I. Introduction
Retributivism is commonly regarded as a position that glorifies human suffering, even if restricted to the suffering of the deserving. Welfare-oriented approaches, on the other hand, aim to preserve, enhance, promote, maximize, etc. human welfare or well-being. Taken in this oversimplified form, the two appear to be directly at odds with one another, where retributivism aims at human suffering while welfare-oriented approaches aim at its alleviation. A less caricaturized look at the positions, however, demonstrates that this opposition presents a false dichotomy. Yet, in the literature on punishment, this opposition is often relied on not only to advance false claims about retributive theory, but to argue for its displacement as a justification of punishment given the conflict.
Recent work on punishment that illustrates this common refrain includes monographs by Martha Nussbaum, Erin Kelly, and Vincent Chiao, which all, in defending a consequentialist outlook on punishment, assume a basic dichotomy between the aims of retribution and welfare.Footnote 1 This dichotomy then serves as a basis to argue against retributivism as a viable justification of punishment. In the following, I aim to challenge this received wisdom by looking more carefully at these antiretributive arguments and to demonstrate that the proposed welfare-oriented aims may be achieved without resorting to the abandonment of retribution. I present a picture of complementarity that invites welcoming the welfare-based criticism offered by critics, but denies that these provide grounds for rejecting retributivism. Further, I argue that the normative core that underlies interest in human welfare can itself be understood as underlying the very grounds of retributivism, allowing not only for potential complementarity, but for more robust congruence.
Section II sets forth the relevant line of objection against retributivism, which has recently received much support. Disentangling various arguments made within this line of objection, Section III identifies and addresses two central arguments advanced in the literature, which prove false: (1) that retributivism entails the rejection of welfare-promotion, and (2) that retributivists cannot object to harsh and cruel punishment nor to blatant injustices such as the injustices of mass incarceration. The section concludes by offering reasons to conceive of the projects of welfare-promotion and retributive punishment not only as potentially complementary projects, but as projects that emerge from the same set of normative commitments, though it does not aim to offer conclusive arguments to this effect.
Section IV then attempts to excavate the underlying concerns that may rest beneath the surface of these arguments, offering alternative welfare-oriented arguments that may be and have been raised against retributivism: primarily, the traditional concern with retributivism's endorsement of the goodness of suffering. It elucidates the myriad ways in which retributive theories need not be (and often are not) committed to the intrinsic goodness claim, and proposes that in fact, retributive views generally do not attribute intrinsic goodness to suffering. Section V concludes that while tensions remain, the proposed line of argument against retributivism fails.Footnote 2
II. The Line of Objection
Contemporary retributive thought has flourished since the 1970s. The so-called retributivist revival has seen an outpouring of in-depth engagement with different strains of retributive thought, which attempt to carefully address myriad aspects of punitivity and defend an ultimately desert-based justification of punishment.Footnote 3 While retributivism encompasses a plurality of views, central to this set of views is the contention that the punishment of the deserving is right or good, and that punishment is justified in terms of the desert of the agent.Footnote 4 Retributivism is, of course, not alone in endorsing punishment, that is, in endorsing the deliberate imposition of burdens, deprivations, or suffering on wrongdoers in response to their wrongs.Footnote 5 Despite the welfare-inhibiting implications of such endorsement, all nonabolitionist views, including retributivism's traditional consequentialist competitors, endorse such imposition.Footnote 6 However, to ground punishment's justification, competitors rely on the nonretributive goods that punishment has the capacity to produce, such as deterrence, incapacitation, and rehabilitation, while retributivism alone relies on the normative force of desert.
From the outset, such revival has been accompanied by a broad range of critical reactions that have produced a counter-literature to match the rise of retributive theory.Footnote 7 Recently, however, a particular line of objection has emerged as a dominant theme in antiretributivist writings, in the center of which stands the presumption that if we care about human well-being or welfare,Footnote 8 retributivism must be rejected.Footnote 9
Current interest in human welfare and well-being in the context of punishment follows a much-needed resurgence of political interest in the harshness of our punitive systems, not least of which the American criminal justice system. This includes concern with solitary confinement, life without parole, prison suicide rates, and more particular to the American context, mass incarceration and the reproduction of patterns of enslavement and racial discrimination, to name just a few ills. Public interest in the welfare of persons, including that of the incarcerated, has redirected attention toward the need to cure the ills of the system.Footnote 10 These are welcome cries. And one hopes they will motivate change and reform and produce better and more humane systems of criminal law and punishment. Retributive theory can in fact provide a bulwark against many such ills, and can serve as a resource in the fight for their eradication.
However, reasons to protest and the targets of protest can and have unfortunately come apart. Not for the first time in history, the interest in care, compassion, mitigation, welfare, and well-being has led to an attack on retributivism. Retributivism is targeted as an ill or, more brazenly, a cause to be eradicated if we are to move forward toward a more humane criminal law.
Some of these attacks are attacks against rhetoric: that the language and dissemination of retributive ideas and concepts have generated harsh systems of criminal punishment, independent of the merits of retributive views. James Whitman and Erin Kelly, for example, attack the language of blame and retribution, arguing that “crying blame” does more harm than good, and is responsible for the excessively punitive state of American criminal justice.Footnote 11 They predict, though it appears no more than a mere (yet adamant) guess, that abandoning such language will make the system more humane and moderate. Here the argument is empirical, though not backed by empirical evidence beyond gestures toward correlations between the two, without any consideration of how the harshness of punishment correlates with other legitimating narratives and rhetorics of punishment.Footnote 12 But the merits of these arguments are to be empirically tested and are not the subject of this article.
More to the point, the arguments are also often an attack on substance: that the substance of retributivism and what it has to offer as a justification of punishment is at odds with valuing welfare, and that, as above, if human welfare or well-being is valuable, retributivism must be abandoned.Footnote 13 It is to this set of arguments that this article turns to demonstrate that the constructed opposition has no basis. This point should be evident from the fact that many contemporary retributivists would demand the very reforms that critics seem to believe retributivism must be laid waste to, to promote. But it is not. This paper is therefore intended to set the record straight.
At the base of the paper lies the insight that promoting the well-being of persons, on the one hand, and retributive responses to wrongdoing, on the other, can arise from the same normative commitments, and should be viewed as complementary projects that emerge from a single worldview. The paper is directly occupied, however, with engaging with particular objections to retributivism and demonstrating that they fail, independent of whether the deeper normative picture presented is endorsed. It parses out the ways in which retributivism and welfare orientation are, contrary to what seems to be common belief, quite simply happy bedfellows.
