Article contents
Luhmann without tears: complex economic regulation and the erosion of the market sphere
Published online by Cambridge University Press: 02 January 2018
Abstract
One of the concepts central to the ‘reconceiving’ of the ‘regulatory state’ during ‘the age of regulatory reform’ which we might trace back to the neoliberal revolution of the 1970s, has been that of the ‘hybrid’ form of economic organisation. Rejection of command-and-control regulation led, in the public sector, to the adoption of ‘marketmimicking’, a technique that claimed to replace the hierarchical direction of planning with the mobilisation of self-interest in ‘quasi-markets’, thereby merging ‘economic’ incentivisation with the ‘political’ stipulation of the markets' outcomes. In the private sector, institutions that had long been recognised to sit between contract and the company, of which the franchise had been the most thoroughly analysed within contract law, began to be regarded as ‘networks’.
- Type
- Research Article
- Information
- Copyright
- Copyright © Society of Legal Scholars 2013
Footnotes
I am grateful to Oliver Gerstenberg, Matthias Klaes and Jiri Přibáň for their comments, to which the normal disclaimer applies in force.
References
1. Pashukanis, EB‘Economics and legal regulation’ in Pashukanis, EB Selected Writings on Marxism and Law (London: Academic Press, 1980) p 237.Google Scholar
2. Unattributed page references in parentheses are to the book under review.
3. Powell, WW, ‘Neither markets nor hierarchies: network forms of organisation’ (1990) 12 Research in Org Behav 295.Google Scholar
4. Collins provides a list of the principal works in English (2 n 2).
5. Hereinafter NCC.
6. I must point out that I have contributed to this series.
7. Amstutz, M and Teubner, G (eds)Networks: Legal Issues of Multilateral Co-operation (Oxford: Hart, 2010).Google Scholar
8. Teubner, G‘ Coincidentia oppositorum: hybrid networks beyond contract and organisation’ in Amstutz, and Teubner, (eds), above n 8.Google Scholar
9. Of which Collins, H Regulating Contracts (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999)Google Scholar is the most important. Collins gave a highly interesting paper at Fribourg, :‘The weakest link: legal implications of the network architecture of supply chains’ in Amstutz, and Teubner, (eds), above n 8.Google Scholar Both it, and the comments on it by Mouzas, Stephan in Amstutz, and Teubner, (eds), above n 8,Google Scholar seem to me to be ambivalent about the possibility of welfare-enhancing general regulation of networks in a way that also is manifest in Collin's Introduction to NCC.
10. Buxbaum, RM ‘Is “network” a legal concept?’ (1993) 149 J Inst'l & Theoretical Econ 698, 704.Google Scholar
11. Teubner's Fribourg paper also starts with this reference to Buxbaum: Teubner, , above n 9, p 3.Google Scholar Evidently, the Fribourg conference was preoccupied with Buxbaum's question: G-P Calliess ‘Fitness clubs: consumer protection between contract and association’ in Amstutz and Teubner (eds), above n 8, p 243.
12. Teubner, G ‘Legal irritants: good faith in British law, or how unifying law ends up in new divergencies’ (1998) 61 Mod L Rev 11.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
13. Collins takes this line (22–23).
14. In a Fribourg paper that I found particularly interesting, Gralf-Peter Calliess, above n 12, examined the consumer regulation of fitness clubs.
15. I leave aside the relationship of this classification to the larger number of ‘specific risks of networks’ identified in ch 1 (100–111).
16. The problems set out in chs 4 and 5 are regarded, it seems perfectly legitimately, as third-party problems by Marina Wellenhofer and Manfred Wolf in their Fribourg papers: Wellenhoffer, M,‘Third party effects of bilateral contracts within the network’ in Amstutz, and Teubner, (eds), above n 8;Google Scholar Wolf, M,‘The protection of contractual networks against interference by third parties’ in Amstutz, and Teubner, (eds), above n 8.Google Scholar Wellenhofer, loc cit, 129, is of the opinion that ‘there is no need for a new innovative approach’. Wolf reaches the opposite conclusion.
