D of P contained in A, supD $\in A$ when $\sup D$ exists. Until it is otherwise stated, we always equip posets with the Scott topology, and $cl_{\sigma}(A)$ or $\overline A$ is used to denote the closure of $A\subseteq P$ with respect to the Scott topology.

For a $T_{0}$ topological space X, the partial order $\leq$ $_{X}$ , defined by $x\leq y$ iff x is contained in the closure of y, is called the specialization order. We have that for any $x\in X$ , $\downarrow$ x = $cl(\{x\})$ and a continuous map f between two $T_{0}$ spaces is always order-preserving. X is called a monotone convergence space (or a d-space) if every subset D directed relative to the specialization order has a supremum, and the relation $\sup D\in U$ for any open set U of X implies $D\cap U \neq \emptyset$ . Let C(X) denote the set of all closed subsets of X. The lower Vietoris topology on C(X) is the topology generated by $\{\lozenge U: U\in \mathcal{O}(X)\}$ as a subbase, where $\lozenge U = \{A\in C(X): A\cap U\neq \emptyset\}$ , and the resulting space denoted by $\mathcal H_t(X)$ is called the Hoare power space, here t in the subscript refers to the fact that the construction acts on topological spaces. $A\in C(X)$ is called irreducible if for any $B, C\in C(X)$ , $A\subseteq B\cup C$ implies that $A\subseteq B$ or $A\subseteq C$ . X is called sober if every nonempty irreducible closed set is the closure of a point. From Gierz et al. (Reference Gierz, Hofmann, Keimel, Lawson, Mislove and Scott2003, Exercise V-4.9) we know that there is a sobrification $(\mathbb S(X), s_X)$ for each $T_0$ space X, where the standard construction for the sobrification is to set

\begin{align*} \mathbb S(X):= \{A\subseteq X: A\ \mathrm{is\ closed\ and\ irreducible}\} \end{align*}

topologized by open sets $U^{s} := \{A\in \mathbb S(X): A\cap U\neq\emptyset\}$ for each open subset U of X and $s_X$ is a topological embedding from X to $\mathbb S(X)$ defined by $s_X(x) = cl(\{x\})$ for each $x\in X$ . We call it standard sobrification.

For a general full subcategory $\mathbf K$ of a category $\mathbf{C}$ , $\mathbf K$ is called reflective if the inclusion functor has a left adjoint, which is then called a reflector and exhibited in the following

Definition 2.1. (Keimel and Lawson Reference Keimel and Lawson2009) A morphism $\mu: C\rightarrow \widetilde{C}$ of an object C in $\mathbf C$ to an object $\widetilde{C}$ is called a universal $\mathbf K$ -ification if it satisfies the following universal property:

For every object K in $\mathbf K$ and every map $f: C\rightarrow K$ in $\mathbf C$ , there is a unique morphism $\tilde{f}: \widetilde{C}\rightarrow K$ in $\mathbf K$ such that $\tilde{f}\circ\mu = f$ :

We call $\widetilde{C}$ together with the universal $\mathbf K$ -ification $\mu$ a $\mathbf K$ -ification of C. It was Keimel and Lawson who first showed that a full subcategory $\mathbf K$ is reflective in $\mathbf{TOP}_{\mathbf{0}}$ if it satisfies $(K_1)$ to $(K_4)$ mentioned in the Introduction. In this sense of universal $\mathbf K$ -ifications, Xu in (2020) provided another approach to constructing $\mathbf K$ -ifications of $T_0$ spaces.

Definition 2.2 (Xu Reference Xu2020). Fix a subcategory $\mathbf K$ of $\mathbf{TOP}_{\mathbf{0}}$ that satisfies $(K_2)$ . A subset A of a $T_{0}$ space X is called a $\mathbf{K}$ -set, provided for any continuous map $f: X\rightarrow Y$ to a $\mathbf{K}$ -space Y (i.e., Y is an object in $\mathbf K$ ), there exists a unique $y_{A}\in Y$ such that cl(f(A))= $cl(\{y_{A}\})$ . Denote by $\mathbf{K}(X)$ the set of all closed $\mathbf{K}$ -sets of X.

In Xu (Reference Xu2020), Xu called a full subcategory $\mathbf K$ of $\mathbf{TOP}_{\mathbf{0}}$ adequate if for any $T_{0}$ space X, $\mathcal{K}(X)$ , the space obtained by endowing $\mathbf{K}(X)$ with the lower Vietoris topology, is a $\mathbf{K}$ -space. He proved that when $\mathbf K$ satisfies $(K_2)$ and is adequate, the pair $\langle \mathcal{K}(X), \zeta_{X} \rangle$ , where $\zeta_{X}: X\rightarrow \mathcal K(X): x\mapsto cl(\{x\})$ , is a $\mathbf{K}$ -ification of X.

Recently, Ershov called a full subcategory $\mathbf K$ of $\mathbf{TOP}_{\mathbf{0}}$ wide if for any $T_0$ space X there exists an extension $Y\geq X$ such that $Y\in \mathbf K$ . For a wide category $\mathbf K$ , he endowed new definitions for $\mathbf K$ -subspaces and $\mathbf K$ -completions and used them to offer sufficient conditions for the existence of $\mathbf K$ -ification of an arbitrary $T_0$ space (Ershov Reference Ershov2022).

Definition 2.3 (Ershov Reference Ershov2022). Let $\mathbf K$ be a wide subcategory of $\mathbf{TOP}_{\mathbf{0}}$ . We say that a continuous map $f: X\rightarrow Y$ between two $T_0$ spaces is $\mathbf K$ -precomplete if for the inclusion functor $i: \mathbf K\hookrightarrow \mathbf{Top}_{\mathbf{0}}$ , the natural transformation $({-}) \circ f : \mathbf{Top}_{\mathbf{0}} (Y, i({-})) \rightarrow \mathbf{Top}_{\mathbf{0}} (X, i({-}))$ is invertible.

Definition 2.4 (Ershov Reference Ershov2022). Let $\mathbf K$ be a wide category. An arbitrary subspace $Z\leq \mathbb S(X)$ containing X, for which the natural embedding $s_X: X\rightarrow Z$ is $\mathbf K$ -precomplete, is called a $\mathbf K$ -subspace for X.

Ershov denoted by $X^{\mathbf K}$ the greatest $\mathbf K$ -subspace for X, whose existence is guaranteed by Ershov (Reference Ershov2022, Theorem 2.2). In addition, he called $X^{\mathbf K}$ a $\mathbf K$ -completion of a $T_0$ space X if $X^{\mathbf K}\in \mathbf K$ .

Definition 2.5. (Ershov Reference Ershov2022) Let $\mathbf K$ be a wide category. A functor $F: \mathbf{TOP}_{\mathbf{0}}\rightarrow \mathbf{TOP}_{\mathbf{0}}$ together with a natural transformation $\eta: Id\rightarrow F$ is called a $\mathbf K$ -precompletion if the map $\eta_X: X\rightarrow F(X)$ is $\mathbf K$ -precomplete for any $T_0$ space X.

A $\mathbf K$ -precompletion $(F, \eta)$ is referred to as ample if, for any $T_0$ space X, the fact that $\eta_X: X\rightarrow F(X)$ is an identity map implies the inclusion $X\in \mathbf K$ .

Ershov has proved that for a wide category $\mathbf K$ , the existence of an ample $\mathbf K$ -precompletion guarantees the existence of the $\mathbf K$ -completion of an arbitrary $T_0$ space X (Ershov Reference Ershov2022, Theorem 4.3), in other words, he provided a sufficient condition to make the category $\mathbf K$ reflective in $\mathbf{TOP}_{\mathbf{0}}$ . Next we will show that this condition is also necessary.

Proposition 2.6. Let $\mathbf K$ be a wide category. Then, the $\mathbf K$ -completion exists for each $T_0$ space X if and only if there is an ample $\mathbf K$ -precompletion $(F, \eta)$ .

Proof. “If” is clear from Ershov (Reference Ershov2022, Theorem 4.3). Now assume that the $\mathbf K$ -completion exists for each $T_0$ space X, i.e., $X^{\mathbf K}\in \mathbf K$ . Define $F: \mathbf{TOP}_{\mathbf{0}}\rightarrow \mathbf{TOP}_{\mathbf{0}}$ as the form of Ershov (Reference Ershov2022, Theorem 3.7) and $\eta_X: X\rightarrow F(X) = X^{\mathbf K}$ as $s_X$ . Since $X^{\mathbf K}$ is a $\mathbf K$ -subspace of X, $s_X$ is $\mathbf K$ -precomplete, so is $\eta_X$ . If $\eta_X$ is an identity map, i.e., $X\cong X^{\mathbf K}$ , then from Ershov (Reference Ershov2022, Theorem 3.8), we know the existence of $\mathbf K$ -completions indicates that $(K_1)$ is satisfied. So $X^{\mathbf K}\in \mathbf K$ implies $X\in \mathbf K$ . Hence, $(F, \eta)$ is an ample $\mathbf K$ -precompletion.