III. Two False Objections
The project of this article is thus to demonstrate the consistency of welfare orientation and retribution. This consistency is denied at a number of points throughout the antiretributive literature, which are not always kept apart. It will be important to clarify each of the relevant objections, which offer different focal points for grounding the rejection of retributivism, in order to adequately address the concerns each may raise. To anticipate, these include the claims that:
1. promoting (ex ante) welfare-oriented goals and projects requires rejecting retributivism;
2. opposing welfare-destroying and unjust practices, particularly mass incarceration, requires rejecting retributivism;
3. a commitment to human welfare excludes the possibility of endorsing retributivism.
In this section, I address the first two lines of argument, which I take to be weaker arguments against retributivism. I begin by illustrating examples of prominent work that promotes these arguments, taking some time to demonstrate the way the constructed opposition figures in arguments about punishment, before explaining the fallacies and misunderstandings that sustain them. In the next section, I identify what I take to be deeper underlying concerns about the tensions between retributivism and welfare-orientation that may underlie such rejections of retributivism. I argue that when pressed, these too come undone, and explore possible tensions that remain. Ultimately, I aim to demonstrate that this line of objection does not provide grounds for rejecting retributivism.
A. Retribution vs. Welfare-Promotion
1. Substantive Inconsistency
One claim prevalent in the contemporary antiretributive literature is the argument that to endorse welfare-oriented projects, we have to give up on retribution. Martha Nussbaum's Anger and Forgiveness is a prime example of the literature that trades in this false dichotomy. The book presents promoting welfare and justice, on the one hand, and retribution, on the other, as mutually exclusive options that are in direct conflict with one another, where opting for a future, welfare-oriented approach requires abandoning anger and retribution in favor of love and an exclusively future-looking program.Footnote 14 While Nussbaum is interested in the emotional side of anger, integral to her argument is a rejection of the normative basis of retributivism, which she takes to be an integral part of the concept of anger—“the idea that it would be a good thing if the wrongdoer suffers some bad consequence.”Footnote 15 She conceives of forward-looking punishment as a replacement for anger and retribution, where deterrence is to be pursued “rather than payback.”Footnote 16 The abandonment of the project of retribution is, on her view, necessary for the progression to a just, welfare-oriented resolution to the problem of wrongdoing.Footnote 17
Vincent Chiao's Criminal Law in the Age of the Administrative State also understands retributive commitments to be at odds with a welfare-oriented approach. While the monograph's positive proposal is concerned with promoting a particular justice-oriented approach to criminal law, its negative proposal presumes that the adoption of any such approach requires the abandonment of retributive and other such desert-oriented, “private morality,” “backward-looking,” or “strict deontological” approaches to punishment.Footnote 18 This is evident, for example, in Chiao's analysis of DeShaney v. Winnebago County Department of Social Services,Footnote 19 with which he opens and closes the first chapter.Footnote 20 In DeShaney, the Court addressed the case of a boy who had been physically abused by his father over a period of time during which he was not removed from his home, at the end of which the boy was severely injured. The boy and his mother sued the state of Wisconsin for its failure to remove the boy from the father's home, despite prolonged evidence of abuse, and its failure to protect the boy from abuse. The Court, in both instances, found for the defendant, alleging that the state had no duty to protect the child, though it did have a duty to punish the perpetrator ex post. Chiao rightly criticizes the Court for its austere approach, defending only the state's duty to punish without recognizing its duty to protect or provide other ex ante services, which per the Court are provided by the state at its own discretion. Chiao, however, allies retributive views with the DeShaney Court's position, positing a conflict between retributivism and welfare provision.Footnote 21 The analysis polarizes the views by positing that theoretically (not just budgetarily) one has to choose—either one thinks ex post punishment is what is needed, or one recognizes the state's ex ante welfare obligations of protection. On Chiao's analysis, one cannot defend both.Footnote 22 A focus on ex ante schemes for the promotion of welfare is assumed to be inaccessible to a view that would offer a famed “backward-looking” perspective on the justification of punishment.
This mutual inconsistency of retribution and welfare-promotion is similar to that posited by Nussbaum, according to which either we care about the social determinants of crime and its alleviation in the form, inter alia, of early intervention in education, nutrition, welfare provision, etc. or we care about holding people retributively accountable for their wrongs. This, however, is to demonize retributivism in unwarranted ways that hark back to the critique of retributivism as committed to the inflation of wrongdoing: for, or so the argument goes, if the suffering of the deserving is intrinsically good, then the retributivist should be committed to hoping for more crime to allow for more retribution.Footnote 23 Cleary, however, the initial wrongdoing is as detested by a retributivist as it is by the welfarist or pluralist-consequentialist (and possibly more so, if we focus not merely on the objection to loss but to the wrong as well). To the extent that the wrongfulness and harmfulness of wrongdoing can be avoided by investing in welfare-enhancing projects that not only help persons facing difficulties, but have the further advantage of preventing future crime and alleviating social ills, this certainly can be desirable on a retributivist picture. A commitment to holding persons accountable ex post in no way undermines the grounds for being committed to addressing human needs and challenges ex ante. (In fact, the grounds of the former may dictate that we ought to promote the latter, as I shall suggest in Section III.C below.)
What is crucial to undermine this line of attack against retributivism is to see that retributive commitments do not interfere with the case for expanding public protection, education, health services, etc., or with a general pro-welfare-provision approach to state responsibilities. While the backward-looking approach to punishment is indispensable on any retributive view, the retributivist can also endorse Nussbaum's charge that “society should take an ex ante perspective, analyzing the whole problem of crime and searching for the best strategies to address it going forward.” What will determine whether one endorses this view will depend, however, not on one's retributive commitments, but on one's conception of the proper scope of the state.
This line of objection thus seems to confuse the retributivist commitment to punishment with a political conception of the state as restricted to the function of punishing. That is, the view that the authors appear to be justified in opposing is one that restricts the legitimate scope of political intervention to punitive measures, whereas, on their conceptions of justice, the state should be engaged in a far broader set of welfare and justice-promoting projects beyond those that can be achieved by the punitive. In other words, they oppose a minimal, or night-watchman state. Importantly, however, there is no clear allegiance between a minimal conception of the state and a retributive conception of punishment. If anything, one would think that a minimal state would steer clear of morally charged interventions that depend on a moral rather than political conception of wrongdoing, or that aim at aligning the lives of wrongdoers with an ideal moral state (whereby wrongdoers “get what they deserve”).Footnote 24 It would rather restrict itself, one supposes, to a consequentialist defense of social stability—of “keeping the peace”—a project that appears far more consistent with a political conception that endorses a minimal state (aimed merely at securing the basic conditions for civil coexistence).Footnote 25
More importantly, the commitment to retributive punishment does not ground a commitment to a minimal state. Rather, it leaves open the question of the scope and authorities of the state, while retributivism can be consistent with even a radically expansive conception of the state that sets its sights on bettering the opportunities and situations of all those in need, so long as the duty of retributive punishment is among the responsibilities that the state is understood to be required to bear and carry out.