17. Hereinafter BGB.
18. Available at (accessed 22 December 2012).
19. A long second part of this subsection has special provisions for conveyances of interests in land.
20. With Heerman, I am unsure whether it is possible ever to include end consumers in the network, or what Teubner's position exactly is on this. This statement of the proprium of connected contracts seems to exclude it, but it seems to be necessary if regulation in their interests is to be possible on the basis of identifying a network: Heermann, PW‘The status of multilateral synallagmas in the law of connected contracts’ in Amstutz, and Teubner, (eds), above n 8, p 110. The point is also taken by Collins (65).Google Scholar
21. Nooteboom, B,Inter-firm Alliances (London: Routledge, 1999);CrossRefGoogle Scholar Nooteboom, B,Inter-firm Collaboration, Learning and Networks (London: Routledge, 2004).Google Scholar
22. Daintith, T‘Mixed public–private networks as vehicles for regulatory policy’ in Amstutz, and Teubner, (eds), above n 8, 298–299.Google Scholar
23. Druey, JN‘The path to the law: the difficult legal access of networks’ in Amstutz, and Teubner, (eds), above n 8, 87, 94–95. Teubner himself puts forward some observations on ‘mixed contracts’ (131).Google Scholar
24. Unless my reading is faulty, coincidentia oppositorum does not appear in NCC itself but is the core of Teubner's Fribourg paper: Teubner, above n 9.
25. Druey, , above n 24, p 95.Google Scholar
26. Smith, A Wealth of Nations (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1976) p 456.Google Scholar
27. Chandler, AD Jr The Visible Hand (Cambridge, MA, Belknap Press, 1977) pp 1–3.Google Scholar
28. Why, indeed, cannot both of these paradoxes be applied to both of these forms of organisation?
29. Teubner, G Law as an Autopoietic System (Oxford: Blackwell, 1993) ch 7.Google Scholar Collins himself describes the public company as a network on the basis of accepting the agency theory of the corporation (8–9), when that theory has no basis in empirical reality whatsoever: Campbell, D ‘The role of monitoring and morality in company law: a criticism of the direction of present regulation’ (1997) 7 Austl J Corp L 343.Google Scholar
30. Whitehead, AN Process and Reality (New York: Harper, 1929) p 17.Google Scholar
31. Teubner, , above n 9, 3.Google Scholar Teubner further restated his views in a paper identified by Collins (2 n 2), which is a chapter in a book that was unpublished at the time NCC appeared: Teubner, G‘Sociological jurisprudence – impossible but necessary: the case of networks’ in Gordon, RW and Horwitz, MJ (eds)Law, Society and History (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2011).Google Scholar
32. Coase, RH‘The nature of the firm’ in Coase, RH The Firm, the Market and the Law (Chicago Ill, University of Chicago Press, 1986).Google Scholar
33. Marx, K Capital, vol 1 (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1976) p 779.Google ScholarPubMed This passage is omitted from the Collected Works edition of volume one, which retains what Marx had put in the three previous German editions. This omission from the normally immensely exhaustive Collected Works is puzzling, especially as I cannot find this important passage anywhere else in the Collected Works. One fears that its omission was motivated by a superficial and unnecessary embarrassment about Engels' prediction not having come to pass.
34. Hilferding, R Finance Capital (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1981) p 234.Google Scholar
35. Campbell, D‘The critique of bourgeois justice after the failure of Marxism’ in Kerner, A Přibáň, J and Young, J (eds)Current Legal Issues in the Czech Republic and the United Kingdom (Prague: Charles University Press, 2003) pp 18–23.Google Scholar
36. Coase, , above n 33, p 36.Google Scholar
37. Ibid, p 35.
38. Ibid, pp 35–36.
39. Barnard, C The Functions of the Executive (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1953) ch 12.Google ScholarPubMed
40. Coase, , above n 33, p 36.Google Scholar
41. Ibid, p 38.
42. Campbell, D and Klaes, M ‘The principle of institutional direction: Coase's regulatory critique of intervention’ (2005) 29 Cambridge J Econ 263, 269.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
43. Williamson, OE The Economic Institutions of Capitalism (New York: Free Press, 1985).Google Scholar
44. Macneil, IR ‘Contracts: adjustment of long-term economic relations under classical, neo-classical and relational contract law’ (1978) 72 Nw UL Rev 854.Google Scholar
45. Landes, DS‘Introduction’ in Landes, DS (ed)The Rise of Capitalism (London: Collier-Macmillan, 1966) p 12.Google Scholar
46. Landes, D The Unbound Prometheus (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2nd edn, 2003) pp 43–44, 114, 117–120.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
47. Marshall, A Industry and Trade (New York: Cosimo Classics, 2011) pp 507–576.Google Scholar
48. Robertson, DH and Dennison, S The Control of Industry (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, new edn, 1960) p 9.Google ScholarPubMed Coase makes important reference to the 1928 edn of this work in ‘The nature of the firm’, above n 33, pp 34, 35.