Lemma 2.7 (Xu Reference Xu2020). Let $\mathbf{K}$ be a subcategory of $\mathbf{TOP}_{\mathbf{0}}$ that satisfies $(K_1)$ and $(K_2)$ . If it is adequate, then the following conditions are equivalent for each $T_{0}$ space X:

  1. (1) X is a $\mathbf{K}$ -space.

  2. (2) $\mathbf{K}(X)$ = $\{{\downarrow}x: x\in X\}$ , that is, for each $A\in\mathbf{K}(X)$ , there exists an $x\in X$ such that A = $cl(\{x\})$ .

Lemma 2.8. Let Y be a $T_{0}$ space and X a subspace of Y. If $A\subseteq X$ , then $cl_{Y}(cl_{X}(A)) = cl_{Y}(A)$ .

Proof. It is clear that $cl_{X}(A) = cl_{Y}(A)$ for any $A\subseteq X$ . So $cl_{Y}(cl_{X}(A)) = cl_{Y}(A)$ .

Proposition 2.9. If $\mathbf K$ is a subcategory of $\mathbf{TOP}_{\mathbf{0}}$ satisfying the property $(K_{2})$ , then it satisfies properties $(K_{1})$ to $(K_{4})$ if and only if it is closed and adequate.

Proof. Theorem 5.17 in Xu (Reference Xu2020) told us each subcategory satisfying $(K_{1})$ to $(K_{4})$ is adequate. Thus, we just need to prove the reverse; that is, $\mathbf K$ satisfies ( $K_{3}$ ) and ( $K_{4}$ ) if it is closed and adequate.

For ( $K_{3}$ ), let $\{X_{i}: i\in I\}$ be a family of $\mathbf{K}$ -subspaces of S, where $\mathbf K$ -subspaces mentioned in $(K_3)$ are subspaces of S that are $\mathbf K$ -spaces in the relative topology. Suppose $A\subseteq\bigcap_{i\in I}X_{i}$ is a $\mathbf{K}$ -set. Then, A is a $\mathbf{K}$ -set of S, which implies that $cl_{S}(A) = cl_{S}(\{a\})$ for some $a\in S$ since the sober space S is a $\mathbf{K}$ -space. Meanwhile, A is also a $\mathbf{K}$ -set of every $\mathbf{K}$ -space $X_{i}$ ; thus, there is an $a_{i}\in X_{i}$ such that $cl_{X_{i}}(A) = cl_{X_{i}}(\{a_{i}\})$ . By Lemma 2.8, we have $cl_{S}(cl_{X_{i}}(A)) = cl_{S}(A)$ , which means $cl_{S}(cl_{X_{i}}(\{a_{i}\})) = cl_{S}(\{a\})$ . By the fact that $cl_{S}(cl_{X_{i}}(\{a_{i}\})) = cl_{S}(\{a_{i}\})$ , we have $cl_{S}(\{a_{i}\}) = cl_{S}(\{a\})$ . Thus, $a_{i} = a$ and $a\in \bigcap_{i\in I}X_{i}$ . Therefore, $cl_{\bigcap_{i\in I}X_{i}}(A) = cl_{\bigcap_{i\in I}X_{i}}(\{a\})$ . So relying on the adequateness, by Lemma 2.7, we have that ${\bigcap_{i\in I}X_{i}}$ is a $\mathbf{K}$ -space.

For ( $K_{4}$ ), let S, T be sober spaces and $f: S\rightarrow T$ a continuous map. Assume that X is a $\mathbf{K}$ -subspace of T. For any $\mathbf{K}$ -set $A\subseteq f^{-1}(X)$ , A is also a $\mathbf{K}$ -set of S. Then, there is an $a\in S$ such that $cl_{S}(A) = cl_{S}(\{a\})$ . Besides, by the continuity of f, we know $f(A)\subseteq X$ is a $\mathbf{K}$ -set of T and one can verify that f(A) is also a $\mathbf{K}$ -set of X. Thus there are two points $a_{1}\in X$ and $a_{2}\in T$ such that $cl_{X}(f(A)) = cl_{X}(\{a_{1}\})$ and $cl_{T}(f(A)) = cl_{T}(\{a_{2}\})$ , respectively. By Lemma 2.8, $cl_{T}(cl_{X}(f(A))) = cl_{T}(f(A))$ , thus $a_{1} = a_{2}$ . Now we have $f(a) = f(\sup_{S} A) = \sup_{T}f(A) = a_{2}$ . As $a_{1} = a_{2}$ and $a_{1}\in X$ , $f(a)\in X$ , that is, $\sup_{S} A = a\in f^{-1}(X)$ . This means $\sup_{f^{-1}(X)}A$ exists and equals to $\sup_{S} A$ . Thus, $cl_{f^{-1}(X)}(A) = cl_{f^{-1}(X)}(\{\sup_{f^{-1}(X)}A \}) = cl_{f^{-1}(X)}(\{\sup_{S}A\}) = cl_{f^{-1}(X)}(\{a\})$ . Therefore, using the adequateness and Lemma 2.7 again, we have that $f^{-1}(X)$ is a $\mathbf{K}$ -subspace of S.

Given that Ershov has shown that a full subcategory $\mathbf K$ of $\mathbf{TOP}_{\mathbf{0}}$ satisfies the properties $(K_1)$ to $(K_4)$ if and only if $\mathbf K$ is wide and $\mathbf K$ -completion exists for each $T_0$ space (see Ershov Reference Ershov2022, Theorem 3.8), then together with Propositions 2.6 and 2.9, we could draw the following conclusion.

Theorem 2.10. Let $\mathbf K$ be a full subcategory of $\mathbf{TOP}_{\mathbf{0}}$ . Then, the following statements are equivalent.

  1. (1) $\mathbf K$ is a wide category and there exists an ample $\mathbf K$ -precompletion $(F, \eta)$ on the category $\mathbf{TOP}_{\mathbf{0}}$ .

  2. (2) $\mathbf K$ satisfies the properties $(K_1)$ - $(K_4)$ .

  3. (3) $\mathbf K$ satisfies the properties $(K_1)$ , $(K_2)$ and is adequate.

It can be seen from the above theorem that the $\mathbf K$ -ifications of a $T_0$ space constructed by Keimel and Lawson, Xu, and Ershov respectively are consistent. In our paper, we will mainly use Xu’s description for $\mathbf K$ -ifications. This is because, when constructing an order- $\mathbf K$ -ification monad on DCPO and further examining its algebras, it benefits us a lot if we know concretely what composes such a completion.

3. Categories of Type $\mathrm K^*$

In what follows, a category of type $\mathrm K$ is defined by satisfying Properties $(K_1)$ , $(K_2)$ mentioned in the Introduction and the adequacy property. Categories of type $\mathrm K$ were initially considered by Keimel and Lawson in (2009), and they are also called K-categories in Jia and Mislove (Reference Jia and Mislove2022).

Definition 3.1. A full subcategory of $\mathbf{TOP}_{\mathbf{0}}$ of type $\mathrm K$ is said to be of type $\mathrm{K}^{*}$ if its objects, called $\mathbf K^*$ -spaces, also satisfy the following property:

( $K_5$ ) All $\mathbf K^*$ -spaces are monotone convergence spaces.

Remark 3.2. Given a category of type $\mathrm K$ , the full subcategory of all monotone convergence $\mathbf K$ -spaces, denoted by $\mathbf K^{*}$ , is of type $\mathrm K^{*}$ . In the following, the category $\mathbf K^{*}$ is always constructed in this way from a category $\mathbf K$ of type $\mathrm K$ .

Example 3.3. SOB and MCS have been shown to be categories of type $\mathrm K^{*}$ in Gierz et al. (Reference Gierz, Hofmann, Keimel, Lawson, Mislove and Scott2003), Keimel and Lawson (Reference Keimel and Lawson2009). Wu et al. proved that WF of all well-filtered spaces and continuous maps satisfies the properties $(K_1)$ to $(K_4)$ and thus a category of type K (Wu et al. Reference Wu, Xi, Xu and Zhao2020). As Xi and Lawson in Xi nad Lawson (2017) illustrated that each well-filtered space is a monotone convergence space, WF is also a category of type $\mathrm K^{*}$ , which lies between SOB and MCS.

The following example distinguishes the category of type $\mathrm{K}^{*}$ from that of type K.

Example 3.4. In Xu et al. (Reference Xu, Shen, Xi and Zhao2020), Xu introduced the $\omega$ -well-filtered spaces and illustrated that an $\omega$ -well-filtered space may not be a monotone convergence space. The reader is referred to Xu et al. (Reference Xu, Shen, Xi and Zhao2020, Example 4.3) for details. It was proved that the category $\omega$ - $\mathbf{WF}$ of all $\omega$ -well-filtered spaces and continuous maps is reflective in $\mathbf{TOP}_{\mathbf{0}}$ , which indicates that $\omega$ - $\mathbf{WF}$ satisfies the properties $(K_1)$ to $(K_4)$ by Shen et al. (Reference Shen, Xi and Zhao2021, Theorem 2.16). So $\omega$ - $\mathbf{WF}$ is of type K, but not of type $\mathrm{K}^{*}$ .

