Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-rdxmf Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-22T05:29:17.801Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Private law theory and taxonomy: reframing the debate

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  02 January 2018

Duncan Sheehan*
Affiliation:
University of East Anglia and Newcastle University
TT Arvind*
Affiliation:
University of East Anglia and Newcastle University
*
Duncan Sheehan, Law School, University of East Anglia, Norwich Research Park, Norwich NR4 7TJ, UK. Email: [email protected]. TT Arvind, Newcastle Law School, Newcastle University, Newcastle upon Tyne NE1 7RU, UK. Email: [email protected]
Duncan Sheehan, Law School, University of East Anglia, Norwich Research Park, Norwich NR4 7TJ, UK. Email: [email protected]. TT Arvind, Newcastle Law School, Newcastle University, Newcastle upon Tyne NE1 7RU, UK. Email: [email protected]

Abstract

The aim of this paper is to reframe the taxonomy debate which has, in recent years, come to dominate private law theory. We argue that the debate to date has been flawed by two fundamental mistakes. First, little attention has been paid to how legal taxonomies are actually used. This, we argue, is regrettable: how we build a taxonomy depends on why we build a taxonomy, and a clearer focus on this question produces an approach that is very different from the approaches that currently dominate private law theory. Secondly, both sides in the debate have misunderstood what legal concepts are, and hence tend to misuse them. We argue that legal concepts are Weberian ideal types, and use philosophical theories of concepts to put forward a very different understanding of how concepts acquire content and are used in the legal system. Putting these together, we argue for a far more developmental, and historically informed, approach to taxonomy and to legal concepts generally.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Society of Legal Scholars 2015 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1. Beever, A and Rickett, CInterpretivism and the academic lawyer’ (2005) 69 Mod L Rev 320.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

2. See eg Hedley, SThe shock of the old: interpretivism in obligations’ in Rickett, C and Grantham, R (eds) Structure and Justification in Private Law (Oxford: Hart Publishing, 2008) p 205.Google Scholar

3. Smith, S Contract Theory (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2004).Google Scholar

4. Beever, APolicy in private law: an admission of failure’ (2006) 25 U Qld L J 287 at 294–297.Google Scholar

5. Birks, Pbh Unjust Enrichment (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2nd edn, 2005).CrossRefGoogle Scholar

6. Hedley, above n 2, pp 206207; seeGoogle Scholar Sheehan, DImplied contract and the structure of unjust enrichment’ in Giliker, P (ed) Re-examining Contract and Unjust Enrichment (Leiden: Brill, 2007) p 185 for an argument that the Birksian grid, and by extension the interpretivist project, can more easily be defended from a Dworkinian outlook.Google Scholar

7. Hedley, SContract, tort and restitution: or on cutting the legal system down to size’ (1988) 8 Legal Stud 137.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

8. Waddams, S Dimensions of Private Law (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 2004).Google Scholar

9. See eg Dagan, H The Law and Ethics of Restitution (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 2005), where although he accepts the existence of the area, he provides some radical reinterpretations based on different values that do, or should, underlie the area.Google Scholar

10. Dagan, HThe “craft” of property’ (2003) 91 Cal L Rev 1519 at 1535–1558 (in the US marital context); in England, seeCrossRefGoogle Scholar Hayward, AFamily property and the process of “familialisation” of property law’ (2012) 24 Child & Fam L Q 284 at 302–303, arguing that the family home (in a non-marital context) has been hived away doctrinally from normal rules about resulting and constructive trusts.Google Scholar

11. Hedley, S A Critical Introduction to Restitution (London: Butterworths, 2001);Google Scholar see also Hedley, S Restitution: Its Division and Ordering (London: Sweet and Maxwell, 2001).Google Scholar

12. Hedley, SUnjust enrichment: the same old mistake’ in Robertson, A (ed) The Law of Obligations: Connections and Boundaries (London: UCL Press, 2004) pp 73, 79;Google Scholar Atiyah, PS An Introduction to the Law of Contract (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 5th edn, 1995) p 40, cfGoogle Scholar Smith, S Atiyah's Introduction to the Law of Contract (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 6th edn, 2006) ch 2.Google Scholar

13. Hedley, above n 7, at 150–168.

14. Dagan, HThe realist conception of law’ (2007) 57 U Toronto L J 607 at 657–658.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

15. In discussing the nature of concepts, this paper does not make any general epistemological claims about concepts or taxonomies. Our claim is not that concepts are necessarily as we describe them to be, in all legal systems and at all times: it is that they are currently so in private law in England and the Commonwealth.

