Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-t5tsf Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-09T21:52:41.808Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Commodification and Phenomenology: Evading Consent in Theory Regarding Rape

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  16 February 2009

John H. Bogart
Affiliation:
Heller, Ehrman, White & McAuliffe

Abstract

In a recent essay, Donald Dripps advanced what he calls a “commodification theory” of rape, offered as an alternative to understanding rape in terms of lack of consent. Under the “commodification theory,” rape is understood as the expropriation of sexual services, i.e., obtaining sex through “illegitimate” means. One aim of Dripps's effort was to show the inadequacy of consent approaches to understanding rape. Robin West, while accepting Dripps's critique of consent theories, criticizes Dripps's commodification approach. In its place, West suggests a more phenomenological approach.

The author argues that (1) neither Dripps nor West offers convincing critiques of consent-based theories; (2) the alternatives they offer presuppose the vitality of a consent-based approach to understanding rape; and (3) that both Dripps and West consistently conflate more general moral and political issues with that of the nature of rape.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 1996

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1. Real Rape, 1987.Google Scholar

2. More specifically, sexual services as property interests. Dripps, D.A., Beyond Rape: An Essay on the Difference Between the Presence of Force and the Absence of Consent, 92 Colum. L. Rev. 1780, 1786 (1992) (“Dripps”).CrossRefGoogle Scholar

3. Id.

4. There is a non sequitur in the leap from identification of rape with sexual appropriation to a focus on perpetrator states of mind. Dripps seems to assume that expropriation entails intentional states with respect to the expropriation itself. It doesn't. One may expropriate another's property without knowing (or forming similar intentional states with respect to) the property as the other's.

5. Id. at 1803.

6. Id. at 1797, 1799, 1807.

7. Id. at 1787, 1793–94.

8. Id. at 1787.

9. Id.

10. Id. at 1788.

11. Id. at 1788–89.

12. Id. at 1789.

13. Id. at 1791.

14. Id. at 1788–89.

15. Id. at 1789.

16. Id. at 1799.

17. Id. at 1793.

18. Id.

19. Id. at 1799.

20. Id. at 1792–94.

21. Id. at 1794, 1801.

22. Id. at 1792.

23. Id.

24. Id. at 1789.

25. Id.

26. Id.

27. West, R., Legitimating the Illegitimate: A Comment on Beyond Rape 93 Colum. L. Rev. 1442, 1446 (1993) (“West”).CrossRefGoogle Scholar

28. Id. at 1447.

29. Id. at 1446

30. Id. at 1448.

31. Id.

32. Id.

33. Id.

34. Id. at 1449.

35. Id. at 1451.

36. Id.

37. Id.

38. Id. at 1449.

39. Here, as in a number of other works, West's work reminds me of Max Scheler's phenomenology.

40. Id. at 1443.

41. Id. at 1448–49.

42. Id. at 1452.

43. Id. at 1458.

44. Id. at 1452, 1458.

45. Id. at 1458.

46. Dripps, at 1788.Google Scholar

47. Dripps, at 1785.Google Scholar

48. The paucity of imagination in Dripps's exposition reflects a limitation in thought. Just as his view of sex is stilted and narrow, so too is his conceptualization of autonomy, rights, and responsibility.

49. Dripps, at 1789; West at 1443.Google Scholar

50. Dripps, , Reply to Professor West, 93 Colum. L. Rev. 1464 (1993).Google Scholar

51. West at 1453

52. Dripps, at 1788.Google Scholar

53. Dripps, at 1807.Google Scholar

54. Dripps seems to think that there is a failure of consent only when there is a refusal of consent

55. Cf. West at 1450–51 with Dripps, at 1802–03.Google Scholar

56. Dripps, at 1801.Google Scholar

57. West at 1452–53; Dripps, at 1791.Google Scholar

58. Dripps, at 1781.Google Scholar The discussion of causality otherwise seems pointless.

59. Dripps, at 1791.Google Scholar

60. I find this an odd locution, as “sex with” may suggest a cooperative activity. In this case, it may be accurate to say “sex on” or “sex in” W; but this usage may not be proper English.

61. For an example of such a theory, see Bogart, J.H., Reconsidering Rape: Rethinking the Conceptual Foundations of Rape Law, 8 Can. J. Law and Jurisprudence 159 (1995).CrossRefGoogle Scholar