To put the point in terms more particular to the allegations made, while certain punitive means might be ruled out by retributivism (e.g., incarcerating the innocent) to achieve benefits such as protection against victimization,Footnote 26 the retributive commitment to the punishment of the deserving does not rule out most of the penal interventions defended by Chiao, including public policing, investment in prevention, social services monitoring, and early intervention, all of which might be provided to protect against victimization. Nor does it rule out the broader welfare-oriented interventions supported by Nussbaum, including nutrition, education, health care, housing, and employment. In fact, the best retributive views can be understood to be grounded in the same principles that underlie these projects, in terms of the need to respect the equal worth of persons: the former via ex ante means of providing the opportunity to live in ways that are consistent with such worth, and the latter via ex post appropriate reactions to the actions of others that violate such worth. Thus the first argument against retributivism fails.
2. Inconsistent Psychologically?
While Nussbaum's argument is plausibly read as an argument about the substantive inconsistency of retribution and welfare orientation, there is an alternative version of the argument that may yet survive: one that focuses on human psychology rather than substantive inconsistency. That is, her argument can be read as proposing that as a matter of human psychology, one can either focus on the future, love, and welfare, or focus on the past, anger, and retribution, but one cannot contain both. On this understanding, even if there is no principled reason not to view welfare-promotion and retribution as complimentary projects in an ethical system or a system of justice, human psychology renders the commitment to these projects mutually exclusive, i.e., people are either angry or compassionate, interested in retribution or welfare. This worry is reinforced by a simple glance at the political arena, wherein “tough-on-crime” and social-welfare camps are generally politically opposed. Thus, given the choice between these two psychologically exclusive moral outlooks, we should endorse the latter and abandon the former (presumably as a necessary psychological step toward fully embracing the latter).
This psychologically grounded argument seems at least to have more plausibility than the substantive variant. Yet it relies on an empirical picture that Nussbaum does not exert effort to support, and that seems to be undermined by daily experience. That is, perhaps Nussbaum is right about her conjecture (and I expect that every reader will have had acquaintance with people who appear to polarize in this way). But perhaps she is not; perhaps these are caricatures that fail to appreciate the deep tensions that can be and are borne by the human condition and multitextured human psychologies. Even in the political context, major political movements in fact endorse both modes of interaction, though often with respect to different target groups. Consider feminist concerns for care and compassion that are coupled with calls for increasing punitive accountability with respect to sexual and domestic crime. The insistence on promoting well-being and the insistence on accountability are not mutually exclusive psychological options, but perspectives appealed to where we perceive a lack of responsiveness to each. Both environment (or predicament) and agency are important factors that play a role in the way we respond to wrongdoing. Though we may instinctively focus more quickly on the “wrongdoer as victim” in some contexts and “wrongdoer as agent” in others, the capacity to be responsive to both these perspectives is apparent, while a prereflective attraction to one perspective rather than another provides no reason to abandon the project of aiming to address all morally relevant aspects of wrongdoing, requiring the appreciation of both. Each brings important moral factors to bear on the way in which we respond to others: those that call for holding offenders to account for their culpable behavior, and those that require the appreciation of the social factors and patterns associated with crime, and of the persons disadvantaged by these as victims, even if also perpetrators of wrongs against victims.
In fact, personal reflection of the kind invited by Nussbaum on the many relationships we have with others would seem to further demonstrate that we are far more nuanced and psychologically pluralistic than the picture she presents would allow. Many people are not “angry, period;” or “compassionate, period.” Susan Wolf's compelling depiction of “blame, Italian-style” is an expression of the central place anger can have in relationships structured by love and care, which themselves can elicit anger when those whom we love act in ways we cannot accept.Footnote 27 This depiction demonstrates that Nussbaum's suggestion that anger and retribution must be displaced to clear the way for love and compassion straightjackets the human emotional and moral life into a singular picture that is far from persuasive.Footnote 28
If then human psychology does not rule out pursuing a moral worldview that endorses retributivism and welfare orientation, a defense of the latter does not serve to displace the former.Footnote 29
B. Retributivism and Mass Incarceration
1. Placing Blame
Another set of arguments marshalled against retributivism revolves around the alleged relation between retributivism and harsh and unjust punishment. Arguments in this regard have centered around the phenomenon of mass incarceration, which, per some critics, is a product of retributivism, and per others, retributivists cannot oppose, such that to move forward and overcome excessive harshness and mass incarceration, we must, once again, abandon retributivism.
Mass incarceration is a phenomenon that refers, inter alia, to the problem of the sheer number of persons incarcerated in the United States, which is higher in absolute and per capita numbers than in any other nation in the world (at a rate that is five to ten times higher than that of other liberal democracies, and five times higher than that in the United States a generation ago). But it only begins there. The racial core of mass incarceration and its profound impact on young, black men is well documented, as is the impact of mass incarceration on black communities, the social stigmatization of color, and its role in the relegation of entire swaths of the population to a social underclass, which predicts the repetition of current patterns of social disadvantage.
The first of this set of arguments alleges that retributivism is responsible for harsh, excessive, oppressive aspects of criminal justice systems, including mass incarceration. These and a host of other ills are attributed to retributivism's influence on the criminal “justice” system. Thus, it is argued that to move forward to a more humane, welfare-oriented, just system of punishment, we must eradicate the retributive idea and its influence on systems of criminal punishment.
Erin Kelly defends such a claim, contending, at times explicitly, at times implicitly, that retributivism is responsible for many of the ills she identifies in the criminal justice system, including “massive suffering,” “excessive and degrading” punishment, and racial discrimination.Footnote 30 She blames retributive and blame-oriented theories as inadequate justifications of punishment and the language and public narrative of blame used to legitimize punitive practices. Her criticism of these is not unconnected: she thinks of the logic of blame and retribution as “stretched” to justify a massively overreaching punitive system (and as a natural inflation of these substantive ideas rather than a case of their illegitimate usurpation for independent political purposes). Kelly advances a concrete causal claim: that the language and theorizing of retribution and blame are responsible for many of the system's injustices. Kelly asserts that were we to eradicate these ideas, the system would be improved and become more humane and moderate.Footnote 31 Thus a commitment to humaneness and moderation begs the rejection of retribution.
