Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-g7gxr Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-05T12:23:03.619Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Alchemies of the Mind: Transmutation and Misrepresentation

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  16 February 2009

Jon Elster
Affiliation:
Columbia University

Extract

At least since the French moralists—Montaigne, Pascal, La Rochefoucauld, La Bruyère—it has been a commonplace that people can fool themselves as well as others about their beliefs and motivations. In this article, I consider some mechanisms of transmutation (deceiving oneself) and misrepresentation (deceiving others), and their impact on behavior. (I refer to these collectively as transformations.) I argue that deception and self-deception are not merely ex post rationalizations of behavior whose real motive and explanation are found elsewhere, but that they have independent causal and explanatory power. If people, that is, did not fool themselves or others about why they do what they do they would act differently. The reason is that deception and self-deception take place under constraints that prevent us from offering totally opportunistic or self-serving rationalizations of what we do. There is a consistency constraint that is induced by the costs of being seen (by oneself or others) as offering inconsistent justifications for one's behavior, and an imperfection constraint diat is induced by the costs of being seen (by oneself or others) as offering justifications that are too blatantly self-serving.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 1997

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1. Habermas, J., 1, 2 The Theory of Communicative Action (1984/1987).Google Scholar

2. Caro, R.A., The Power Broker: Robert Moses and the Fall of New York (1974).Google Scholar

3. Rochefoucauld, La, Maxim 218, Maxims (1959).Google Scholar

4. See also Habermas, J., Between Facts and Norms 340 (1996).Google Scholar

5. Rochefoucauld, La, supra note 3, Maxim 102.Google Scholar

6. Id., Maxim 119.

7. For a survey, see Wicklund, R.A. & Brehm, J., Perspectives on Cognitive Dissonance Ch. 3 (1976).Google Scholar

8. Scheler, M.. Ressentiment 74 (1961)Google Scholar; see also Nietzsche, F., The Genealogy of Morals in Kaufman, W., ed., Basic Writings of Nietzsche (1992).Google Scholar

9. There is little overlap, therefore, between the present analysis and that offered in Kuran, T., Private Truths, Public Lies (1995).Google Scholar

10. Bruyère, La, Characters 77 (1992)Google Scholar. For discussions of this trichotomy, see Hirschman, A., The Passions and the Interests (1977)Google Scholar and White, M., Philosophy, The Federalist, and the Constitution (1987).Google Scholar

11. Habermas, , supra note 1.Google Scholar

12. For the place of impartiality in political argument, see Barry, B., Justice as Impartiality (1995).Google Scholar

13. In wage bargaining, for instance, “Taking account of all possible permutations, the number of plausible-sounding norms is certainly well into three figures. It would be a particularly unfortunate or inept group that did not find some norm to justify its claim to a larger share.” Elster, J., The Cement of Society 233–34 (1989)Google Scholar. Cf. also Tocqueville's description of American democracy: “In the United States a politician first tries to see what his own interest is and who have analogous interests which can be grouped around his own; he is next concerned to discover whether by chance there may not be somewhere in the world a doctrine or a principle that could conveniently be placed at the head of the new association.” Democracyin America 177 (1969).Google Scholar

14. Komm, S., Layoffs, inGoogle Scholar Local Justice in America (Elster, J. ed., 1995).Google Scholar

15. Rochefoucauld, La, supra note 3, Maxim 39.Google Scholar

16. Alloy, L. & Abrahamson, L., Depressive Realism, in Cognitive Processes in Depression 441–85Google Scholar (Alloy, L. ed., 1988).Google Scholar

17. Elster, , supra note 13, Ch. 6.Google Scholar

18. Babcock, L. & Olson, C., The Causrs of Impasses in Bargaining, 31 Indus. Rel. 348–60 (1992)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Babcock, L. et al. , Choosing the Wrong Pond: Sodai Comparisons in Negotiations That Reflect a Self-Serving Bias, III Q. J. Econ. 120 (1996).CrossRefGoogle Scholar

19. Wills, W. Ashby, Downward Comparison Principles in Social Psychology, 90 Psychol. Bull. 245–71 (1981).CrossRefGoogle Scholar

20. Thus, Babcock, et al. , supra note 18, at 18Google Scholar, raise the possibility that “in advocating a particular set of comparables to the other side during negotiations, the parties lose track of the fact thai they have selected them strategically and come to view them as fair.” This illustrates the idea that misrepresentation may induce transmutation.