Definition 3.5. Let X be a $T_{0}$ space. $A\subseteq X$ is a $\mathbf{K}^{*}$ -set if for any $\mathbf{K}^{*}$ -space Y and any continuous map $f: X\rightarrow Y$ , there exists a unique element $y_{0}\in Y$ such that cl(f(A)) = $cl(\{y_{0}\})$ .

Let $\mathbf{K}^{*}(X)$ denote the set of all closed $\mathbf{K}^{*}$ -sets of X. Then, A is a $\mathbf{K}^{*}$ -set iff $cl(A)\in \mathbf{K}^{*}(X)$ . In particular, when $\mathbf{K}^{*}$ is SOB or WF, a $\mathbf{K}^{*}$ -set of a $T_{0}$ space X is indeed an irreducible set or a well-filtered determined set defined by Xu in Xu and Zhao (Reference Xu and Zhao2020), respectively. We will use $\mathbf{WF}(X)$ to denote the family consisting of all closed well-filtered determined sets of X.

Lemma 3.6. Let X, Y be $T_{0}$ spaces and $f: X\rightarrow Y$ a continuous map. If $A\subseteq X$ is a $\mathbf{K}^{*}$ -set, then f(A) is a $\mathbf{K}^{*}$ -set of Y.

Proof. The proof is similar to that of Xu (Reference Xu2020, Lemma 3.11).

Definition 3.7 (Zhang and Li Reference Zhang and Li2017). A subset A of a space X is called tapered if for any continuous map $f:X\rightarrow Y$ with Y a monotone convergence space, $\sup f(A)$ always exists in Y.

Lemma 3.8 (Zhang and Li Reference Zhang and Li2017). Let X be a monotone convergence space. If $A\subseteq X$ is tapered and closed, then $A = \ \downarrow\!\!(\bigvee A)$ .

Clearly, each directed subset is tapered, which together with the above lemma guarantees the following result:

Lemma 3.9. Let X be a $T_{0}$ space. Then, the following conditions are equivalent:

  1. (1) X is a monotone convergence space.

  2. (2) For any tapered and closed subset $A\subseteq X$ , $A = cl(\{x_{0}\})$ for some $x_{0}\in X$ .

Lemma 3.10. Let X be a $T_{0}$ space. Then, we have

  1. (1) Every $\mathbf{K}$ -set of X is a $\mathbf{K}^{*}$ -set.

  2. (2) Every tapered set of X is a $\mathbf{K}^{*}$ -set.

Proof. (1): Let Y be a $\mathbf{K}^{*}$ -space and $f: X\rightarrow Y$ a continuous map. By definition of a $\mathbf{K}^{*}$ -space, we know Y is a K-space; thus for any $\mathbf{K}$ -set $A\subseteq X$ , there exists a unique element y such that cl(f(A)) = $cl(\{y\})$ by Lemma 2.7. It follows that A is a $\mathbf{K}^{*}$ -set.

(2): Similarly, we can prove that each tapered set is also a $\mathbf{K}^{*}$ -set by Lemma 3.9.

Lemma 3.11. For a $T_{0}$ space X, the following conditions are equivalent:

  1. (1) X is a $\mathbf{{K}}^{*}$ -space.

  2. (2) For each $\mathbf{K}^{*}$ -set $A\subseteq X$ , there exists an element $a_0$ such that $cl(A) = cl(\{a_0\})$ .

Proof. $(1)\Rightarrow(2)$ : Let $id: X\rightarrow X$ be the identity map. Its continuity makes a fact that there is an element $a_0$ such that cl(A) = $cl(\{a_0\})$ .

$(2)\Rightarrow (1)$ : For any $\mathbf{K}$ -set A of X, by Lemma 3.10, A is a $\mathbf{K}^{*}$ -set, thus cl(A) = $cl(\{a_0\})$ for some $a_0\in A$ by (2). So we conclude that X is a $\mathbf{K}$ -space by Lemma 2.7. Similarly, we could show that X is also a monotone convergence space.

Theorem 3.12. Let X be a $T_{0}$ space. Then, $\mathcal K_{t}(X)$ , i.e., $\mathbf{K}^{*}(X)$ endowed with the lower Vietoris topology is a $\mathbf{K}^{*}$ -space.

Proof. Assume that $\mathcal{A}$ is a closed $\mathbf{K}^{*}$ -set of $\mathbf{K}^{*}(X)$ . We claim that $\bigcup\mathcal{A}$ is a $\mathbf{K}^{*}$ -set of X. Let Y be a $\mathbf{K}^{*}$ -space and $f: X\rightarrow Y$ a continuous map. Then, define a map

\begin{align*} g: \mathbf{K}^{*}(X)\rightarrow \mathbf{K}^{*}(Y): C\mapsto cl(f(C)), \end{align*}

whose rationality is guaranteed by Lemma 3.6. For each open set $\lozenge U$ of $ \mathbf{K}^{*}(Y)$ , where $U\in \mathcal{O}(Y)$ , $g^{-1}(\lozenge U) = \lozenge f^{-1}(U)$ , so g is continuous. Since each $A\in \mathcal{A}$ belongs to $\mathbf{K}^{*}(X)$ , there exists a $y_{A}\in Y$ such that $cl(f(A)) = {\downarrow} y_{A}$ . It follows that $g(\mathcal{A}) = \{{\downarrow} y_{A}: A\in \mathcal{A}\}$ is a $\mathbf{K}^{*}$ -set of $\mathbf{K}^{*}(Y)$ . As Y is a $\mathbf{K}^{*}$ -space, by Lemma 3.11, we could define a map

\begin{align*} h: \mathbf{K}^{*}(Y)\rightarrow Y: E\mapsto \sup E, \end{align*}

one can easily verify that h is continuous. Then, by Lemma 3.6 again, $h(\{{\downarrow} y_{A}: A\in \mathcal{A}\}) = \{y_{A}: A\in \mathcal{A}\}$ is a $\mathbf{K}^{*}$ -set of Y. Hence, $\sup\{y_{A}: A\in \mathcal{A}\} = y_{0}$ exists. Then, we have

\begin{align*} cl(f(\bigcup\mathcal{A})) = cl(\bigcup\{f(A): A\in \mathcal{A}\}) = cl(\bigcup\{{\downarrow}y_{A}: A\in \mathcal{A}\}) = cl(\{y_{0}\}), \end{align*}

which entails that $\bigcup\mathcal{A}$ is a $\mathbf{K}^{*}$ -set. So $\mathcal{A} = cl(\{\bigcup\mathcal{A}\})$ and $\mathcal K_{t}(X)$ is a $\mathbf{K}^{*}$ -space by Lemma 3.11.

Theorem 3.13. Let X be a $T_{0}$ space. Then, the pair $(\mathcal K_{t}(X), \eta_{X})$ , where $\eta_{X}$ : $X\rightarrow \mathcal K_{t}(X)$ , $x\mapsto cl(\{x\})$ , is a $\mathbf{K}^{*}$ -ification of X.

Proof. The proof is similar to that of Xu (Reference Xu2020, Theorem 4.6) which proves that $\langle X^{k} = \mathcal K(X), \zeta_{X}\rangle$ is a $\mathbf{K}$ -ification of X.

Remark 3.14. (Xu 2020, Theorem 5.14) When a category $\mathbf{K}^{*}$ of type $\mathrm K^*$ is specifically taken as WF, $\mathcal K_t(X)$ is $\mathcal{WF}_t(X)$ , i.e., $\mathbf{WF}(X)$ endowed with the lower Vietoris topology, and $\eta_X: X\rightarrow \mathcal{WF}_t(X)$ is defined as

\begin{align*}\mathrm{for any} x\in X, \eta_X(x) = {\downarrow}x.\end{align*}

Then, ( $\mathcal{WF}_t(X), \eta_X)$ is a well-filtered reflection of X.

4. The Order-K-ification Monad

A monad on a category C consists of an endofunctor $\mathcal T$ on C together with natural transformations $\eta : Id_{\mathbf C} \rightarrow \mathcal T$ and $\mu: \mathcal T^2 \rightarrow \mathcal T$ such that $\mu_{A} \circ \mathcal T\eta_A = Id_{\mathcal TA} = \mu_A \circ \eta_{\mathcal TA}$ and $\mu_A \circ \mathcal T\mu_A = \mu_A \circ \mu_{\mathcal TA}$ (Mac Lane Reference Mac Lane1998).