Kelly here relies on James Whitman's attribution of American harshness and punitiveness to retribution,Footnote 32 and her work is later echoed, for example, by Ekow Yankah, who takes the charge a step further. Yankah takes retributivism to be the dominant justification of American criminal justice, a fact he takes to be revealed, inter alia, in none other than the phenomenon of mass incarceration itself.Footnote 33 “The American experience with mass incarceration,” he writes, “vastly disproportionate to any sensibly consequential or rehabilitative value of prison, reveals the retributivism at the heart of our system,” an allegeation made in apparent obliviousness to its glaring disproportionality within a retributive theory system of thought.Footnote 34 He takes retributive thought, at the heart of the system, to be responsible for much of the havoc wreaked on individuals, communities, and minority groups by way of the criminal legal system, and unavoidably so: mass incarceration, he argues, is both an “inexorable” and “predictable” outcome of a commitment to a retributive system of thought.Footnote 35 Echoing sentiments present in the work of Nussbaum, Kelly, and Chiao, he writes: “The simple point is that without addressing our retributivist commitments, there is no way forward on mass incarceration.”Footnote 36
These are tall accusations, and if successful, would provide grounds for rejecting retributivism.Footnote 37 But there are reasons to doubt the plausibility of such claims.Footnote 38 For one, empirical evidence is not offered to back the causal claims, beyond motioning in the direction of correlations between “the rise of the retributive justice movement” and the exacerbation of such ills.Footnote 39 Empirical evidence in such contexts is of course notoriously difficult to establish, yet there are further reasons to seriously doubt that retributive thought and justification and the legitimating narrative of retribution are in fact to blame for the harshness of American criminal justice. First, despite the rise of retributive theory within contemporary Anglo-American philosophical circles, retributive thought has not had nearly as significant an impact on American law and criminal doctrine as such criticisms suppose.Footnote 40 To cite a number of examples, the influential Model Penal Code places greater emphasis on the standard of dangerousness than on an ethic of desert,Footnote 41 while the Sentencing Guidelines, famed for their influence on excessive and lengthy criminal sentences, fail to take account of the many retributive factors that would affect (and mitigate) sentencing, while attributing decisive significance only to criminal record (primarily as an indicator of dangerousness) and severity (which is relevant on almost any view, retributive, deterrence-based, or otherwise).Footnote 42 In other words, retributivism is not the dominant system of thought that underlies American criminal law, even if it is a salient rhetoric utilized in the political sphere, and thus would be hard pressed to be responsible for a system that has largely ignored its contentions.Footnote 43 By comparison, the German criminal legal system, which is doctrinally more committed to culpability-based principles of punishment, has emerged as a far more moderate system, further undermining the contention that retributive principles inevitably produce harsh justice.
Though a question of political discourse rather than punishment theory, there is also reason to doubt that retributive language and rhetoric are in any way responsible for the current state of affairs. Kelly is right that retributive rhetoric has been mobilized in the political arena to advance the case for harsher punishments. Yet the trope of dangerousness has similarly played a salient role in mobilizing American punitiveness (a point that need not be established as against, e.g., Kelly herself, who refers repeatedly to the centrality of idioms of dangerousness and images such as that of the to-be-feared “Super-Predator” in the American legal context).Footnote 44 In fact, the “lock ’em up” mentality Kelly hopes to destabilize as well as the policies she attacks, from three-strikes laws to incarceration as a standard mode of punishment, are even more consistent with a logic and language of dangerousness than that of blame and retribution. Why—one might ask—would we throw people in a cell and throw away the key? One answer that might present itself is: because “they” are not moral agents like the rest of “us” to be engaged with and held accountable as per retributive theory, but rather, radical “others,” too dangerous to be allowed to remain on “our” streets. Kelly rightly objects to categorizations such as “social psychopath” and “pedophile,” and one might add “criminal” and “felon” to the list of essentializing categorizations that enable excessive punitiveness. But these categories mark out wrongdoers as stigmatized others regardless of whether it is their being “to blame” (deserving) or “evil,” or alternatively, “dangerous” or “sick,” that demands their removal. One wonders therefore whether the current state of American criminal law tells more of the hydraulics of aggression than the malignance of retribution.
In fact, retributivism is opposed to many of the very features that Kelly opposes: excessive and degrading punishment, racial discrimination, and the relegation of wrongdoers to a social underclass are all inconsistent with a retributive ethic, which defends the imposition of proportionate punishment only on the deserving and only to the extent of their desert. This congruity seems to offer ripe grounds for theorists of all stripes, nonretributivists and retributivists alike, to view each other as allies in a joint enterprise of opposing the ills of the system, which they mutually regard as targets, rather than as foes engaged in mutually exclusive projects. This is yet another opportunity for complementarity where the resources of welfare-oriented and retributive approaches can both be drawn upon to limit excessive punitiveness and take punishment “forward.”Footnote 45 Ironically however, the choice has been to cry blame, pointing a finger at retributivism rather than joining forces to combat these ills.Footnote 46
2. Barring Objections
Another rendition of the connection between retributivism and harsh and oppressive punishment alleges that retributivism, even if not responsible for mass incarceration, cannot oppose it. That is, it is claimed that another good that is unavailable to the retributivist is the ability to criticize oppressive and unjust punishment (other than where the injustice inheres in a deviation from retributive principles).