16. See Jolowicz, JAFact-based classification of law’ in Jolowicz, JA (ed) The Division and Classification of the Law (London: Butterworths, 1970).Google Scholar

17. Kant, I Critique of Pure Reason, tr P Gruyer and A Wood (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1999) at A132/B171.Google Scholar

18. A historical example might be the retreat in the 1930s of the English courts from using trusts to provide relief to third parties in contracts, as a result of reclassifying the cases as purely contractual. See Corbin, ALContracts for the benefit of third parties’ (1930) 46 L Q Rev 12. Of course, a Birksian would wince at the equity versus contract divide set up here.Google Scholar

19. Birks, above n 5, p 20.

20. Hedley, SThe taxonomic approach to restitution’ in Hudson, A (ed) New Perspectives on Property Law: Obligations and Restitution (London: Cavendish, 2003) pp 151, 153;Google Scholar Samuel, GCan Gaius really be compared to Darwin?’ (2000) 49 Int'l & Comp L Q 297.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

21. Atiyah, PS Promises, Morals, and Law (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1981).Google Scholar

22. Dagan, HLegal realism and the taxonomy of private law’ in Rickett, C and Grantham, R (eds) Structure and Justification in Private Law (Oxford: Hart Publishing, 2008) pp 147, 161.Google Scholar

23. Samuel, GIs legal knowledge cumulative?’ (2012) 32 Legal Stud 445 at 461. Some interpretivists, such as Steve Smith, adopt a position closer to an inclusive positivism, which accepts the role of morality in hard cases:CrossRefGoogle Scholar Smith, above n 3, pp 1315.Google Scholar

24. Sherwin, ELegal positivism and taxonomy’ in Rickett, C and Grantham, R (eds) Structure and Justification in Private Law (Oxford: Hart Publishing, 2008) pp 103, 123.Google Scholar

25. Smith, above n 3, p 4.

26. Ibid, pp 4–5.

27. Ibid, p 4.

28. Ibid, p 6; Dagan, above n 22, p 160, has suggested that ‘doctrinalist taxonomies’ as he calls them are primarily descriptive; Dworkin's theory has elements of description and prescription according to Kress, KThe interpretive turn’ (1987) 97 Ethics 834.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

29. Waddams, above n 8.

30. Beever and Rickett, above n 1, at 327.

31. See eg Dworkin, R Taking Rights Seriously (London: Duckworth, 1978) p 290.Google Scholar

32. Dworkin, R Law's Empire (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1986) pp 407409.Google Scholar

33. Ibid, pp 405–406.

34. Llewellyn, KRemarks on the theory of appellate decision and the rules or canons about how statutes are to be construed’ (1949) 3 Vand L Rev 395, 396Google Scholar

35. On knowing receipt, see Virgo, G The Principles of Equity and Trusts (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2012) pp 677697.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

36. Birks, above n 5, p 156; Birks may well not have accepted the interprevitist label, but many that do expressly acknowledge a debt to his way of doing things.Google Scholar

37. The High Court of Australia refused to do so in Say-Dee Pty Ltd v Farah Constructions Ltd [2007] HCA 22, (2007) 236 ALR 209. For discussion, see Sheehan, DDisentangling equitable personal liability for receipt and assistance’ [2008] RLR 41;Google Scholar Low, KThe use and abuse of taxonomy’ (2009) 29 Legal Stud 355 at 366–368;CrossRefGoogle Scholar Low, KRecipient liability in equity: resisting the siren's lure’ [2008] RLR 96.Google Scholar

38. Birks, above n 5, p 157.

39. Sheehan, above n 6, pp 211–212.

40. Twining, WErnie and the centipede’ in Jolowicz, above n 16, p 23.Google Scholar

41. That is, specifying that in virtue of X object A differs from all other objects, including those with which it shares characteristics. Davis, WConcepts, individuation, possession conditions and propositional attitudes’ (2005) 39 Noûs 140.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

42. See eg Beever and Rickett, above n 1, at 328.

43. Davis, above n 41, at 142.

44. Dworkin, R Justice for Hedgehogs (Cambridge, MA: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, 2011) pp 161163;Google Scholar Dworkin, RJudicial discretion’ (1963) 60 J Phil 624 at 632.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