Let $\mathbf K^*$ be a category of type $\mathrm K^{*}$ , as in Remark 3.2, determined by certain category of type $\mathrm K$ . Theorems 3.12 and 3.13 tell us the corresponding reflector $\mathcal K_t$ , sending each $T_0$ topological space X to its $\mathbf{K}^{\mathbf{*}}$ -ification (or the $\mathbf{K}^{\mathbf{*}}$ -space completion), composing the inclusion functor Inc is not only a monad on $\mathbf{TOP}_{\mathbf{0}}$ but can be restricted to $\mathbf {MCS}$ . Now compose them with the pair of functors $\Omega$ and $\Sigma$ :

where $\Sigma$ assigns to each dcpo L the topological space $(L, \sigma (L))$ , and $\Omega$ assigns to each monotone convergence space X the dcpo $(X, \leq)$ with $\leq$ the specialization order on X. We write $\mathcal K_{t}\circ \Sigma$ as $\mathcal K_{d}$ and $Inc\circ \Omega$ as $\mathrm {Inc}$ . Then $\mathcal K_{d}$ is left adjoint to $\mathrm {Inc}$ . By the fact that each adjoint pair determines a monad, one can refer to Borceux (Reference Borceux1994, Proposition 4.2.1), we know the triple $(\mathrm {Inc}\circ \mathcal K_{d}, \eta, \mathrm{Inc}\circ\varepsilon \circ \mathcal K_{d})$ , where $\eta$ and $\varepsilon$ are the unit and counit respectively, turns into a monad on $\mathbf{DCPO}$ .

We denote $\mathrm{Inc}\circ\mathcal K_{d}$ with $\mathcal K$ , for any dcpo L, $\mathcal{K}(L)$ is a dcpo consisting of all closed $\mathbf{K}^{*}$ -sets of $(L, \sigma(L))$ ordered by set inclusion. For each directed family $\mathcal{C}$ of $\mathcal{K}(L)$ , one can verify that $\bigcup \mathcal{C}$ is a $\mathbf{K}^{*}$ -set of L, so the supremum of $\mathcal{C}$ in $\mathcal{K}(L)$ is the Scott closure of $\bigcup \mathcal{C}$ . Meanwhile, we calculate that $\mathrm{Inc}\circ\varepsilon\circ \mathcal K_{d}$ (replaced by $\mu_{L}$ when it works on a dcpo L) is a natural transformation from $\mathcal{K}(\mathcal{K}(L))$ to $\mathcal{K}(L)$ that maps $\mathcal{A}$ to $\sup_{\mathcal{K}(L)}\mathcal A$ .

Lemma 4.1. Let L be a dcpo and $\mathcal{A}$ a Scott closed $\mathbf K^{*}$ -set of $\mathcal K(L)$ . Then $\bigcup\mathcal{A}\in \mathcal{K}(L)$ .

Proof. The proof of $\bigcup\mathcal{A}$ being a $\mathbf K^{*}$ -set is similar to that in Theorem 3.12 and the Scott closure of $\bigcup\mathcal{A}$ one can easily verify.

This lemma tells us for each $\mathcal A\in \mathcal K(\mathcal K(L))$ , $\sup_{\mathcal K(L)}\mathcal{A} = \bigcup\mathcal{A}$ . Now we conclude that

Theorem 4.2. The endofunctor $\mathcal{K}$ together with the unit $\eta$ and the multiplication $\mu$ forms a monad, called an order- $\mathbf{K}$ -ification monad, on $\mathbf{DCPO}$ . Concretely, $\mathcal{K}$ associates with a dcpo L the dcpo $\mathcal{K}(L)$ and with a morphism $f: L\longrightarrow M$ in $\mathbf{DCPO}$ the map $\mathcal{K}(f)$ : $\mathcal{K}(L)\longrightarrow \mathcal{K}(M)$ , which is defined by

\begin{align*} \forall A \in \mathcal{K}(L), \mathcal{K}(f)(A) = \overline{f(A)}; \end{align*}

$\eta_{L}:L\longrightarrow \mathcal{K}(L)$ and $\mu_{L}: \mathcal{K}(\mathcal{K}(L))\longrightarrow \mathcal{K}(L)$ are defined by

\begin{align*} \forall x\in L, \eta(x) = \overline{\{x\}}, \end{align*}

and

\begin{align*} \forall\mathcal{A}\in \mathcal{K}(\mathcal{K}(L)), \mu(\mathcal{A}) = \bigcup \mathcal{A},\end{align*}

respectively.

Remark 4.3. When the category K is specifically taken as SOB or WF, the inducing order-SOB-ification monad or order-WF-ification monad is denoted by $\mathcal S$ or $\mathcal W$ , where $\mathcal S$ is actually the order-sobrification monad constructed by Ho et al. to solve the Ho-Zhao problem in Ho et al. (2018).

5. The Eilenberg-Moore Algebras of $\mathcal K$

Recall that a $\mathcal{T}$ ${-algebra}$ (Mac Lane Reference Mac Lane1998) of a monad $(\mathcal{T}, \eta, \mu)$ is a pair $(C, \xi)$ , where C is an object of C and $\xi: \mathcal{T}C\rightarrow C$ is a morphism in C, that satisfies $\xi\circ\mu_{C} = \xi\circ \mathcal{T}\xi$ and $\xi\circ \eta_{C} = id_{C}$ . In this case, $\xi$ is called a structure map. If both $(A, \xi_{A})$ and $(B, \xi_{B})$ are $\mathcal{T}$ -algebras, a $\mathcal T$ -algebra homomorphism from $(A, \xi_{A})$ to $(B, \xi_{B})$ is an arrow $h: A\rightarrow B$ satisfying $ h\circ \xi_{A} = \xi_{B}\circ \mathcal{T}h$ .

For a monad $(\mathcal T, \eta, \mu)$ on the category C, the category of $\mathcal T$ -algebras determines with respect to what algebraic structures the functor $\mathcal T$ can be understood to be universal. More precisely, for each morphism f in $\mathbf C$ which maps A to a $\mathcal T$ -algebra $(C, \xi)$ , there exists a unique $\mathcal T$ -algebra homomorphism $h: \mathcal TA\rightarrow C$ such that $f = h\circ \eta_A$ . Identifying such structures is not only an interesting mathematical problem, but also could be useful for semantics. One can refer to Jia et al. (Reference Jia, Kornell, Lindenhovius, Mislove and Zamdzhiev2022) for example, where the authors proved that the category of algebras of the subprobability valuation monad on the category of domains is isomorphic to the category of so-called continuous Kegelspitzen, and this result plays a crucial role in giving an adequate semantics to variational quantum programming languages.

Let $\mathbf{C}^{\mathcal{T}}$ denote the category of all $\mathcal{T}$ -algebras and their homomorphisms, which is also called the Eilenberg-Moore category of $\mathcal{T}$ over $\mathbf C$ . We proceed to characterize the $\mathcal K$ -algebras over $\mathbf{DCPO}$ .

Definition 5.1. (1) A poset P is called k-complete if for every Scott closed ${\mathbf{K}^{*}}$ -set A of P, $\sup A$ exists.

(2) Let L and M be posets. A map $f: L\rightarrow M$ is called k-continuous if for any $A\in \mathcal{K}(L)$ whose supremum exists, $f(\sup A) = \sup f(A)$ .

When $\mathbf K^*$ is $\mathbf {SOB}$ , k-complete posets are precisely strongly complete (Ho et al. Reference Ho, Goubault-Larrecq, Jung and Xi2018, Definition 2.1); when $\mathbf K^*$ is $\mathbf {WF}$ , we call a k-complete poset P w-complete, that is, every Scott closed well-filtered determined subset of P has a supremum in P.

Since directed subsets are tapered, they are $\mathbf{K}^{*}$ -sets by Lemma 3.10. Then the following results are immediately obtained.

Proposition 5.2.

  1. (1) Every k-complete poset is a dcpo.

  2. (2) Each k-continuous map between two posets is Scott-continuous.

Readers will be referred to Escardó (Reference Escardó1998) for the notions mentioned in the following.

A category C is called poset-enriched if the set of its hom-sets is a poset and its composition operation is monotone. A poset-functor between poset-enriched categories is a functor which is monotone on hom-posets. One can easily see that $\mathbf{DCPO}$ is a poset-enriched category and $\mathcal{K}$ is a poset-functor. If there is a pair of arrows $l: X\rightarrow Y$ and $r: Y\rightarrow X$ in C such that $l\circ r\leq {\mathrm{id}}_{Y}$ and $r\circ l\geq {\mathrm{id}}_{X}$ , then l is said to be a left adjoint of r, denoted by $l\dashv r$ . The adjunction $l\dashv r$ is reflective if $l\circ r = {\mathrm{id}}_{Y}$ . A monad $\mathcal{T} = (\mathcal{T}, \eta, \mu)$ on a poset-enriched category $\mathcal{C}$ is called a left KZ-monad if and only if $\mathcal{T}$ is a poset-functor and $ \mu_{C}\dashv\eta_{\mathcal{T}C}$ for all $C\in \mathcal{C}$ . In addition, if $\mathcal{F}: \mathbf{C}\rightarrow \mathbf{C}$ is a poset-functor, we shall say that a map $f: X\rightarrow Y$ in $\mathbf{C}$ is a left $\mathcal{F}$ -embedding if $\mathcal{F}f$ has a right adjoint and the adjunction is reflective.