Chiao, for example, argues that one can either affirm that mass incarceration is a problem, or endorse deontological theories such as (strict deontological) retributivism, but one cannot do both.Footnote 47 On Chiao's conception, this is because it is plausible that each person incarcerated in the United States deserves punishment in the retributive sense, while retributivism does not have the resources to recognize that punishment can be oppressive under conditions where, individually, each person is receiving their “just deserts.”Footnote 48
If Chiao's claim, a claim echoed in other contemporary attacks on retributivism,Footnote 49 were true, and one could not endorse a critical view of mass incarceration, this would once again be a real blow to retributive theory.Footnote 50 However, first, Chiao underestimates the resources available to the retributivist to object to mass incarceration. Per the analysis offered, retributive theory cannot point to any injustice that might lie in the sheer quantity of persons incarcerated in the United States, a significant feature of the phenomenon of mass incarceration, though by no means its most objectionable. Yet while a retributive theory of the type envisioned by Chiao cannot capture all of the injustices encompassed by this complex phenomenon, it can at least explain more than Chiao is willing to concede. For example, noting the relativity of the case for injustice in the numbers, as well as the historical patterns of discrimination reproduced in mass incarceration, can easily shed light on how retributive theories alone can point to the injustices latent in the system.Footnote 51
The very idea that there are too many people incarcerated in the United States is not an absolute claim, but a relative one. Nearly every empirical rendering of the ills of mass incarceration, including that presented by Chiao, highlights the quantity and ratio of incarcerated persons in the United States as compared to the numbers of incarcerated persons in other liberal and nonliberal states. What is horrifying, or at least one thing that is horrifying, is US exceptionalism in this regard. If one presumes that at least some other systems are broadly invested in the significance of desert, noting this difference is reason to suspect that the United States may be going very wrong even exclusively on a retributive account.Footnote 52
Moreover, as noted in Chiao's work, much evidence demonstrates that patterns of incarceration in the United States mimic patterns of plantation enslavement and historical patterns of discrimination against the black population.Footnote 53 The reproduction of these patterns is reason enough, even on a strict deontological view, to suspect that the US system is rife with injustice.Footnote 54
But suppose that Chiao is correct—that such theories cannot point to any injustice in the quantity of persons incarcerated in America. Even if we accept that all the incarcerated are also robustly guilty as proposed by Chiao, is this a problem for retributive theory or reason to reject it? Chiao insists that it is.Footnote 55 Yet retributivism does not offer the comprehensive moral account that the argument against retributivism presumes. Retributivism aims to offer a justification of punishment, that is, an account of the rightness or goodness of deliberately imposing harm on others in response to their wrongs that turns to the desert of the agent to explain how the prima facie objection to the deliberate imposition of harm in the context of punishment is overcome, while reasons in favor of imposing such punishment are generated. But it does not aim to offer a comprehensive account of all moral value or duties, and so needs not have the resources to address every possible moral calamity or offer grounds for criticism thereof, even in the context of punishment. Imposing undeserved punishment simply is not the only thing that can go wrong with punishment. Deserved punishment can be manipulatively imposed, exploitative, oppressive, discriminatory, etc.
The possibility of these forms of injustices is not ruled out by retributive theory, nor is an account of them provided by retributive theory. To obtain a comprehensive answer to the question of when and under what conditions punishment is justified one needs not only a theory of desert, which licenses punishment and generates reason in favor of punishing, as well as a pro tanto duty to punish, but also theories of exploitation, oppression, discrimination, and other wrongs, the violation of which might render even deserved punishment unjustifiably imposed, as well as an account of how different moral duties interact. Developing the contours of any of these may be seen as complementary to the project of developing the contours of retributivism, such that if retributive theory fails to capture what is wrong with some aspects of the phenomenon of mass incarceration, this need not be to its detriment. Other ills may occur.
C. Taking Stock and Moving Forward
What both of the above sets of failed arguments against retributivism appear to assume is ethical or political monism: that on a retributive view the only thing that can matter is retributive right or good, to the detriment of all else, possibly even where the pursuit of other aims does not conflict with pursuing retribution.Footnote 56 Against this caricature of the retributivist position emerges the claim that if we care about welfare, being humane, oppression, or injustice, we must abandon retributivism. But retributivism is not committed to ignoring all other moral concerns.Footnote 57 (Nor are any retributivists committed to ignoring all other moral concerns.) In fact, its commitment to punishment may be understood to emerge from the very normative grounds that underlie welfare orientation and what Nussbaum refers to as “care.”
While the refrain has been that to care about persons we must eschew retributivism, it is in fact care about persons and an unwillingness to fall to indifference and immunity in the face of attacks against persons, their welfare, and other humanistic goods and values (e.g., autonomy, equality, rights, etc., all of which Nussbaum and others take to be part of an expansive conception of welfare) that provide the best grounds for retributive punishment.
The retributive charge to punish is grounded in recognition of the special moral concern with culpable wrongdoing, that is, primarily, with manifest disrespect for persons, their welfare, their interests, and their rights.Footnote 58 In this sense, it might be understood to be an ex post analog of the ex ante commitment to promoting such goods and values. To view each and every person as an individual bearer of irreducible, equal worth, is to take human well-being and its cognates to be ends worth protecting and enhancing.Footnote 59 In a parallel vein, to view each and every person as an individual bearer of irreducible, equal worth, would, one supposes, also lead to taking special interest in voluntary attacks against these goods and values and attempts to interfere with human flourishing.Footnote 60 This, one might suggest, is precisely what lies at the root of the call for retributive punishment, a response that rejects and responds negatively and burdensomely to actions that fly in the face of respect for persons, their well-being, or their interests. Blame and retributive punishment can thus be ways of valuing and caring about persons and humanistic goods and values,Footnote 61 while retributivism and welfare orientation can be understood to be grounded in the same normative source materials, such that if one allows a nonminimal state, taking a position in favor of one is reason to endorse the other.
The classic consequentialist position has of course been to insist that in the face of crime, prevention and addressing the future is sufficient, to the exclusion of a retributive response. Critics insist that we should address the problem of wrongdoing ex ante and invest in projects that would make everyone better off, rather than focusing on the past. And undoubtably, prevention of future losses and wrongs is of the utmost concern. Yet the retributivist is well positioned to adopt just this concern for the future and prevention as part of her broader picture, while arguably it is deep care for persons and their well-being that calls not only for looking forward and preventing future crime, but insisting on the irreducible significance of the attacks themselves. Notice that forward-looking responses only address attacks as occasions or opportunities to engage in projects that we already have reason to pursue (presumably, to take Nussbaum's example, we should be raising campus awareness about sexual assault, but this is true independent of whether a sexual assault has just occurred). Exclusively addressing the future, on the other hand, means that we do not take the attacks against human goods and values—that is, this attack, this wrong, this failure of regard—to be independently worthy of our attention and care.
Yet it is unclear why the time barrier should afford such immunity. True enough, we cannot change the past. But it is misleading to suggest that the only thing relevant to the future is the future. Our present and future are shaped by the way we understand and relate to the past, where we can change the meaning of a past event for the future by addressing it as a collectively recognized culpable wrong perpetrated by a responsible agent. The animating idea behind retributivism is that if we truly care or attribute significance to what has happened, we must respond negatively to the culpable wrong, holding the culpable wrongdoer responsible for her disrespectful action, and not merely look to dealing with the future.