21. See Elster, ed., Local Justice (1992)Google Scholar and Local Justice in America (1995)Google Scholar and Romm, , Layoffs, supra note 14.Google Scholar

22. Zajac, E., The Political Economy of Fairness 121–22 (1995)Google Scholar, cites as a “striking example of status quo property or equity rights … the attempt to ‘vintage’ utility rates, that is, to charge ‘old’ customers a different, usually lower rate than ‘new’ ones.” Cf. also Aristotle, , Rhetoric 1387a.Google Scholar

23. See, e.g., Madison in I Records Of the Federal Convention 151 (Farrand, M. ed., 1966)Google Scholar versus Dickinson, , at 159.Google Scholar

24. Id. at 348.

25. Id. at 250–51.

26. Elster, J., Constitution-Making in Eastern Europe, 71 Pub. Admin. 169218 (1993).CrossRefGoogle Scholar

27. Loewenstein, G. et al. , Self-serving Assessment of Fairness and Pretrial Bargaining, 22 J. Legal Stud. 135–59 (1993)CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Babcock, L. et al. , Biased Judgments of Fairness in Bargaining, 85 Am. Econ. Rev. 1337–43 (1995).Google Scholar

28. Veyne, P., Le Pain et le Cirque 667 (1976)Google Scholar; see also Elster, J., Sour Grapes 156 (1983).Google Scholar

29. Loewenstein, et al. , supra note 27, at 152–53Google Scholar. They add that “Curiously, however, plaintiff's predictions and fairness rallies did not have a significant effect on settlement values.”

30. Id. at 153, n. 42.

31. Elster, , supra note 13, at 275–77Google Scholar, discusses cases in which prebargaining behaviors of the parties have a negative impact on the probability of agreement and a positive impact on the amount agreed upon, as well as cases in which they increase the share of the total while reducing the size of the total to be shared. These behaviors are, however, intentionally chosen and would presumably not be undertaken unless the expected net effect was positive. The fairness bias, although shaped by interest, is not similarly guided by interest.

32. Thus, Pascal, Pensée 78: “Our own interest is [a] wonderful instrument for blinding us agreeably. The fairest man in the world is not allowed to be judge in his own case. I know of men who, to avoid the danger of partiality in their own favor, have leaned over to the opposite extreme of injustice. The surest way to lose a perfectly just case was to get close relatives to recommend it to them.”

33. Babcock, et al. , supra note 27, at 1338.Google Scholar

34. Id. at 1339.

35. Rabin, M., Moral Preferences, Moral Constraints, and Self-Serving Biases (manuscript 1995).Google Scholar

36. Swenson, P., Fair Shares 4353 (1988).Google Scholar

37. Gōsta Rehn, cited in id. at 60.

38. Elster, , supra note 13, Ch. 4.Google Scholar

39. Rochefoucauld, La, supra note 3, Maxim 246.Google Scholar

40. It should be possible to test the hypothesis experimentally by offering subjects the choice between several maxims of fairness to see whether they choose one that corresponds moderately to their interest or one that offers a perfect fit. To induce transmutation rather than misrepresentation, one could tell them that actual allocations would be made by applying an average of the fairness proposals made by different subjects, and (nonveridically) that no one would know who chose which maxim.