Proposition 5.3. $\mathcal{K}$ is a left KZ-monad over the poset-enriched category $\mathbf{DCPO}$ .

Proof. We just need to prove that $\mu_{L}\dashv \eta_{\mathcal{K}(L)}$ for any dcpo L. On the one hand, it follows immediately from the monad law that $\mu_{L}\circ\eta_{\mathcal{K}(L)} = {\mathrm{id}}_{\mathcal{K}(L)}$ holds. On the other hand, for any $\mathcal{A}\in \mathcal{K}(\mathcal{K}(L))$ ,

\begin{align*} \eta_{\mathcal{K}(L)}\circ\mu_{L}(\mathcal{A}) = \eta_{\mathcal{K}(L)}(\bigcup\mathcal{A}) = \downarrow\!\{\bigcup\mathcal{A}\}\supseteq \mathcal{A}, \end{align*}

which means $\eta_{\mathcal{K}(L)}\circ\mu_{L}\geq {\mathrm{id}}_{\mathcal{K}(\mathcal{K}(L))}$ . So $\mu_{L}\dashv \eta_{\mathcal{K}(L)}$ ; hence, $\mathcal{K}$ is a left KZ-monad over $\mathbf{DCPO}$ .

We fully characterize the Eilenberg-Moore algebras of the monad $\mathcal K$ in the following theorem.

Theorem 5.4. Let L be a dcpo. The following statements are equivalent.

  1. (1) There exists a structure map $\alpha: \mathcal{K}(L)\rightarrow L$ such that $(L, \alpha)$ is a $\mathcal{K}$ -algebra.

  2. (2) L is an injective object over left $\mathcal{K}$ -embeddings.

  3. (3) L is a k-complete poset.

Proof. $(1)\Rightarrow (2)$ : It is immediate by Escardó (Reference Escardó1998, Theorem 4.2.2).

$(2)\Rightarrow (3)$ : One can derive from the monad law that $\mu_L\circ \mathcal K\eta_L = id_{\mathcal K(L)}$ , which reveals that $\eta_L$ is a left embedding. So there is an extension $m: \mathcal K(L)\rightarrow L$ of the identity of L along $\eta_L$ by (2). This entails that $m\circ \eta_L = id_L$ . Let A be a Scott closed $\mathbf K^{*}$ -set of L. We claim that $\sup A = m(A)$ exists. For each $a\in A$ , $\downarrow\!\!a\subseteq A$ . Since m is monotone, $m(\downarrow\!\!a)\leq m(A)$ , which means $a = m\circ\eta(a)\leq m(A)$ . If b is another upper bound of A, then $A\subseteq \downarrow\!b$ . By the monotonicity of m again, we have $m(A)\leq m(\downarrow\!b) = b$ . Thus, $\sup A = m(A)$ exists and L is a k-complete poset.

$(3)\Rightarrow (1)$ : Since $\sup A$ exists for each $A\in \mathcal{K}(L)$ , we could define a map $\alpha: \mathcal{K}(L)\rightarrow L$ by

\begin{align*} \forall A\in \mathcal{K}(L), \alpha(A) = \sup A.\end{align*}

Then, one can easily verify that $\alpha$ is Scott-continuous, besides, $\alpha\circ\eta = {\mathrm{id}}_{L}$ and $\alpha\circ\mu = \alpha\circ\mathcal{K}\alpha$ hold. So $(L, \alpha)$ is a $\mathcal{K}$ -algebra.

By definitions of the $\mathcal{K}$ -algebra homomorphisms and the k-continuity, the following conclusion is obtained immediately, which will help us characterize the Eilenberg-Moore category of $\mathcal K$ .

Proposition 5.5. Let L, M be dcpos. If $(L, \alpha_{L})$ and $(M, \alpha_{M})$ are $\mathcal{K}$ -algebras, then $f: L\rightarrow M$ is a $\mathcal{K}$ -algebra homomorphism if and only if f is k-continuous.

Now let $\mathbf{DCPO}^{\mathcal{K}}$ denote the category of all $\mathcal K$ -algebras and all $\mathcal K$ -algebra homomorphisms, that is the Eilenberg-Moore category of $\mathcal K$ . Then obviously, $\mathcal{K}$ produces a monadic adjunction:

\begin{align*} \mathcal{F}: \mathbf{DCPO}\rightarrow \mathbf{DCPO}^{\mathcal{K}}, \qquad \mathcal U: \mathbf{DCPO}^{\mathcal{K}}\rightarrow \mathbf{DCPO},\end{align*}

where $\mathcal{F}$ assigns each dcpo L to $(\mathcal{K}(L), \mu_{L})$ and each map $f: L\rightarrow M$ from L to dcpo M to $\mathcal{K}(f): (\mathcal{K}(L), \mu_{L})\rightarrow(\mathcal{K}(M), \mu_{M})$ , and $\mathcal U$ as a forgetful functor is the right adjoint of $\mathcal F$ . As the characterizations of $\mathcal{K}$ -algebras and their homomorphisms imply that $\mathbf{DCPO}^{\mathcal{K}}$ is equivalent to the category $\mathbf{KCPO}$ , which has the k-complete posets as objects and the k-continuous maps as morphisms, we reach the following conclusion:

Corollary 5.6. $\mathcal{K}$ gives a free k-complete poset construction over $\mathbf{DCPO}$ .

In Zhao and Fan (Reference Zhao and Fan2010), Zhao and Fan have proved that the category $\mathbf{DCPO}$ is a reflective full subcategory of the category $\mathbf{POS}_{\mathbf{d}}$ of posets and Scott-continuous maps. Thus combining the above corollary, the following result can be derived immediately:

Corollary 5.7. $\mathcal{K}$ gives a free k-complete poset construction over $\mathbf{POS}_{\mathbf{d}}$ .

Let $\mathbf{KCPO}_{\sigma}$ be the full subcategory of $\mathbf{DCPO}$ which has k-complete posets as objects and Scott-continuous maps as morphisms.

It is a truism that Cartesian closed categories give rise to the models of various typed and untyped $\lambda$ -calculi and functional programming languages (Lambek Reference Lambek1985; Scott Reference Scott1976; Streicher Reference Streicher2006). We will see in the following theorem that similar to the category DCPO, $\mathbf{KCPO}_{\sigma}$ is Cartesian closed for each category $\mathbf K^*$ of type $\mathrm K^*$ .

Proposition 5.8. The category $\mathbf{KCPO}_{\sigma}$ is Cartesian closed.

Proof. Since $\mathbf{KCPO}_{\sigma}$ is a full subcategory of $\mathbf{DCPO}$ , we only need to prove that for any k-complete posets L and M, $L\times M$ and $[L\rightarrow M]$ (the set of all Scott-continuous maps between L and M) are still k-complete posets.

$\mathbf{Claim\ 1}$ : $L\times M$ is a k-complete poset.

Let $A\subseteq L\times M$ be a Scott closed $\mathbf{K}^{\mathbf{*}}$ -set. Then, A is a $\mathbf{K}^{\mathbf{*}}$ -set in $\Sigma L\times \Sigma M$ . Since the projections $\pi_{L}$ and $\pi_{M}$ are continuous, $\pi_{L}(A)$ and $\pi_{M}(A)$ are $\mathbf{K}^{\mathbf{*}}$ -sets of L and M, respectively. The fact that L and M are k-complete posets implies the existence of $\sup(\pi_{L}(A))$ and $\sup(\pi_{M}(A))$ . One can verify that $(\sup(\pi_{L}(A)), \sup(\pi_{M}(A)))$ is the supremum of A. So $L\times M$ is a k-complete poset.

$\mathbf{Claim\ 2}$ : $[L\rightarrow M]$ is a k-complete poset.

Let $\{f_{i}: i\in I\}\subseteq [L\rightarrow M]$ be a $\mathbf{K}^{\mathbf{*}}$ -set. We define $g: L\rightarrow M$ by

\begin{align*} \forall x\in L, g(x) = \sup\{f_{i}(x): i\in I\}. \end{align*}

By Lemma 2-2.8 and Lemma 2-2.9 in Gierz et al. (Reference Gierz, Hofmann, Keimel, Lawson, Mislove and Scott2003), we know the map $eval_{x}: [L\rightarrow M]\rightarrow M$ defined by $eval_{x}(h) = h(x)$ is continuous. Thus, $eval_{x}(\{f_{i}: i\in I\}) = \{f_{i}(x): i\in I\}$ is a $\mathbf{K}^{\mathbf{*}}$ -set of M. Since M is k-complete, $\sup\{f_{i}(x): i\in I\}$ exists in M. This means g is well-defined. Obviously, g is Scott-continuous and $g = \sup\{f_{i}: i\in I\}$ . Thus, $[L\rightarrow M]$ is k-complete.

In conclusion, $\mathbf{KCPO}_{\sigma}$ is Cartesian closed.

