Article contents
POLITICAL OBLIGATIONS IN A SEA OF TYRANNY AND CRUSHING POVERTY*
Published online by Cambridge University Press: 09 December 2014
Abstract
Christopher Wellman is the strongest proponent of the natural-duty theory of political obligations and argues that his version of the theory can satisfy the key requirement of “particularity”; namely, justifying to members of a state the system of political obligations they share in. Critics argue that natural-duty theories like Wellman's actually require well-ordered states and/or their members to dedicate resources to providing the goods associated with political order to needy outsiders. The implication is that natural-duty approaches weaken the particularity requirement and cannot justify to citizens the systems of political obligation they share in. I argue that the critics’ diagnosis of natural-duty approaches is correct, whereas the proposed implication is false. I maintain that 1) only natural-duty approaches can justify political obligations, and that 2) weakening the particularity requirement contributes to the theory's ability to justify a range-limited system of political obligations among compatriots.
- Type
- Research Article
- Information
- Copyright
- Copyright © Cambridge University Press 2014
Footnotes
Helpful comments on an earlier draft were provided by Sofia Näsström, Marcus Agnafors, Eva Erman, Jörgen Hermansson, Ed Page, Chris Armstrong, Magnus Reitberger, Jouni Reinikainen, Jörgen Ödalen, Jonas Hultin Rosenberg, and from workshop participants in Uppsala and Växjö.
References
1 See Edmundson, William A., State of the Art: The Duty to Obey the Law, 10 Legal Theory 215–259 (2004)Google Scholar; Dagger, Richard, Political Obligation, in The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Zalta, Edward N. ed., 2010)Google Scholar, http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2010/entries/political-obligation/.
2 Wellman, Christopher H., Political Obligation and the Particularity Requirement, 10 Legal Theory 97–115 (2004)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.
3 Renzo, Massimo, Duties of Samaritanism and Political Obligation, 14 Legal Theory 193–217 (2008)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.
4 For similar treatments of these distinctions, see Kramer, Michael, Legal and Moral Obligation, in The Blackwell Guide to the Philosophy of Law and Legal Theory 179–190 (Golding, Martin. P. & Edmundson, William A. eds., 2005)Google Scholar; Edmundson, supra note 1, at 215–216.
5 For support for the view that having exclusionary reasons to accept state dictates is too strong a requirement for a theory of political obligation, see Gur, Noam, Legal Directives in the Realm of Practical Reason: A Challenge to the Pre-emption Thesis, 52 Am. J. Juris. 159–228 (2007)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Martin, Margaret E., Raz's The Morality of Freedom: Two Models of Authority, 1 Jurisprudence 53–72 (2010)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.
6 Mokrosińska, Dorota, What Is Political about Political Obligation: A Neglected Lesson from Consent Theory, 16 Critical Rev. Int’l Soc. & Pol. Phil. 88–108 (2013)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.
7 Democratic control over the political order does not amount to individual consent to the political obligations associated with political order. A theory of political obligation aims to justify why some subset of human interaction ought to be under democratic political control in the first place.
8 Hume, David, Of the Original Contract, in Hume's Ethical Writings 263 (Macintyre, Alistair ed., 1970)Google Scholar; John A. Simmons, Moral Principles and Political Obligations (1979), at 99–100.
9 Dworkin, Ronald, The Original Position, in Reading Rawls 16–52 (Daniels, Norman ed., 1975), at 17–21Google Scholar; Jean Hampton, Political Philosophy (1997), at 65–66.
10 Simmons, John A., Justification and Legitimacy, 109 Ethics 739–771 (1999), at 761CrossRefGoogle Scholar.
11 Id. at 766.
12 Id. at 768.
13 Mokrosińska, supra note 6, at 7–10.
14 Wellman, supra note 2, at 110–111.
15 John Locke, Two Treatises of Government and A Letter Concerning Toleration (Ian Shapiro ed., 2003), at 142.
16 Joseph Raz, The Morality of Freedom (1986), at 90; Hampton, supra note 9, at 59–61.
17 Simmons, John A., Consent Theory for Libertarians, 22 Soc. Phil. & Pol’y 330–356 (2005), at 352–354CrossRefGoogle Scholar.
18 Id. at 349–350.
19 Pitkin, Hanna, Obligation and Consent—I, 59 Am. Pol. Sci. Rev. 990–999 (1965)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.
20 Hart, H.L.A., Are There Any Natural Rights?, 64 Phil. Rev. 175–191 (1955)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.
21 Goodin, Robert E., What Is So Special about Our Fellow Countrymen?, 98 Ethics 663–686 (1988), at 677CrossRefGoogle Scholar.