This is not an argument for any necessary connection between welfare orientation and retributivism. The question of what it takes to address past wrongs adequately is a fraught one, and Nussbaum, for example, asserts that while accountability for the past is necessary for moving forward, retribution is not.Footnote 62 The nonretributivist may thus reject the further commitments that may be necessary to arrive at a defense of retributive punishment.Footnote 63 The point is rather that that the two might be understood to be derivable from common normative precepts that allow positing a deep affinity between the two rather than the necessary opposition posited by the discussed line of objection.
(One suspects that what often lies behind the rejection of retributivism is not, then, the contrived conflict between welfare orientation and retribution, but rather a rejection of the premises of retributive punishment, namely moral responsibility and the culpability of the agent being blamed and punished. While the free will debate is beyond the scope of this paper, suffice it to say that while absence of responsibility is reason to reject retributive punishment, welfare orientation is not.)
D. Summation
Whether or not one accepts the argument for the normative connectedness of welfare orientation and retribution, we have thus far demonstrated that the welfare-oriented arguments raised by critics against retribution fail: the retributivist is able both to support welfare-promoting projects and to criticize harsh, oppressive practices.
IV. Retribution and Suffering
A. Retributivism and the Intrinsic Value of Suffering
While the above accusations against retributivism fail to provide grounds for its rejection, there nonetheless seems to be a deeper tension between retribution and welfare that underlies the line of objection that posits their incompatibility. This tension might be captured by the less patently false accusation that it is the commitment to human welfare that excludes the possibility of endorsing retributivism. Here the problem lies in the prosuffering attitude attributed to retributive theory. As addressed earlier, a welfare-oriented approach is committed to the value and promotion of human welfare, whereas retributive theory is understood to attribute intrinsic value to human suffering. If this is the case, then welfare orientation, even if it does not monistically attribute value only to welfare, may exclude the possibility of endorsing retributivism given the direct conflict between retribution and the welfare of wrongdoers. It is worth noting that it is not the very justification of punishment that raises these worries, as all nonabolitionist, welfare-oriented approaches, including the approaches endorsed by all the critics discussed here, endorse the institution of punishment. That is, they too offer accounts that take the deliberate imposition of burdens, deprivations, or suffering to be a justifiable enterprise. Yet retributivism alone is taken to offer a justification of punishment that is founded on the intrinsic rather than instrumental value of human suffering.
We thus arrive at the concern that is at the heart of many classic and contemporary objections to retributivism and may supply the greatest motivation to reject retributivism as a theory of punishment. It is what underlies Hart's concern with retribution as “a mysterious piece of moral alchemy, in which the two evils of moral wickedness and suffering are transmuted into good.”Footnote 64 It is the concern that underlies John Gardner's skepticism with respect to retributive justification, Thomas Scanlon's relation to retributivism as “morally repugnan[t],”Footnote 65 Victor Tadros's attack against retributivism as “barbaric,”Footnote 66 as well as many similar charges.Footnote 67 As straightforwardly articulated by Tadros, retributivism is necessarily in conflict with “a basic concern that I hold dear—that the lives of all people . . . go well.” Articulating a deep skepticism about the moral credentials of retributive theory, he continues: “Few claims need more defence than the [retributive] claim that the suffering of other human beings is impersonally valuable.”Footnote 68
Suffering, one might say, is tolerated by other views, whereas it is valued by retributivism, at least in the context of punishment. Herein lies the heart of the problem: that to endorse retributivism requires accepting a view that takes human suffering to be “good” or of value, which is precisely what those committed to the value of human welfare would deny.
Or so the oversimplified rendition of retributivism alleges. Careful attention to contemporary retributive theory demonstrates that this simple articulation of the conflict between retributivism and welfare fails to capture the richness of retributive theory and may misunderstand it altogether. In either case, the ousting of retributivism given its conflict with welfare would turn out to be unnecessary or unmotivated, whether because the relevant objection applies only to a subset of retributive justifications of punishment, leaving viable options on the justificatory table, or because contemporary retributivism turns out not to be vulnerable to the relevant charge at all.
To anticipate, in the following I offer three related clarifications intended to unravel this direct conflict between retribution and welfare orientation. First, I clarify that retributive justification can rely on deontic rather than axiological claims, that is, the duty to punish or reasons to punish rather than on any value attributed to suffering. Second, I clarify that axiological retributivism often attributes intrinsic value to an object other than suffering. Third, I clarify that even those views that attribute intrinsic value to “deserved suffering” ought not to be understood as attributing value to human suffering simpliciter.
I anticipate that some will take these clarifications to be “acrobatics” intended to formally escape a conclusion that remains substantively true: that however the retributivist may sugarcoat it, she is ultimately committed to the goodness of human suffering. The problem with this response, however, is that it fails to appreciate that few contemporary retributivists endorse the view that is attacked by this line of objection. If that is right, the objection strikes down a caricature of retributive thought (though not necessarily a strawman, if one takes account of all retributive theories) and makes no progress with respect to the question of whether we should endorse or reject retributivism and retributive punishment. This I take to be sufficient to undermine this relevant line of objection.
One point worth highlighting before we proceed: antiretributivists tend to be highly concerned with the value and glorification of suffering attributed to retributivism, where suffering presumably refers to a negative, subjective experience associated with a diminution in well-being. Yet many contemporary retributive accounts directly justify the imposition of burdens and deprivations rather than suffering, where these are not conceived as instruments for the imposition of suffering, but rather as that which is to be imposed. For example, on some accounts, criminal punishment is after deprivations of liberty and other central rights, rather than the suffering that might accompany such deprivations, while other accounts take censure and condemnation to be that which is deserved.Footnote 69 Thus, the charges made against at least some retributive theories are uncharitable. While important retributive accounts do endorse a suffering-oriented articulation, globally rejecting retributivism on grounds of its prosuffering attitude is often inaccurate if not altogether invalid. (Criticisms may of course be rearticulated in terms of objecting to burdens and deprivations, yet at least some of the visceral purchase of objecting to “suffering” would presumably be lost.) Nonetheless, I proceed in terms most charitable to the critic to see if the arguments against retributivism survive even if it is articulated in terms of suffering.