6. $\mathcal K$ is a Commutative Monad

Recall that a monoidal category (see Borceux Reference Borceux1994, Definition 6.1.1) is a category C equipped with an object $\top$ in $\mathbf C$ called unit, a bifunctor $\otimes: \mathbf C\times \mathbf C\rightarrow \mathbf C$ called tensor product, and the natural isomorphisms $\alpha, r$ and l defined as the following forms (for the objects A, B and C):

  1. (i) $ {\alpha_{A, B, C}}: A \otimes (B \otimes C) \rightarrow (A \otimes B) \otimes C$ ,

  2. (ii) $r_A: A\otimes \top \rightarrow A$ ,

  3. (iii) $l_A: \top\otimes A \rightarrow A$ , such that certain equations hold. It will be a symmetric monoidal category if in addition it has the natural isomorphism s defined as the form:

  4. (iv) $ {s_{A, B}}: A\otimes B\rightarrow B\otimes A$ ,

such that certain equations hold. It was Kock who first defined strong monads over symmetric monoidal categories (Kock Reference Kock1972). In this section we will first investigate the strongness of the monad $\mathcal K$ induced by the category $\mathbf K^*$ of type $\mathrm K^*$ on $\mathbf{DCPO}$ , where $\mathbf{DCPO}$ is clearly a Cartesian monoidal category. In this case, the tensor product $\otimes$ is precisely the categorical product and $\top$ is the terminal object, we use $\times$ and 1 to represent them respectively. Moreover, $\alpha(A, B, C), r_A, l_A$ are defined concretely as follows:

  1. (i) $\alpha_{A, B, C} = ((\pi_1, \pi_1\circ\pi_2), \pi_2\circ\pi_2))$ ,

  2. (ii) $r_A = \pi_1$ ,

  3. (iii) $l_A = \pi_2$ ,

where $\pi_{i}(i = 1,2)$ denotes the projection onto the $i{\rm th}$ component.

Definition 6.1. A strong monad over a category $\mathbf{C}$ with an object 1 and finite products is a monad $(\mathcal T,\eta,\mu)$ together with a natural transformation $t'': ({-})\times \mathcal T({=})\rightarrow \mathcal T({-}\times{=})$ such that the following diagrams commute:

in which the natural transformation t” is called tensorial strength. Moreover, $t' = \mathcal Ts\circ t''\circ s: \mathcal T({-})\times (=)\rightarrow \mathcal T({-}\times =)$ is called cotensorial strength.

Lemma 6.2. Let P and Q be posets. Then, $cl_{\sigma}(A)\times B = cl_{\sigma}(A\times B)$ for any $A\subseteq P$ and $B\in \Gamma(Q)$ .

Proof. It is obvious that $cl_{\sigma}(A\times B)\subseteq cl_{\sigma}(A)\times B$ since $cl_{\sigma}(A)\times B$ is closed in $\Sigma(P\times Q)$ . Now see the reverse. For any $(a,b)\in cl_{\sigma}(A)\times B$ and $U\in \sigma(P\times Q)$ with $(a, b)\in U$ . Set $U_{b} = \{x\in P: (x, b)\in U\}$ . Clearly, $a\in U_b$ and it is an upper set. Let $D\subseteq P$ be a directed subset with $\sup D\in U_{b}$ , that is, $(\sup D, b)\in U$ . Then, we have $(d_{0}, b)\in U$ for some $d_{0}\in D$ by the Scott openness of U, which implies that $d_{0}\in U_{b}$ . Thus, $U_{b}\in \sigma(P)$ . Then, $A\cap U_{b} \neq\emptyset$ by $a\in cl_{\sigma}(A)$ , so there is an $a_{0}\in A\cap U_{b}$ . It follows that $(a_{0}, b)\in (A\times B)\cap U$ . Therefore, $(a, b)\in cl_{\sigma}(A\times B)$ and $cl_{\sigma}(A)\times B\subseteq cl_{\sigma}(A\times B)$ .

Proposition 6.3. $\mathcal{K}$ is a strong monad over $\mathbf{DCPO}$ .

Proof. Obviously, the direct product $L_{1}\times\cdot\cdot\cdot\times L_{n}$ of finitely many dcpos $L_{1},...,L_{n}$ is still a dcpo. Given $\{L,M,N\}\subseteq \mathbf{DCPO}$ , we define $l_{L}$ as $\pi_{2}$ and $\alpha_{L,M,N}: (L\times M)\times N\rightarrow L\times (M\times N)$ as $(\pi_{1}\circ\pi_{1},(\pi_{2}\circ\pi_{1},\pi_{2}))$ . Define $t''_{L,M}:L\times \mathcal{K}(M)\longrightarrow \mathcal{K}(L\times M)$ by

\begin{align*} \forall (x, A)\in L\times \mathcal{K}(M), t''_{L,M}(x, A) =\ \downarrow x\times A. \end{align*}

$\mathbf{Claim\; 1}$ : $t''_{L,M}$ is well-defined.

It is sufficient to show that $\downarrow$ $x\times A\in \mathcal{K}(L\times M)$ . Obviously, $\downarrow$ $x\times A$ is closed in $\Sigma(L\times M)$ . Now we prove that $\downarrow$ $x\times A$ is a $\mathbf{K}^{*}$ -set in $\Sigma(L\times M)$ . For any $\mathbf{K}^{*}$ -space Y and the continuous map $f: L\times M\rightarrow Y$ , we fix $x\in L$ and define $f_{x}: M\rightarrow Y$ as

\begin{align*} \forall a\in M, f_{x}(a) = f(x,a), \end{align*}

which is well-defined. Now claim that $f_{x}$ is continuous, i.e., $f_{x}^{-1}(U)\in \sigma(M)$ for each $U\in \mathcal{O}(Y)$ . For any $a_{1}\in f_{x}^{-1}(U)$ and $a_{2}\in M$ with $a_{1}\leq a_{2}$ , $f_{x}(a_{1}) = f(x,a_{1})\in U$ , that is, $(x,a_{1})\in f^{-1}(U)\in \sigma(L\times M)$ . The fact $(x,a_{2})\geq (x,a_{1})$ implies $(x,a_{2})\in f^{-1}(U)$ , and so $f_{x}(a_{2})\in U$ . Thus $f_{x}^{-1}(U)$ is an upper set. Now let $D\subseteq M$ be a directed subset with $\sup D\in f_{x}^{-1}(U)$ . Then, $(x, \sup D)\in f^{-1}(U)$ . It follows that there exists a $d\in D$ such that $(x,d)\in f^{-1}(U)$ , that is, $d\in f_{x}^{-1}(U)$ . Thus, $f_{x}$ is continuous, which guarantees that $f_{x}(A)$ is a $\mathbf{K}^{*}$ -set of Y by Lemma 3.6. Since Y is a $\mathbf{K}^{*}$ -space, $\overline{f_{x}(A)} = \overline{\{f(x,a): a\in A\}} = \overline{\{y_{0}\}}$ for some $y_{0}\in Y$ . This means $\overline{f(\downarrow\!\!x\times A)} = \overline{\{y_{0}\},}$ and hence, $\downarrow$ $x\times A$ is a $\mathbf{K}^{*}$ -set of $L\times M$ .

$\mathbf{Claim\; 2}$ : $t''_{L,M}$ is Scott-continuous.

We just need to prove $t''_{L,M}$ is Scott-continuous in each component. Fixed $A\in \mathcal{K}(M)$ , for any directed subset $D\subseteq L$ , we have

\begin{align*} t''_{L,M}(\sup D, A) &= \downarrow\!\!\sup D\times A \\ &= \overline{\bigcup_{d\in D}\downarrow\!\!d}\times A \\ &= \overline{\bigcup_{d\in D}(\downarrow\!\!d\times A)} \\ &= \sup\{t''_{L,M}(d, A): d\in D\}, \end{align*}

where Lemma 6.2 guarantees the third equation. It follows that $t''_{L,M}$ is Scott-continuous in the first component. Next, given $x\in L$ , let $\{A_{i}: i\in I\}$ be a directed family of $\mathcal{K}(M)$ . We have

\begin{align*} t''_{L,M}(x, \sup_{i\in I}A_{i}) &= \downarrow\!\!x\times \sup_{i\in I}A_{i} \\ &= \downarrow\!\!x\times \overline{\bigcup_{i\in I}A_{i}} \\ &= \overline{\bigcup_{i\in I}(\downarrow\!\!x\times A_{i})} \\ &= \sup_{i\in I}t''_{L,M}(x, A_{i}). \end{align*}

So $t''_{L,M}$ is Scott-continuous in the second component, and it is concluded that $t''_{L,M}$ is Scott-continuous.

$\mathbf{Claim\; 3}$ : $t''_{L,M}$ is a natural transformation, that is, the following diagram commutes:

where L’, M’ are dcpos and $f: L\rightarrow L'$ , $g: M\rightarrow M'$ are Scott-continuous maps.