45. Margolis, E and Laurence, SThe ontology of concepts: abstract objects or mental representations?’ (2007) 41 Noûs 561.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

46. Frege, GOn sense and reference’ in Geach, P and Black, M (eds) Translations from the Philosophical Writings of Gottlob Frege (Oxford: Blackwell, 1952) p 57.Google Scholar

47. Gupta, A and Belnap, NA note on extension, intension and truth’ (1987) 84 J Phil 168 at 168.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

48. DiMatteo, LA theory of interpretation in the realm of idealism’ (2006) 5 DePaul Bus & Com L Rev 17 at 34.Google Scholar

49. See eg Burrows, ASContract, tort and restitution – a satisfactory division or not?’ (1983) 99 L Q Rev 217.Google Scholar

50. Hedley, above n 7, at 137.

51. Narain, JClassification of law: a realist view’ in Jolowicz, above n 5, pp 4648.Google Scholar

52. Jolowicz, above n 5, p 9.

53. Shivakumar, DThe pure theory as ideal type: defending Kelsen on the basis of Weberian methodology’ (1996) 105 Yale L J 1383 at 1401–1403.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

54. Weber, M The Methodology of the Social Sciences (New York: Free Press, 1969) p 90.Google Scholar

55. Ibid, p 103.

56. Weber, above n 54, p 93.

57. Shivakumar, above n 54, at 1399.

58. Fried, C Contract as Promise: A Theory of Contractual Obligation (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1982).Google Scholar

59. Barnett, RA consent theory of contract’ (1986) 86 Colum L Rev 299.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

60. Atiyah, above n 12.

61. Arvind, TTContract transactions and equity’ in DiMatteo, L et al (eds) Commercial Contract Law: Transatlantic Perspectives (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 2013) ch 7.Google Scholar

62. MacNeil, I The New Social Contract: An Inquiry into Modern Contractual Relations (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1980).Google Scholar

63. Ibid, pp 90–91.

64. See Sheehan, above n 6, p 190.

65. Samuel, GEnglish private law: old and new thinking in the taxonomy debate’ (2004) 24 Oxford J Legal Stud 335 at 339.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

66. McMeel, GWhat kind of jurist was Peter Birks?’ [2011] RLR 15;Google Scholar Birks, never having really engaged with theoretical jurisprudence (Sheehan, above n 6, p 194), would not have described himself as Leibnizian; this is avowedly a reconstruction of his views.Google Scholar

67. Hoeflich, MHLaw and geometry: legal science from Leibniz to Langdell’ (1986) 30 Am J Legal Hist 95 at 100.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

68. Kahn-Freund, OIntroduction’ in Renner, K The Institutions of Private Law and Their Social Functions, tr A Schwarzschild (London: Routledge, 1949) pp 1, 2.Google Scholar

69. Sheehan, above n 6, pp 211–212.

70. Stevens, R Torts and Rights (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007) pp 329337; Stevens seems to accept this when he suggests that his (short) account will seem naïve to any familiar with the rights literature (p 329).CrossRefGoogle Scholar

71. Smith, above n 3, p 9.

72. On inclusive legal positivism and the moral norms in judicial decisions, see eg Coleman, JBeyond inclusive legal positivism’ (2009) 22 Ratio Juris 359;CrossRefGoogle Scholar Einar Himma, KFinal authority to bind with moral mistakes: on the explanatory potential of inclusive legal positivism’ (2005) 24 Law & Phil 1 at 2;CrossRefGoogle Scholar Waluchow, W Inclusive Legal Positivism (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1994) pp 140141.Google Scholar

73. Dagan, above n 14, at 658–659; Smith, SWRight answers and realism: Ronald Dworkin's theory of integrity as a successor to realism’ (2013) 64 N Ireland L Q 507.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

74. Dworkin, R Justice in Robes (Cambridge, MA: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, 2007) p 25.Google Scholar

75. Peel, E (ed) Treitel's Law of Contract (London: Sweet and Maxwell, 13th edn, 2011) pp 136140.Google Scholar

76. Dworkin, above n 31, pp 92–93.

77. Ibid, pp 26–27.

78. Sherwin, above n 24, p 11.

79. In principle, it is possible to come up with as many axes as one might like – sector of (defendant's) activity, type of relationship between claimant and defendant, type of relationship between defendant and impugned act, type of relationship between defendant and harm suffered, and so on. At some stage, however, the creation of more axes runs into diminishing returns. The two discussed here are simply intended as general examples. Others might be more relevant in specific instances, or as specific instances of the application of these two general axes.