22 Robert Nozick, Anarchy, State, and Utopia (1974), at 90–95; Simmons, Moral Principles, supra note 8, at 147–152.
23 George Klosko, Political Obligations (2005), at 17–74.
24 Id. at 71.
25 Klosko, George, Presumptive Benefit, Fairness, and Political Obligation, 16 Phil. & Pub. Aff. 241–259 (1987)Google Scholar, at 249–259; Klosko, Political, supra note 23, at 52.
26 Klosko does argue that a mutual benefit theory of political obligations must be accompanied by natural-duty reasoning in order to be adequately inclusiveness. See Klosko, George, Multiple Principles of Political Obligation, 32 Pol. Theory, 801–824 (2004)CrossRefGoogle Scholar. However, as shown below, he insists that fair reciprocity is the foundational principle on which a theory of political obligations must rest. I challenge this reasoning in Section III.
27 Ronald Dworkin, Law's Empire (1986), at 196–2002.
28 For examples, see Yael Tamir, Liberal Nationalism (1993); David Miller, On Nationality (1995); Horton, John, In Defence of Associative Political Obligations: Part One, 54 Pol. Stud. 427–443 (2006)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.
29 van der Vossen, Bas, Associative Political Obligations: Their Potential, 6 Phil. Compass 488–496 (2011), at 490CrossRefGoogle Scholar.
30 Id. at 491–493.
31 Renzo, Massimo, Associative Responsibilities and Political Obligation, 62 Phil. Q. 106–127 (2012)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.
32 Associativists often and compellingly argue that an obligation to die for one's country can be understandable only as an associative obligation. This suggests to me that such an obligation is not a political one. Thus it might be that a necessary condition for claiming that someone has an obligation to die for her country (if or when such an obligations is justifiable) is that she actually endorses the values of patriotism and/or has the feelings of love that make this level of sacrifice intelligible. See Paul W. Kahn, Political Theology (2011), at 23–27.
33 The three main natural-duty theories are based in justice, consequences, and Samaritanism. They all argue for nonvoluntary and other-regarding obligations to support political order, and it is this commonality that is relevant here.
34 John A. Rawls, A Theory of Justice: Revised Edition (1999), at 99; Wellman, Christopher H., Toward a Liberal Theory of Political Obligation, 111 Ethics 735–759 (2001), at 744CrossRefGoogle Scholar.
35 Waldron, Jeremy, Special Ties and Natural Duties, 22 Phil. & Pub. Aff. 3–30 (1993)Google Scholar, at 15; Nagel, Thomas, The Problem of Global Justice, 33 Phil. & Pub. Aff. 113–147 (2005), at 133CrossRefGoogle Scholar.
36 See Buchanan, Allen, Justice as Reciprocity versus Subject-Centered Justice, 19 Phil. & Pub. Aff. 227–252 (1990)Google Scholar.
37 Note that the natural-duty approach is not bound to the existing state system as the only institutional means to securing political order.
38 See Wellman, Christopher H., Relational Facts in Liberal Political Theory: Is There Magic in the Pronoun “My”?, 110 Ethics 537–562 (2000)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Blake, Michael, Distributive Justice, State Coercion, and Autonomy, 30 Phil. & Pub. Aff. 257–296 (2001)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Nagel, supra note 35.
39 Renzo, Duties, supra note 3.
41 John Rawls, The Law of Peoples (1999), at 39.
42 Id. at 9.
43 See Renzo, Duties, supra note 3, at 193–217.
44 Rawls, Law, supra note 41, at 106.
45 See Lægaard, Sune, What Is the Right to Exclude Immigrants?, 16 Res Publica 245–262 (2010)CrossRefGoogle Scholar, especially at 260–262.
46 Goodin, supra note 21, at 684–686.
47 See id.
48 Id. at 685.
49 Wellman, Political, supra note 2, at 99.
50 Id. at 110–111; Finnis, John, Authority of Law in the Predicament of Contemporary Social Theory, 1 Notre Dame J.L. Ethics & Pub. Pol’y 115–137 (1984)Google Scholar.
51 See Wellman, Relational, supra note 38, at 544–545.
52 Klosko, Multiple, supra note 26.
53 Rawls, Theory, supra note 34, at 99–100.
54 See Klosko, Multiple, supra note 26, at 808–812.
55 Id. at 811.
56 Wellman, Political, supra note 2, at 106.
57 See Thomas M. Scanlon, What We Owe to Each Other (1998), at 189–247; Thomas Nagel, Equality and Partiality (1991), at 10–20, 41–52.
58 See Wenar, Leif, What We Owe to Distant Others, 2 Pol. Phil. & Econ. 283–304 (2003)CrossRefGoogle Scholar, at 287–291; Ashford, Elizabeth, The Demandingness of Scanlon's Contractualism, 113 Ethics 273–302 (2003)CrossRefGoogle Scholar.
59 See Garrett Cullity, The Moral Demands of Affluence (2006), at 128–166.
60 Waldron, supra note 35, at 30.
- 4
- Cited by