Now pick $(m, A)\in L\times \mathcal{K}(M)$ to prove that $(\mathcal{K}(f\times g)\circ t''_{L,M})(m, A) = (t''_{L',M'}\circ f\times \mathcal{K}(g))(m, A)$ . By the facts that

\begin{align*} (\mathcal{K}(f\times g)\circ t''_{L,M})(m, A) = \mathcal{K}(f\times g)(\downarrow\!\!m\times A) = \overline{(f\times g) (\downarrow\!\!m\times A)} = \overline{f(\downarrow\!\!m)\times g(A)} \mathrm{and},\\ (t''_{L^{'},M^{'}}\circ f\times \mathcal{K}(g))(m, A) = t''_{L^{'},M^{'}}(f(m), \overline{g(A)}) = \downarrow\!\!f(m)\times \overline{g(A)}, \end{align*}

we just need to show $\overline{f(\downarrow\!\!m)\times g(A)} = \downarrow\!\!f(m)\times \overline{g(A)}$ . Obviously, $\overline{f(\downarrow\!\!m)\times g(A)}\subseteq\;\downarrow\!\!f(m)\times \overline{g(A)}$ . On the contrary, for any $x\in \overline{g(A)}$ and $U\in \sigma(L'\times M')$ with $(f(m), x)\in U$ . Set $U_{f(m)} = \{y\in M': (f(m),y)\in U\}$ . Then, $x\in U_{f(m)}$ and $U_{f(m)}\in \sigma({M'})$ . As $x\in \overline{g(A)}$ , $U_{f(m)}\cap g(A) \neq \emptyset$ , which implies that there exists a $y_{0}\in U_{f(m)}\cap g(A)$ , that is, $(f(m), y_{0})\in (f(\downarrow\!\!m)\times g(A))\cap U\neq\emptyset$ . This means $(f(m), x)\in \overline{f(\downarrow\!\!m)\times g(A)}$ , so $\downarrow\!\!f(m)\times \overline{g(A)}\subseteq \overline{f(\downarrow\!\!m)\times g(A)}$ holds.

$\mathbf{Claim\ 4}$ : The four diagrams given in Definition 6.1 commute when replacing $\mathcal T$ with $\mathcal{K}$ and A, B, C with dcpos L, M, N, respectively.

The proof of the following equations is similar to that of the above, so we omit it.

  1. (i) For any $A\in \mathcal{K}(L)$ ,

    \begin{align*} (\mathcal{K}l_{L}\circ t''_{\{1\},L})(1, A) = r_{\mathcal{K}(L)}(1, A), \end{align*}
    where 1 is the terminal object in $\mathbf {DCPO}$ .
  2. (ii) For any $(a, b)\in L\times M$ ,

    \begin{align*} (t''_{L,M}\circ {\mathrm{id}}_{L}\times \eta_{M})(a, b) = \eta_{L\times M}(a, b). \end{align*}
  3. (iii) For any $((a, b), A)\in (L\times M)\times \mathcal{K}(N)$ ,

    \begin{align*} (\mathcal{K}\alpha_{L,M,N}\circ t''_{L\times M,N})((a,b),A) = (t''_{L,M\times N}\circ {\mathrm{id}}_{L}\times t''_{M,N}\circ \alpha_{L,M,\mathcal{K}(N)})((a,b),A) . \end{align*}
  4. (iv) For any $(a, \mathcal{A})\in L\times \mathcal{K}(\mathcal{K}(M))$ ,

    \begin{align*} (\mu_{L\times M}\circ \mathcal{K}t''_{L,M}\circ t''_{L,\mathcal{K}(M)})(a, \mathcal{A}) = (t''_{L,M}\circ {\mathrm{id}}_{L}\times \mu_{M})(a, \mathcal{A}). \end{align*}

From the construction of the $s_{L,M}$ above, we can obtain the following result.

Corollary 6.4. $\mathcal{K}(L)\times \mathcal{K}(M) \subseteq \mathcal{K}(L\times M)$ , where $\mathcal{K}(L)\times \mathcal{K}(M) = \{A\times B: A\in \mathcal{K}(L), B\in \mathcal{K}(M)\}$ .

Proof. For any $(A, B)\in \mathcal{K}(L)\times \mathcal{K}(M)$ , we define the map $t''^{B}_{L,M}: L\rightarrow \mathcal{K}(L\times M)$ :

\begin{align*} \forall x\in L, t''^{B}_{L,M}(x) = t''_{L,M}(x, B). \end{align*}

By the proof of Proposition 6.3, we know $t''^{B}_{L,M}$ is well-defined and Scott-continuous. Thus, $\overline{t''^{B}_{L,M}(A)} = \overline{\{\downarrow\!\!x\times B: x\in A\}}\in\mathcal{K}(\mathcal{K}(L\times M))$ . It follows that $A\times B = \mu(\overline{\{\downarrow\!\!x\times B: x\in A\}})\in \mathcal{K}(L\times M)$ .

For dcpos L and M, we calculate the cotensorial strength $t'_{L, M}: \mathcal{K}(L)\times M\rightarrow \mathcal{K}(L\times M)$ as $\ t'_{L,M}((C, x)) = C\times {\downarrow}x $ for any $(C, x)\in \mathcal{K}(L)\times M$ . Following the standard categorical terminology (see Kock Reference Kock1970), the strong monad $(\mathcal{K}, \eta, \mu)$ on $\mathbf{DCPO}$ is commutative if $\psi$ and $\widetilde{\psi}$ agree, where $\psi, \widetilde{\psi}: \mathcal{K}(L)\times \mathcal{K}(M) \rightarrow \mathcal{K}(L\times M)$ are defined as follows:

\begin{align*} \psi_{L,M} = \mu_{L\times M}\circ \mathcal{K}t''_{L,M}\circ t'_{L,\mathcal{K}(M)}\\ \widetilde{\psi}_{L,M} = \mu_{L\times M}\circ \mathcal{K}t'_{L,M}\circ t''_{\mathcal{K}(L),M}. \end{align*}

It is folklore that computationally, strongness of a monad together with adequacy of the corresponding denotational semantics can be used to establish contextual equivalences for effectful programs (Moggi Reference Moggi1991; Plotkin and Power Reference Plotkin and Power2001). Particularly, if $\mathcal K$ is commutative, it will carry the structure $\psi$ making $(\mathcal K, \eta, \mu)$ into a symmetric monoidal monad on DCPO. With this stronger commutative property, we would know that it does not matter which order two instances of the effect appear in programs.

Theorem 6.5. $\mathcal{K}$ is a commutative monad on $\mathbf{DCPO}$ .

Proof. We just need to prove that for any dcpos L, M and $(A, B)\in \mathcal{K}(L)\times \mathcal{K}(M)$ , $ (\mu_{L\times M}\circ \mathcal{K}t''_{L,M}\circ t'_{L,\mathcal{K}(M)}) (A, B) = (\mu_{L\times M}\circ \mathcal{K}t'_{L,M}\circ t''_{\mathcal{K}(L),M}) (A,B)$ , that is,

\begin{align*} \bigcup{\overline{\{\downarrow\!\!a\times B': a\in A, B'\subseteq B\}}} = \bigcup{\overline{\{A'\times {\downarrow}b: A'\subseteq A, b\in B\}}}. \end{align*}

For convenience, let lhs denote the left hand side of the equation and rhs the right hand side. Consider each $a\in A$ and $B'\subseteq B$ . For any $b'\in B'$ , $b'\in B$ . Then, ${\downarrow}a\times {\downarrow}b'\in \{A'\times {\downarrow}b: A'\subseteq A, b\in B\}$ , which implies ${\downarrow}a\times {\downarrow}b'\subseteq rhs$ . It follows that ${\downarrow}a\times B' = \bigcup\{{\downarrow}a\times {\downarrow}b': b'\in B'\}\subseteq rhs$ , in other words, ${\downarrow}a\times B'\in {\downarrow} rhs$ . Then $\overline{\{\downarrow\!\!a\times B': a\in A, B'\subseteq B\}} \subseteq {\downarrow} rhs$ , which means $lhs\subseteq rhs$ . $rhs\subseteq lhs$ can be proved similarly.

Remark 6.6. When $\mathcal K$ is specifically taken as $\mathcal S$ , i.e., the order-sobrification monad proposed by Ho et al. (2018), then $\mathcal S$ is commutative, and the conclusion (Jia 2020, Theorem 3.6) given by Jia is generalized by Theorem 6.5.

We conclude our paper with a brief discussion of the advantage of semantic applications of $\mathcal K$ . We have proved that each $\mathcal K$ is a strong monad over the category DCPO, this gives rise to the structures of $\lambda_c$ -models considered by Moggi (Reference Moggi1989).

Definition 6.7. (Moggi Reference Moggi1989) A $\lambda_c$ -model over a category C with finite products is a strong monad $(\mathcal T, \eta, \mu)$ together with a $\mathcal T$ -exponential for every pair (A, B) of objects in C, i.e., a pair

\begin{align*} \langle {(\mathcal TB)}^A, eval_{A, \mathcal TB}: {(\mathcal TB)}^A\times A\rightarrow \mathcal TB\rangle \end{align*}

satisfying the universal property that for any object C and $f: C\times A\rightarrow \mathcal TB$ , there exists a unique $h: C\rightarrow {(\mathcal TB)}^A$ , denoted by $\Lambda_{A, \mathcal T B}(f)$ s.t.

\begin{align*} f = eval_{A, \mathcal TB}\circ (\Lambda_{A, \mathcal T B}(f)\times Id_A).\end{align*}

From the above definition, we could clearly see that each strong monad on a Cartesian closed category is a $\lambda_c$ -model. So each order-K-ification monad $\mathcal K$ is a $\lambda_c$ -model by its strongness and the Cartesian closedness of $\mathbf{DCPO}$ .

