Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-vdxz6 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-26T04:48:38.509Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Why Omissions are Special

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  13 February 2009

A. P. Simester
Affiliation:
Gonville and Caius College, Cambridge

Extract

The criminal law presently distinguishes between actions and omissions, and only rarely proscribes failures to avert consequences that it would be an offense to bring about. Why? In recent years it has been persuasively argued by both Glover and Bennett that, celeris paribus, omissions to prevent a harm are just as culpable as are actions which bring that harm about. On the other hand, and acknowledging that hitherto “lawyers have not been very successful in finding a rationale for it,” Tony Honoré has sought to defend the law's differential treatment. He proposes a “distinct-duties theory” that in addition to the general duties we owe to everyone (e.g., not to inflict harm), we also owe distinct duties to a more limited collection of people and associations, specified by features of our relationship with them (we owe, for instance, duties as parents to our own children). Where a distinct duty holds, breach by omission may well be no better than breach by positive action. But absent a distinct duty, omissions, per Honoré, are less culpable. They are mere failures to intervene and improve or rectify things, whereas actions are positive interventions which make things worse. And, thus, the law has good reason to differentiate between them.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 1995

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1. Among others, Glover, Death, Causing and Lives, Saving, chapter 7 (1977)Google Scholar; Bennett, , Morality and ConsequencesGoogle Scholar, in The Tanner Lectures on Human Values 47 (McMurrin, ed., 1981Google Scholar); and Bennett, , The Act Itself (1995).Google Scholar

2. Are Omissions Less Culpable, in Essays for Patrick Atiyah 31 (Cane, and Stapleton, eds., 1991Google Scholar) (hereafter “Honoré”) at 31.

3. Feinberg, , Harm to Others 154 (1984)Google Scholar; Honoré, at 49.Google Scholar

4. See e.g., Ashworth, , The Scope of Criminal Liability for Omissions, 105Google ScholarLaw Quarterly Review 424 (1989).Google Scholar

5. Moore, , Act and Crime 23 (1993)Google Scholar; Honoré, at 37.Google Scholar

6. At 72; Chapter 7, § VIII(1781).

7. D'arcy, , Human Acts 41 (1963).Google Scholar D'Arcy however accepts Bentham's view in part when he concludes that “Bentham's criterion is no doubt a negative necessary condition for an omission, but it is not a sufficient one.”

8. Supra note 5, at 31.

9. Id. at 28. For the point that Moore uses the term “omissions” to embrace not-doings generally, see his footnote 31.

10. In More on Act and Crime, 142 U. Penn. L. Rev. 1749, 1775–1776 (1994).Google Scholar

11. Supra note5, at 29–31. See also id. at 1777–1778.

12. Negative Acts, in Essays on Davidson: Actions and Events 93 (Vermazen, and Hintikka, eds., 1985) at 95.Google Scholar

13. Supra note 5, at 86–87. Compare Moore's definition of omissions, quoted above in the text.

14. Or, in Vermazen's case, might Andy's twisting his buttons be a sufficient condition of his not eating the hors d'oeuvres.

15. Supra note 5, at 267 ff.

16. Hart, and Honoré, , Causation in the Law 170172 (2nd ed., 1985)Google Scholar; Williams, G.. Text book of Criminal Law 388389 (2nd ed., 1983).Google Scholar

17. The example is Vermazen, 's, supra note 12, at 100.Google ScholarCf. Fletcher, , On the Moral Irrelevance of Bodily Movements, 142 U. Penn. L. Rev. 1443, 1448 (1994)CrossRefGoogle Scholar, citing Hart and Honoré, id. at 38.

18. (1902) 19. T.L.R. 37.

19. Cf. Hart, and Honoré, (supra note 16, at 31)Google Scholar: “in spite of differences between these cases and the simple paradigms, the very real analogies are enough to justify the extension of causal language to them.” Feinberg's discussion (supra note 3, at 172ff) is also instructive.

20. Cf. Honoré, , at 39Google Scholar; Hart, and Honoré, , supra note 16, at 37.Google Scholar

21. Stone, R v. and Dobinson, [1977] Q.B. 354.Google Scholar

22. Something Honoré makes clear (at 41): “if… the break in routine violates a norm…, it is a form of not-doing which amounts to an omission and is a potential ground of responsibility.” Cf. Casey, Actions and Consequences, in Morality and Moral Reasoning 155 (Casey, ed., 1971Google Scholar) at 180: “The introduction of a statement which claims to give the cause of some event presupposes a pattern of normal expectations, such that what will count as the cause of the event is, as itwere, an intrusion into the pattern of expectations.”