41. I use “script” in a sense that is roughly similar to that of Tomkins, S., Affect, Imagery, Consciousness 8386 (1991).Google Scholar

42. Schalin, L., On the Problem of Envy, 2 Scand. Psychioanal. Rev. 134–35 (1979).Google Scholar

43. Hutson, S., Social Ranking in a French Alpine Community, inGoogle ScholarGifts, and Poison, 41–68, at 47Google Scholar (Bailey, F. ed., 1971).Google Scholar

44. Netanyahu, B., The Origins of the Inquisition 989 (1995).Google Scholar

45. Tocqueville, , supra note 13, at 221.Google Scholar

46. Allport, G., Prejudice Ch. 20 (1979).Google Scholar

47. Sniderman, P., Brody, R., & Tetlock, P. E., Political Psychology Ch. 6 (1991).Google Scholar

48. Id. at 49–50.

49. Id. at 52–53.

50. de Tocqueville, Alexis, Democracy in America 526Google Scholar. A few pages later (528–29) he offers a similar argument about religion: Some Christians believe that they do good toward others for the sake of their own rewards in the next world, but Tocqueville claims they are deceiving themselves and are really acting for the love of God.

51. For a fuller discussion, see J. Elster, Alchemies of the Mind (forthcoming).

52. This phrase by Madison (from The Federalist, No. 42) is also the title of a book by Bessette, J. (1934).Google Scholar

53. Posner, R., Economics, Politics, and the Reading of Statutes and the Constitution, 49 U. Chi. L. Rev. 263–91, at 273 (1982).CrossRefGoogle Scholar

54. Elster, , supra note 28. at 24, 3839.Google Scholar

55. Colcman, J., Foundations of Social Theory 393 (1990).Google Scholar

56. For a similar argument, see Perelman, C. & Olbrechts-Tyteca, L., The New Rhetoric 75 (1969).Google Scholar

57. Id. at 56; my italics.

58. I am assuming here lhat punishment takes a material form such as voting someone out of office rather than shame-inducing behavior. The shame case is discussed below.

59. There is no reason to go to a higher-order argument and assume lhat B might expect a purely self-interested C to punish him because if he doesn't one of D, E … will punish C for not punishing B. As the transaction between A and B takes place in full view of all oilier members of society, B knows that he will be punished by someone for not punishing A.

60. This argument has a rough resemblance with that offered in Kreps, D.M. et al. , Rational Cooperation in thf Finitely Iterated Prisoner's Dilemma, 27 J. Econ. Theory 245–52 (1982).CrossRefGoogle Scholar

61. Posner, , supra note 53, at 286Google Scholar. He cites this as an extreme example.

62. Macey, J., Promoting Public-Regarding Legislation Through Statutory Interpretation: An Interest-Group Model, 86 Colum. L. Rev. 223–68, 251 (1986).CrossRefGoogle Scholar

63. Perelman, & Olbrechts-Tyteca, , supra note 56, at 62.Google Scholar

64. Id. at 457.

65. Id. at 473.

66. Farrand, ed., Records, supra note 23, at 421, 430.Google Scholar

67. Creppell, I., Democracy and Literacy: The Role of Culture in Political Life, 30 Arch. Européennes Soc 2247 (1989).CrossRefGoogle Scholar

68. The following discussion draws on Mackie, G., U.S. Immigration Policy and Local JusticeGoogle Scholar, in Elster, , supra note 13.Google Scholar

69. The following discussion draws on Conley, P., The Allocation of College AdmissionsGoogle Scholar, id.

70. In their admission processes, some state colleges assign points for disadvantages of various kinds. As Conley explains, this process may be backward-driven, in the sense that the weights are assigned so as to get a preset number of minority applicants admitted, id. For a similar manipulation of the Preliminary Scholastic Assessment Test, see College Board Revises Test to improve Chances for Girls, N. Y. Times. 10 2, 1996, sec. B8.Google Scholar

71. The following simplified exposition draws on Dennis, M., Scarce Medical Resources: Hemodialysis and Kidney TransplantationGoogle Scholar, in Elster, , supra note 14.Google Scholar

72. 1996 N.V. App. Div. Lexis 8713.