Moggi gave the interpretation of a formal system called $\lambda_c$ -calculus in a $\lambda_c$ -model, which is sound and complete with respect to the interpretation. In our case, $\lambda_c$ -calculus is interpreted as morphisms of the Kleisli category for $\mathcal K$ .

Recall that the Hoare power construction $\mathcal H$ on the category DCPO is useful for modeling the angelic non-determinism. In particular, one can verify that $\mathcal H$ is a strong monad on DCPO, so naturally, it is also a $\lambda_c$ -model. As a refinement of $\mathcal H$ , there are fewer morphisms in the Kleisli category of each monad $\mathcal K$ than that of $\mathcal H$ . So some useless semantic trash could be culled if we consider using the Kleisli category of $\mathcal K$ as semantic categories, to provide a more accurate interpretation for the programming language at hand.

We would end this paper with an example to illustrate that there are indeed fewer morphisms in the Kleisli category of the monad $\mathcal K$ for some particular categories of type $\mathrm K$ , than that of $\mathcal H$ .

Example 6.8. Let’s take $\mathcal K$ as the order-sobrification monad $\mathcal S$ , which assigns $(Irr\Gamma(L), \subseteq)$ to each dcpo L, i.e., the poset of all irreducible closed subsets of $\Sigma L$ with the inclusion order. Clearly, $\mathcal S(L)\subseteq \mathcal H(L)$ . We take a concrete dcpo $L = \mathbb Z\cup \{\perp\}$ with the order $x\leq y$ defined as $x = \perp, y\in \mathbb Z$ or $x= y \in \mathbb Z$ , where $\mathbb Z$ is the set of all integers, and a dcpo $M = \{0, 1\}$ with the usual order $0\leq 1$ . In denotational semantics, L is the semantic of the type int and M is that of the type unit. Note that $\Gamma(L) = \{{\downarrow}A: A\subseteq \mathbb Z\}\cup\{\bot\}$ , $Irr\Gamma(L) = \{{\downarrow}n: n\in \mathbb Z\}\cup\{\bot\}$ . We define a map $f: M\rightarrow \mathcal H(L)$ as

\begin{align*} f(m) =\begin{cases} \bot,& \mathrm{m = 0}\\ {\downarrow}\{1,2\},& \mathrm{m = 1}.\end{cases} \end{align*}

The map f is Scott-continuous since it is monotone and M is finite; hence, it is in $\mathbf{DCPO}_{\mathcal H}$ . However, there is no Scott-continuous map $g: M\to \mathcal S(L)$ in $\mathbf{DCPO}_{\mathcal S}$ such that $f = i\circ g$ , where $i: \mathcal S(L)\rightarrow\mathcal H(L)$ is the canonical inclusion map. This is obvious because the images of $i\circ g$ consist of principal ideals, while f(1) is not a principal ideal.

Acknowledgements

The authors would like to thank the referee for the numerous and very helpful suggestions that have improved this paper substantially.

Competing interests

The authors declare that they have no known competing financial interests or personal relationships that could have appeared to influence the work reported in this paper.

Footnotes

*This work is supported by the National Natural Science Foundation of China (No.12231007).

References

Borceux, F. (1994). Handbook of Categorical Algebra: Volume 2, Categories and Structures , Encyclopedia of Mathematics and Its Applications, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Eilenberg, S. and Moore, J. (1965). Adjoint functors and triples. Illinois Journal of Mathematics 9 381398.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ershov, Y. L. (2022). K-Completions of T 0-spaces. Algebra and Logic 61 177187.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ershov, Y. L. (1999). On d-spaces. Theoretical Computer Science 224 5972.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Escardó, M. (1998). Properly injective spaces and function spaces. Topology and its Applications 89 75120.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gierz, G., Hofmann, K., Keimel, K., Lawson, J., Mislove, M. and Scott, D. (2003). Continuous lattices and domains. In: Encyclopedia of Mathematics and its Applications, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goubault-Larrecq, J. (2013). Non-Hausdorff Topology and Domain Theory , New Mathematical Monographs, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Hennessy, M. and Plotkin, G. (1979). Full abstraction for a simple parallel programming language. In: International Symposium on Mathematical Foundations of Computer Science, Berlin, Heidelberg, Springer, 108–120.Google Scholar
Ho, W., Goubault-Larrecq, J., Jung, A. and Xi, X. (2018). The Ho-Zhao problem. Logical Methods in Computer Science 14 119.Google Scholar
Jia, X. (2020). The order-sobrification monad. Applied Categorical Structures 28 845852.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jia, X., Kornell, A., Lindenhovius, B., Mislove, M. and Zamdzhiev, V. (2022). Semantics for variational quantum programming. Proceedings of the ACM on Programming Languages 6 (POPL) 131.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jia, X., Lindenhovius, B., Mislove, M. and Zamdzhiev, V. Commutative monads for probabilistic programming languages. In: In the Proceedings of the 36th Annual ACM/IEEE Symposium on Logic in Computer Science, (LICS2021), 114.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jia, X. and Mislove, M. (2022). Completing simple valuations in K-categories. Topology and its Applications 318 108192.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jung, A. (1989). Cartesian Closed Categories of Domains, Amsterdam, Centrum voor Wiskunde en Informatica.Google Scholar
Keimel, K. and Lawson, J. (2009). D-completions and the d-topology. Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 159 292306.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kock, A. (1970). Monads on symmetric monoidal closed categories. Archiv der Mathematik 21 110.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kock, A. (1972). Strong functors and monoidal monads. Archiv der Mathematik 23 113120.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lambek, J. (1985). Cartesian closed categories and typed λ-calculi. In: LITP Spring School on Theoretical Computer Science, Berlin, Heidelberg, Springer Berlin Heidelberg, 136–175.Google Scholar
Liu, B., Li, Q. and Wu, G. (2020). Well-filterifications of topological spaces. Topology and its Applications 279 107245.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mac Lane, S. (1998). Categories for the Working Mathematician , Graduate Texts in Mathematics, vol. 5, Berlin, Springer.Google Scholar
Moggi, E. (1989). Computational lambda-calculus and monads. In: 4th Symposium on Logic in Computer Science, 14–23.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Moggi, E. (1991). Notions of computation and monads. Information and Computation 93 5592.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Plotkin, G. (1976). A powerdomain construction. SIAM Journal on Computing 5 452487.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Plotkin, G. and Power, J. (2001). Adequacy for algebraic effects. In: International Conference on Foundations of Software Science and Computation Structures, Berlin, Heidelberg, Springer Berlin Heidelberg, 1–24.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schalk, A. (1993). Algebras for Generalized Power Constructions. Phd thesis, Technische Hochschule Darmstadt.Google Scholar
Scott, D. (1976). Data types as lattices. SIAM Journal on computing 5 (3) 522587.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shen, C., Xi, X., Xu, X. and Zhao, D. (2019). On well-filtered reflections of T 0 spaces. Topology and its Applications 267 106869.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shen, C., Xi, X. and Zhao, D. (2021). The reflectivity of some categories of T 0 spaces in domain theory. arXiv e-prints.Google Scholar
Smyth, M. (1976). Powerdomains. In: International Symposium on Mathematical Foundations of Computer Science, Berlin, Heidelberg, Springer, 537–543.Google Scholar
Streicher, T. (2006). Domain-Theoretic Foundations of Functional Programming, Singapore, World Scientific Publishing Company.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wu, G., Xi, X., Xu, X. and Zhao, D. (2020). Existence of well-filterifications of T 0 topological spaces. Topology and its Applications 270 107044.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wyler, O. (1979). Dedekind complete posets and Scott topologies. In: Lecture Notes in Mathematics, Berlin, Heidelberg, Springer, vol. 871, 384–389.Google Scholar
Xi, X. and Lawson, J. (2017). On well-filtered spaces and ordered sets. Topology and its Applications 228 139144.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Xu, X. (2020). A direct approach to K-reflections of T 0 spaces. Topology and its Applications 272 107076.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Xu, X., Shen, C., Xi, X. and Zhao, D. (2020). First countability, ω-well-filtered spaces and reflections. Topology and its Applications 279 107255.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Xu, X. and Zhao, D. (2020). On topological Rudin’s lemma, well-filtered spaces and sober spaces. Topology and its Applications 272 107080.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zhang, Z. and Li, Q. (2017). A direct characterization of the monotone convergence space completion. Topology and its Applications 230 99104.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zhao, D. and Fan, T. (2010). Dcpo-completion of posets. Theoretical Computer Science 411 21672173.CrossRefGoogle Scholar