1. Deontic Retributivism
Many retributive views rely on an intrinsic goodness claim to justify punishment, whether about the intrinsic goodness of deserved suffering or punishment. On such views, whereas we have prima facie reason to believe that a practice that involves the deliberate imposition of suffering is morally bad, in fact, it is morally good. This is an axiological claim, i.e., a claim about value, which is generally taken to have deontic implications, that is, implications for the question of how we ought to act (e.g., for the permissibility of punishment, for reasons in favor of punishment, or for a duty to punish). For example, consider the retributive theory defended by Michael Moore.Footnote 70 Per Moore's account, the punishment of the deserving is intrinsically good. (Moore is perhaps the foremost contemporary defender of this claim and its centrality within retributive thought.)Footnote 71 Further, one ought to promote this retributive good and impose deserved punishment where there are no constraints against its imposition (e.g., liberty constraints, which limit the permissibility of state promotion of this good). In the absence of such constraints, Moore takes the failure to impose deserved punishment to be not only bad, but derivatively unjust. In other words, Moore offers an instrumentalist rendition of retributivist justification, whereby the retributive duty to punish is grounded on an intrinsic goodness claim.
On some retributive views, however, the justification of punishment does not rely on an axiological claim about the goodness of punishment or suffering. Rather, punishment is taken to be right or just, while the burdensomeness or suffering involved in punishment is taken to be constitutive of the right, and thus rightly imposed.Footnote 72 In other words, on these thoroughly deontic versions of retributivism, a claim about the rightness, justice, reason in favor of or duty to punish is endorsed, yet it is not derived from an axiological claim about the intrinsic goodness of suffering or punishment.Footnote 73 Thus, one can endorse a retributive account whereby there is reason or a duty to impose punishment (1) even though suffering is bad , (2) even if suffering is bad, and (3) altogether independent of the question of the badness of suffering, since such reason or duty is grounded in further deontic claims (or in axiological claims that are not about the value of suffering). In any case, on these accounts, retributive punishment is justified without being based on a commitment to the relevant “prosuffering” attitude alleged to be at the foundation of any retributivist account. They of course endorse punishment; but recall: so does our critic. Thus the rejection of retributivism tout court on grounds of the conflict between welfare orientation and retribution fails. Retributivism does not necessarily rely on a conception of human suffering as intrinsically valuable.
2. Intrinsic Goodness of What
Taking this last point seriously should neutralize the relevant worry for some, who are attracted to the force of desert, yet hesitate to adopt a retributive perspective on punishment owing to worries about entertaining a view that sees suffering as “good.” It warrants mentioning, however, that this option will not satisfy (or be available to) consequentialists insofar as they are committed to the priority of the good over the right (though the objection to retribution would no longer inhere in the so-called perverse presumption that human suffering is good). Further, the question arises as to whether all axiologically grounded versions of retributivism, which seem the more prevalent, are vulnerable to the relevant charge.
Here, a second clarification is in order: retributive theories may attribute value to an object other than suffering, and this has implications for our evaluation of the “moral credentials” of retributivism.Footnote 74 As Berman following Feinberg has pointed out, desert is a three-part relation whereby (1) the desert subject is said to deserve (2) the desert object, in virtue of (3) the desert basis.Footnote 75 In the context of punishment, the desert subject is uncontroversially understood to be the wrongdoer. The desert basis is generally understood to be culpable wrongdoing. Yet what wrongdoers deserve might or might not be suffering.Footnote 76 Other alternatives include that what wrongdoers deserve is to be treated or responded to in some particular way, whereby, for example, it is the responsive act of punishing rather than the experience of suffering that is deserved,Footnote 77 and on axiological versions of the relevant claim, valuable.Footnote 78
Thus, to the extent that the objection to retributivism is grounded in presuming suffering to be the desert object, and suffering to be that which is good, it is important to see once again that the discussed antiretributive argument does not succeed in rejecting a potentially substantial subset of retributive theories, even among those grounded on axiological claims. It thus does not constitute an argument against retributivism tout court.
3. “Deserved Suffering” and Its Value
Having demonstrated that a broad set of retributive views are immune to the proposed line of objection, we could stop here, inviting critics to take proponents of these views as fellow travelers in the pursuit of a just criminal law. More, however, can be said with respect to those retributive views that attribute intrinsic value to the suffering of the deserving. I suspect that many take such “suffering-oriented” retributive views to be the only views on offer, equating this option with retributivism itself.Footnote 79 The above should be sufficient to demonstrate that this is false. And that even a successful attack on suffering-oriented retributivism is not a successful attack against retributivism tout court.
Restricting our view to “suffering-oriented” retributivism, does this finally bring us to a retributive outlook that is at odds with welfare orientation? That is committed to the intrinsic goodness of human suffering? And that must be rejected if we are committed to the value of human welfare? I suggest not. Or at least, not yet. There may very well be retributive accounts that are to be rejected on grounds of welfare orientation, but not, I contend, merely on grounds of their attribution of value to “deserved suffering.” Let me elaborate, at risk of belaboring a central retributive point.
While retributive theories of punishment are repeatedly framed as “backward-looking” theories of punishment, many fail to fully appreciate the way in which the past is integral to the retributive idea and the very grounds of the justification of punishment it offers. On both retributive and nonretributive accounts, the world is a better place in the absence of wrongdoing. On both retributive and nonretributive accounts, in the event of wrongdoing, the world can be made better if punishment is introduced into the mix. The accounts diverge on how it is that the world is made better and how it is that value is added through punishment. On a critical rendition of retributivism, the retributivist takes suffering per se to be valuable, such that adding suffering (of the deserving) is what makes the world better. Hence the resistance to retributivism as attributing goodness to human suffering. Yet this is false. In fact, on the retributive picture, we must begin by looking at the past, since insofar as retributive accounts rely on an intrinsic goodness claim, they import the past into the very description of the object of evaluation.