80. Dworkin, above n 32, pp 238–254.

81. On which, see Robertson, AConstraints on policy based reasoning in the law’ in Robertson, A and Wu, TH (eds) The Goals of Private Law (Oxford: Hart Publishing, 2009) p 261.Google Scholar

82. One example of this might be the proposal by the Law Commission in 1992 that the factors taken into account in various regulatory frameworks governing (eg) solicitors, accountants etc, be absorbed into the factors taken into account by courts in deciding if these defendants have breached their fiduciary duties or not. See Law Commission Fiduciary Duties and Regulatory Rules (LCCP no 124 1992) at 220–224.

83. Dworkin, above n 32, p 268.

84. See generally Burrows, AS The Law of Restitution (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 3rd edn, 2011) ch 10.Google Scholar

85. Dworkin, above n 31, pp 90–94.

86. Ibid, p 104.

87. Dagan, above n 14, at 659; Dagan, above n 22, p 161.

88. Lundstedt, AV Obligationsbegreppet I: Fakta och Fiktioner (Uppsala: ABL Norblads Bokhandel, 1929) pp 107127;Google Scholar Lundstedt, AVHar rättsvetenskap behov av rättsideologi?’ in Festskrift tillägnad Thore Engströmer (Uppsala: Almqvist & Wiksells, 1943) pp 107142.Google Scholar

89. On which, see Nourse, V and Shaffer, GVarieties of new legal realism: can a new world order prompt a new legal theory?’ (2009) 95 Cornell L Rev 61.Google Scholar

90. See Weinrib, E The Idea of Private Law (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1995).Google Scholar

91. Smith, LDRestitution: the heart of corrective justice’ (2001) 79 Tex L Rev 2115. Lionel Smith, it should be noted, has not adopted the label ‘interpretivist’, but does nevertheless argue for closely related positions – in particular, in relation to corrective justice.Google Scholar

92. Dworkin, R A Matter of Principle (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1985) pp 137138.Google Scholar

93. Smith, above n 3, p 8.

94. Austen-Baker, RGrant Gilmore and the strange case of the failure of contract to die after all’ (2002) 18 J Cont Law 1;Google Scholar Gilmore, G The Death of Contract (Columbus, OH: Ohio State University Press, 1974).Google Scholar

95. Atiyah, PS The Rise and Fall of Freedom of Contract (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1979); see egGoogle Scholar Baker, John's review in (1980) 43 Mod L Rev 467.Google Scholar

96. Sidhu v Van Dyke [2014] HCA 19.

97. And he admitted as much, saying that we must always be on alert for the possibility of error and inaccuracy. See Birks, PbhEquity in the modern law: an exercise in taxonomy’ (1996) 26 U W Austl L Rev 1 at 4.Google Scholar

98. Nothing more fine-grained than our understanding of a concept can ever play any part in formulating propositions of law. Peacocke, C A Study of Concepts (Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press, 1992) p 5.Google Scholar

99. Taylor, C Hegel (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 2005) p 321.Google Scholar

100. Ibid, p 325.

101. Ibid, p 328; the Concept is derived from both being and essence but is reducible to neither. Houlgate, SWhy Hegel's concept is not the essence of things’ (2004) 3 Cardozo Pub L Pol'y & Ethics J 31 at 32.Google Scholar

102. Discussed by Wartenberg, THegel's idealism: the logic of conceptuality’ in Beiser, E (ed) Cambridge Companion to Hegel (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 2006) p 102;Google Scholar Taylor, above n 99, p 111.

103. Brandom, RSome pragmatist themes in Hegel's idealism’ (1999) 7 Eur J Phil 164 at 179–181.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

104. On the connection between Dworkin's theory and ideas of authority, see Jaffey, PAuthority in the common law’ (2011) 36 Austl J Legal Phil 1.Google Scholar

105. DiMatteo, above n 48, at 18, 46.

106. For one recent example of a contextualist treatise that does precisely this, see Merkin, R and Steele, J Insurance and the Law of Obligations (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2013).CrossRefGoogle Scholar

107. Beever, above n 4, at 294–297.

108. [2003] UKHL 66, [2004] 2 AC 42.