23. Honoré, , at 4142.Google Scholar

24. Ib. at 39.

25. Ib. at 41.

26. Bennett, , supra note 1, at 55ffGoogle Scholar; Bennett, , supra note 1, chapter 6.Google Scholar

27. Honoré, , at 40.Google Scholar It is not quite a paraphrase; Honoré remarks (in his footnote 14) that he has rendered Bennett's analysis “in what seems a more plausible form.”

28. Id.

29. Bennett, , supra note 1, at 6669Google Scholar; Bennett, , supra note 1. at 96100, 112114.Google Scholar

30. Honoré, , at 40–11.Google Scholar

31. Norm, and Action, 39–12 (1963).Google Scholar

32. Cf. Feinberg, , supra note 3, at 159162.Google Scholar

33. Honoré remarks, I believe correctly, that all omissions are not-doings of something, but not all not-doings are omissions (at 36).

34. For instance (Honoré, , at 32Google Scholar), that to “require a positive act normally imposesa greater cost in time, effort, skill, and money than a prohibition with similar results.”

35. Id. at 51.

36. Id.

37. Assuming, as does Honoré (at 50), that “people and objects on the whole continue as they are unless something intervenes to change them.”

38. Though it surely is: We feel very differently about killers than about non-savers. There may be more than one intuition at work here. For one thing, the formerare more threatening de futura. But in addition (and an aspect of the ceteris paribus proviso which I am not going to address here), omissions are often incidental to the defendant's practical deliberations—they typically disclose a different and lesser fault, of limited imagination or empathy rather than hostility. Cf. Glover, , supra note 1, at 111.Google Scholar

39. As has been pointed out earlier, one might even intervene to resist one's body's being moved.

40. Bennett, , supra note 1, at 66.Google ScholarSee Bennett, , supra note 1, at 96ff.Google Scholar

41. Cf. Hart, and Honoré, , supra note 16, at 59Google Scholar: “the careless friend might be held morally and legally bound to compensate the owner for the loss just as for loss ‘directly’ caused, for example, by carelessly starting a fire.”

42. Honoré, , at 51.Google Scholar

43. Cf. Hart and Honoré's vision of the law (supra note 16, at lxxx) as “a system designed to minimize harm by an appeal to individuals to control their conduct.”

44. As Glanville Williams points out in Criminal Omissions—The Conventional View, 107 Law Quarterly Review 86, 89 (1991).Google Scholar

45. Cf. Fletcher, , supra note 17, at 1451.Google Scholar This point does not apply to those whose omissions occur while they arc engaged in specialist activities, including driving or carrying on a business. Such persons have not refrained from entering the law's purview.

46. Drawing on Parfit's distinction between action- and outcome-reasons: Is Common Sense Morality Self Defeating?, 70 Journal of Philosophy 533 (1979)Google Scholar; see also his Reasons, and Persons, (1984).Google Scholar

47. Cf. Bennett, , supra note 1, at 7880Google Scholar; Glover, , supra note 1, at 105Google Scholar; also, The Morality of Freedom 280–281 (1986).

48. Honoré, , at 49.Google Scholar

49. Per Honoré (at 50), “[o]nly if one looks at items of conduct atomistically rather than in their wider setting … do acts and omissions appear equivalent.”

50. In Thomson's own examples, five people are killed if I do not throw the switch: Killing, Letting Die, and the Trolley Problem at 78Google Scholar; The Trolley Problem at 94Google Scholar; in J.J. Thomson-, Rights, Restitution and Risk: Essays in Moral Theory (1986). Although the case is commonly described as Thomson's, she in fact derives it from Foot: The Problem of Abortion and the Doctrine of the Double Effect, Oxford Review 5 (1967).Google Scholar

51. Cf. Berry v. Borough of Sugar Notch, 43 Atl. 240 (1899).

52. Honoré, , at 50.Google Scholar

53. In this I concur with Hart and Honoré (supra note 16, at 128): “suppose, again, that a house can be built and profitably sold only if X delivers bricks and Y mortar, If both Xand Y default in delivery so that the projected house cannot be built and sold each can argue, again, that his default was nota sine qua non of the loss of profit on the sale of the house, since the default of the other was sufficient to preclude it Despite this, lawyers and ordinary people would agree in saying … that the omission of each is causally relevant to the ensuing harm and that each could in a proper case be held responsible for it.”