73. For a brilliant discussion of this predicament, see Perelman, & Tyteca, Olbrechts, supra note 56, at 96.Google Scholar

74. Dixit, A. & Nalebuff, B., Making Threats Credible, in Strategy and Choice 165166Google Scholar (Zeckhauser, R. ed., 1991).Google Scholar

75. Schelling, T., The Strategy of Conflect 27 (1960).Google Scholar

76. Farrand, ed., Records, supra note 23, at 492.Google Scholar

77. Id. at 530.

78. Id. at 532.

79. Id. at 531.

80. 8 Archives Parlementaires, Série 1:1789–99, at 209 (1875–88).

81. Id. at 213.

82. Id.

83. In some cases, though, predictions about one's own future behavior may be uttered as genuine warnings. See Frank, R., Passions Within Reason 55 passim (1988).Google Scholar

84. Perelman & Olbrechts-Tyteca, supra note 56, at 487Google Scholar; my italics.

85. We may note at this point the possibility of self-fulfilling warnings, which are, in this respect, intermediate between ordinary warnings and threats. By publicly telling the French king that his troops were unreliable, Mirabeau may in fact have ensured the truth of that statement

86. Thus, upon the announcement on July 2, 1938, of the arrival of a British emissary, “Hitler started up and said: ‘Gott im Himmel! Don't let him in yet I'm still in a good humor.’ He then proceeded, in front of his staff, to work himself up until his face darkened, he was breathing heavily, and his eyes were glazed.” Bullock, A., Hitler and Stalin 571 (1991).Google Scholar

87. Schelling, , supra note 75, at 143Google Scholar, mentions both these cases, with the difference that his emphasis is on conscious transmutation rather than misrepresentation.

88. Dixit, & Nalebuff, . supra note 74. at 165–66.Google Scholar

89. “Hitler never said anything, even when he appeared to have lost his temper, without calculating the effect both on those present and on those to whom they would recount it.” Bullock, , Supra note 86.Google Scholar

90. Isaacson, W., Kissinger 163–64, 181–82 (1992).Google Scholar

91. Id. at 294. It is probably a mere accident that this episode occurred just one year before publication in The New Yorker of a drawing that shows a disgruntled-looking man selling pencils on the street with a whip in his hand and a sign around his neck saying “Irrational.” Frank, R., supra note 83, at 5556Google Scholar, reproduces this drawing and adds that “the sign round the man's neck is not the only, or even a very good, signal that he is not fully rational. On the contrary, that he seems to have realized the sign might serve his purposes can only detract from its ability to do so.” Isaacson, by contrast, characterizes Nixon's boasting of his irrationality as “disarming and alarming.” My hunch is that Isaacson is right: As a rational man would understand that boasting of his irrationality is self-defeating, doing so is actually self-confirming. The argument could, of course, be taken one step further and so on ad infinitum, leaving the issue essentially indeterminate, which may have been enough for Nixon's purpose.

92. A passage from W. Somerset Maugham that I have been unable to trace is apt here: “Hypocrisy is the most difficult vice to pursue. It cannot be practiced at spare moments: It's a full-time occupation.”

93. Maynard-Sinith, J., Evolution and The Theory of Games Ch. 9 (1982).Google Scholar

94. Thus, after the invasion of Cambodia in 1970, “Nixon's ‘madman’ strategy was backfiring on him: He was coming across as unhinged in the eyes of his own nation. As a result, the Cambodian invasion would turn into the greatest victory for Hanoi since it lost the 1968 Tet offensive.” Isaacson, , supra note 90, at 270.Google Scholar

95. Hansen, M.H., The Athenian Democracy in The Age of Demosthenes 195 (1991)Google Scholar; see also Ober, J., Mass and Elite in Democratic Athens 212 (1989).Google Scholar

96. Aristotle, Rhetoric 1354b–55a.Google Scholar Analogously, in his analyses of the debates at the Federal Convention, Jillson, C.C., Constitution Making: Conflict and Consensus in the Federal Convention of 1787 16(1988)Google Scholar, argues that the speakers were swayed by reason only when their interest was not at stake.