On a nonantagonistic rendition of retribution, a world in which there is wrongdoing left unaddressed is worse than a world in which there is wrongdoing, properly addressed. That is, while we are better off in the absence of wrongdoing, if an agent has culpably wronged, a world in which the wrongdoer suffers their “just deserts” will be better than one in which wrongdoing is left “unmet,” that is, in a state of injustice.Footnote 80 But notice that per this view, suffering is not (or need not be) attributed independent value. Rather the desert relation between the wrongdoing and suffering is the focal point for explaining how the world is made better (or less bad): value is attributed to a complex whole that includes both wrongdoing and suffering, rightly related,Footnote 81 rather than independently to suffering, “when deserved.”Footnote 82 To miss this is to enable the error of thinking that retributivism endorses suffering per se, whereas in fact, the shorthand “deserved suffering” refers to a complex phenomenon that imports into the value-making features of punishment a relation and reference to the past that attributes positive moral valence to the complex whole that correctly aligns between the two. To understand retributivism as a theory that attributes positive moral valence to suffering simpliciter, and then to recoil from retributivism on this ground, is thus to refuse to acknowledge the content of the view.Footnote 83
The critic essentially confuses the content of punishment with the source of its value. Punishment consists in the deliberate imposition of something negative and undesirable on the punishee: burdens, deprivations, or suffering. It cannot generate the relevant value without such imposition. Yet punishment derives its value not from its content, as assumed by views that understand retributivism to endorse “suffering for suffering's sake,” but from its meaning and from the right relations it generates between wrongdoing and deprivations or suffering.Footnote 84 To appreciate how value can inhere in the relations between parts rather than exclusively in the constituent parts of a whole, Leo Zaibert offers a Husserlian example from the field of aesthetics to move the debate about retributive punishment forward: that of a musical masterpiece, in the first instance, in its original form, and in the second, freely rearranged. As Zaibert articulates, in rearranging the parts of the masterpiece “what I will thereby produce will be unfathomably less valuable . . . Independently of the parts of any whole themselves, the specific ordering of these parts generates – or fails to generate – value in different degrees.”Footnote 85 Returning to the context of punishment, the responsiveness involved in wrongdoing being met by punishment is a relational feature that can bear value, without the necessary ascription of value to the burdens and suffering there involved. Thus the intrinsic value (or rightness) associated with retributive punishment does not inhere in the intrinsic features of suffering, but in its extrinsic features—the relations generated between wrongdoing and such burdens, the meaning and value of which can be cashed out in different ways (in terms of fairness, justice, etc.).Footnote 86 As for the intrinsic features of suffering, these, it emerges, are only valuable in service of a further object of value, whether the erasure of immunity, fairness, moral alignment, dissociation, or otherwise, depending on one's particular retributive view.
One might put the point as follows: if we isolate the question of the evaluation of human suffering, even within the retributive outlook, suffering alone is only instrumentally or quasi-instrumentally valuable. While on noninstrumentalist axiological retributivism, punishment does not derive its value from its downstream consequences, but from that of which it is a constitutive part, it is still the case that intrinsic value is not independently attributed to suffering. Rather it has value only in service of some other object. What is distinctive about retributivism, then, is not that it takes suffering to be intrinsically good, but rather that it takes suffering, burdens, or deprivations to be a constitutive element of the good.Footnote 87
The retributivist thus is committed to the thought that a world that includes the suffering of punishment is better than one without. But like on competing consequentialist accounts, adding mere suffering makes things morally worse. As above, more must be added to the mix: in the retributivist case, it is the constitution of the desert relation, while in the consequentialist case, it is the addition of welfare or other goods that makes the moral difference. And while a welfarist may want to insist that the only kind of addition that can make this moral difference is a contribution to human welfare, that is, of course, to fall back on a different debate—about monism vs. pluralism with respect to value, and whether anything other than welfare can be of value (which, if one takes rights, equality, etc. to be independently valuable, already puts one on the antimonistic side of the debate). This, however, is not the disagreement at hand, and in any event not the disagreement that leaves retributivism on the “repugnant” side of the conflict.
B. Remaining Tensions
One might yet worry that the above means that retributivists lack a commitment to the minimization of suffering, and thus there remain welfare-oriented grounds to reject retributivism. Yet this is the case with respect to the alternative justifications of punishment countenanced as well (i.e., the promotion of welfare and the minimization of suffering come apart). There are many circumstances within which suffering can be avoided, though retributive theory would endorse the deliberate imposition of (burdens, deprivations, or) punitive suffering. But this is the case with respect to any view that does not take the minimization of suffering to be the trumping moral criterion. It is not unique to retributive theory but common, for example, to any rich consequentialist vision that takes suffering minimization to have competitors (equality, rights, justice, etc.). In fact, Benthamite utilitarianism can be similarly criticized as it seeks not suffering minimization but welfare maximization. If there are two courses of action, one that imposes less punishment and suffering and leads to a net increase in aggregate utility, and one that imposes a far greater amount of punishment, yet leads to a greater net increase in aggregate utility, the utilitarian (and some welfarists) are committed to the moral superiority and duty to engage in the second, suffering-enhancing course of action. Of course, one could adopt a more sophisticated approach that avoids such outcomes, but the point is that the allegation that retribution cannot be countenanced by a welfare-oriented approach because of its failure to be committed to the course of action that minimizes human suffering cannot be a basis for arguing for the incompatibility of welfare and retribution, if strict welfarist approaches themselves lead down the same path.
The conclusion that may be drawn from the above is that there are tensions between welfare and retribution, and sometimes retribution recommends moving to a world that includes more suffering than otherwise exists (for reasons that are not simply translatable into the intrinsic goodness of suffering). Yet this is not because of some value inherent in promoting suffering “for suffering's sake,” or because of a failure to appreciate the value of human welfare. Rather (in a Strawsonian vein), it is because in a nonideal world, in which culpable wrongdoing is a given, responsive actions and practices that are themselves valuable can involve negative reactions and suffering.Footnote 88 These have an indispensable role to play in just, moral relations.Footnote 89 Further, the aspects of welfare orientation that generate these tensions, if taken to their end, recommend abolitionism rather than the displacement of retributivism in favor of a consequentialist alternative. If one's welfare-oriented approach countenances punishment, it provides no solid grounds to reject retributivism.
V. Conclusion
This paper has aimed to demonstrate that prominent reasons to reject retributivism, voiced regularly in contemporary arguments about punishment, fail, and that retributive punishment and welfare orientation are broadly consistent projects that can and should be pursued concomitantly. Neither generates substantive reason to reject the other, unless one is tempted toward an abolitionist or pacifist ethic, the unattractiveness of which lies beyond the scope of this paper. While keeping both welfare-oriented goals and accountability in our sights may be demanding, it seems not exaggerated to say that justice demands that we abandon neither of these projects, the merging of which will prove the best way forward toward a humane, defensible criminal law.
Acknowledgements
My sincerest thanks to Fernando Bracaccini, Miri Gur-Arye, Ryan Liss, and Alec Walen for their excellent comments on previous drafts. Thanks also to Joanna Langille and the participants of the University of Western Ontario Legal Philosophy Research Group Workshop, as well as participants of the Hebrew University Criminal Theory Workshop for helpful discussions. Research for this paper was supported by the Israel Science Foundation (Grant No. 2003/21).
Competing interests
The author(s) declare none.