54. Thus, Hart and Honoré (id. at lxxx–xi): “The idea that individuals are primarily responsible for the harm which their actions are sufficient to produce without the intervention of others or of extraordinary natural events is important … to … the individual's sense of himself as a separate person whose character is manifested in such actions … [R]espect for ourselves and others as distinct persons would be much weakened, if not dissolved, if we could not think of ourselves as the separate authors of the changes we make in the world.”

55. Cf. Casey, , supra note 22, at 172ffGoogle Scholar: We may misleadingly say of both Jeremy and Stephen that “he so conducted himself with the consequence that John was stabbed.” See also Williams, B., A Critique of UtilitarianismGoogle Scholar, in Smart, and Williams, , Utilitarianism: For and Against 75 at 108 (1973).Google Scholar

56. Or a person who fails to repair a retaining wall himself flood the land beyond: cf. East Suffolk Catchment Board v. Kent [1941] A.C. 74. Note that this proposition is advanced solely as a matter of analytical groundwork. In particular, I am not making an argument here about the fair labelling of defendants (regarding which, see Ashworth, , Principles of Criminal Law 7173 (1991))Google Scholar; that argument could be met by having duplicate offenses in each instance of doing the actus reus and of permitting its occurrence.

57. To borrow the metaphor deployed (in a different context) by Dworkin: Taking Rights Seriously ix (1977).

58. Malm, , Killing, Letting Die, and Simple Conflicts, 18 Philosophy and Public Affairs 238, 245250 (1989).Google ScholarPubMed

59. Malm, id. at 246–2–17; Honoré, , at 52.Google Scholar The characters' names are supplied by Honoré.

60. Honoré, , at 4247.Google ScholarSee also the first four categories discussed by Ashworth, , supra note 4, at 439447.Google Scholar The same point helps to elucidate Corrado's motionless-driver examples: Is There an Act Requirement in the Criminal Law, 142 U. Penn. L. Rev. 1529, 15381541 (1994)Google Scholar; discussed by Moore, , supra note 10, at 17781781.Google Scholar The appeal of these cases seems to be that, whether in virtue of having antecedently created a risk or in virtue of being in control of the car, the motorist stands in some special relationship to the harm inflicted.

61. Miller [1983] 2 A.C. 161.Google Scholar

62. See the text at note 15 supra.

63. Something warned against by Wlliams, Bernard (supra note 55, at 116)Google Scholar, in the context of utilitarianism: Its edict “is to make [the individual] into a channel between the input of everyone's projects, including his own, and an output of optimific decision; but this is to neglect the extent to which Au actions and his decisions have to be seen as the actions and decisions which flow from the projects and attitudes with which he is most closely identified. It is thus, in the most literal sense, an attack on his integrity.”

64. Anarchy, , State and Utopia 50 (1974).Google Scholar

65. Cf. Ashworth, , supra note 4, at 428429Google Scholar; Kamm, , Action, Omission, and the Stringency of Duties, 142 U. Penn. L. Rev. 1493, 1496, 1511 (1994).CrossRefGoogle Scholar

66. Raz, , supra note 47, at 376.Google Scholar

67. Id. at 320.

68. Id. at 382.

69. Cf. Raz, id. at 408, 419; Freeman, , Criminal Liability and the Duty to Aid the Distressed, 142 U. Penn. L. Rev. 1455, 1478ff (1994).CrossRefGoogle Scholar Such considerations might be sufficient, moreover, to warrant the existence of a limited legal duty to rescue. My argument here is directed more generally at why, save exceptionally, the law should be more averse to prohibiting not-doings than it is to proscribing doings.

70. Id. at 425. The objection is made all the more cogent when buttressed by Feinberg, 's claim (supra note 3, at 163164)Google Scholar that, although Ihe degree or restriction of liberty imposed by a criminal law provision depends upon the impact of that provision on one's options, it does not depend on whether the duty imposed is positive or negative.

71. Criminal Law 45 (5th ed., 1983).Google Scholar