97. Aristotle, , Nicomachean Ethics 1202b.Google Scholar

98. Montaigne, . Essays 944 (1991); See also 638.Google Scholar

99. Frijda, N., The Emotions 114 (1986).Google Scholar

100. Ekman, P., Telling Lies (1992).Google Scholar

101. Id. at 85–87.

102. Hatfield, E. et al. , Emotional Contagion (1994).Google Scholar

103. Seneca, , On Anger, l. vii.Google Scholar

104. Id. II. xviii.

105. Perelman, & Olhrechts-Tyteca, , supra note 50, at 24.Google Scholar

106. Bullock, , supra note 86, at 72.Google Scholar

107. Id. at 351.

108. Id. at 146.

109. This “cooperative” model of bargaining is perhaps better thought of as a model of fair arbitration.

110. For voting, See. Gibbard, , Manipulation of Voting Schemes, 41 Econometrica 587602 (1973).CrossRefGoogle Scholar For bargaining, see Crawford, V. & Varian, H., Distortion of Preferences and the Nash Theory of Bargaining, 3 Econ. Let. 203–6 (1979)CrossRefGoogle Scholar, and Sobel, J., Distortion of Utilities and the Bargaining Problem. 49 Econometrica 597617 (1981).CrossRefGoogle Scholar

111. Oren, D., Joining the club: A History of Jews and Yale 198 (1985)Google Scholar; see also Conley, , supra note 69.Google Scholar

112. Loury, G., One by One From the Inside Out 21 (1995).Google Scholar

113. The percentages are: Albania, 2%; Bulgaria, 15%; the Czech Republic, 5.5% (not counting Moravians); Hungary, 8.6%; Poland, 2%; Romania, 10.5%; Slovakia, 14.4%. See Bugajski, J., Ethnic Politics in Eastern Europe (1994).Google Scholar

114. Cohen, D., Law, Violence and Community in Classical Athens 82–83 (1995).CrossRefGoogle Scholar

115. Aristotle, Politics at 131 Ib.

116. Id. at 1315a; see also Cohen, , supra note 114, at 145Google Scholar, and Fisher, N.R., Hybris 3031 (1992).Google Scholar

117. Fisher, id. at 509 (summarizing his earlier analyses, notably in Ch. 11).

118. For this distinction, see Gordon, R., The Structure of Emotions 77passim (1987).Google Scholar

119. Rawls, John, A Theory of Justice (1971)Google Scholar, and utilitarians such as Harsanyi, John, Cardinal Welfare, Individualistic Ethics, and Interpersonal Comparisons of Utility, 61 J. Pol. Econ. 309–21 (1955)CrossRefGoogle Scholar, liave in common the assumption of a very thick veil of ignorance, but they differ with respect to the principles of choice they impute to rational individuals behind the veil. Dworkin, R., What Is Equality? Part 2: Equality of Resources, 10 Phil. & Pub. Aff. 283345 (1981)Google Scholar, differs from either in stipulating a thinner veil.

120. Farrand, ed., Records, supra note 23, at 49.Google Scholar

121. Id. at 530.

122. Id., vol. 2, at 3.

123. Id.

124. Id., Vol. 1, at 578.

125. Banfield, E.. The Moral Basis of a Backward Society 83 (1958).Google Scholar

126. Id. at 85.95.

127. Id. at 10.

128. For the most explicit statements, see supra note 80, vol. 9, at 639, 649 ff.Google Scholar

129. Id. at 496.

130. Id. at 410.

131. Montaigne, , supra note 98. at 737.Google Scholar

132. Loury, , supra note 112, at 154Google Scholar; see also Kuran, , supra note 9, at 56.Google Scholar