49. Deakin, S‘The return of the guild? Network relations in historical perspective’ in Amstutz, and Teubner, (eds), above n 8, 53.Google Scholar
50. Kjaer, PK‘Post-Hegelian networks’ in Amstutz, and Teubner, (eds), above n 8, p 85.Google Scholar
51. Ibid.
52. In addition to Teubner himself, Abegg and Amstutz made valuable general statements of the network idea at the Fribourg conference: Abegg, A‘Regulation of hybrid networks at the intersection between governmental administration and economic self-organisation’ in Amstutz, and Teubner, (eds), above n 8;Google Scholar Amstutz, M‘The constitution of contractual networks’ in Amstutz, and Teubner, , above n 8.Google Scholar
53. I do not find Collins’ treatment of this (66), which seems to retreat into vagueness, convincing.
54. Schumpeter, JA Capitalism, Socialism and Democracy (London: George Allen and Unwin, 5th edn, 1979) p 83.Google Scholar
55. And so Collins can accept the empirical existence of a network but not think this is sufficient to justify regulation. In his Introduction, he can, then, state his (in itself surprising) belief that agency workers should benefit from the ‘normal consequences of employment law’ (62) whilst, in his Fribourg paper, also say that he did not think further legal intervention was needed in regard of supply chains: Collins, ‘The weakest link: legal implications of the network architecture of supply chains’, above n 10.Google Scholar
56. Daintith, , above n 23, p 301.Google Scholar
57. This quotation is taken from Abegg, 's paper: Abegg, above n 53, p 268.Google Scholar
58. Daintith, , above n 23, pp 307–308.Google Scholar
59. In her interesting Fribourg paper, Cordula Heldt tries to develop the network argument alongside the concept of spontaneous order: Heldt, C‘Internal relations and semi-spontaneous order: the case of franchising and construction contracts’ in Amstutz, and Teubner, (eds), above n 8. I am afraid I cannot agree with her interpretation of Hayek's view of the role of what she calls a ‘made order’ and its relationship to spontaneous order.Google Scholar
60. Campbell, and Klaes, , above n 43, pp 273–276.Google Scholar
61. Coase, , above n 33, p 37 n 14.Google Scholar
62. Collins cites two excellent, thought-provoking papers on this point. I would add that in arguably the most influential body of academic work on the subject, that of Stewart Macaulay, the point is also taken: Macaulay, S‘Long-term continuing relations: the American experience regulating dealerships and franchises’ in Joerges, C (ed)Franchising and the Law (Baden Baden: Nomos, 1991). Teubner refers to this paper (101 n 95).Google Scholar
63. Reinhard Böhber's Fribourg paper, whilst much more sympathetic to a position like Teubner's than I am, seems to me to authoritatively raise many important problems: Böhner, R‘Asset-sharing in franchise networks: the obligation to pass on network benefits’ in Amstutz, and Teubner, (eds), above n 8.Google Scholar
64. 133 NW 2d 267 (WI 1965).
65. Scott, R ‘ Hoffman v. Red Owl Stores and the limits of the legal method’ (2010) 61 Hastings LJ 859.Google Scholar
66. On the spelling of Hoffmann's name, see ibid, 861 n 5.
67. Four of the Fribourg papers selected for publication by Amstutz and Teubner closely examine the operation of the German Law, including the relevant provisions of the BGB: Heermann, , above n 21;Google Scholar Wellenhoffer, , above n 17;Google Scholar Heldt, , above n 60 andGoogle Scholar Böhner, , above n 64.Google Scholar
68. Teubner, G (ed)Autopoietic Law (Berlin: Walter de Gruyter, 1988).Google Scholar
69. Teubner, G (ed)State, Law and Economy as Autopoietic Systems (Milan: Guiffre, 1992).Google Scholar
70. Mead, GH Mind, Self and Society (Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press, 1934) p 91.Google Scholar
71. Luhmann, N A Sociological Theory of Law (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1985) pp 167–168.Google Scholar Luhmann gave a revised statement of the point in Luhmann, N Law as a Social System (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2004) ch 11.Google Scholar
72. Luhmann, N The Differentiation of Society (New York: Columbia University Press, 1982) p 346.Google Scholar
73. Luhmann, N Risk: A Sociological Theory (New York: Walter de Gruyter, 1993) p 78.Google Scholar
74. Ewald, F‘The law of law’ in Teubner, (ed), above n 69, p 36.Google Scholar
75. Habermas, J‘Law and morality’ in McMurrin, SM (ed)The Tanner Lectures on Human Values, vol 8 (Salt Lake City, UT: University of Utah Press, 1988) pp 251–259.Google Scholar
76. Luhmann, N‘The cognitive programme of constructivism and a reality that remains unknown’ in Krohn, W, Küpper, G and Nowotny, H (eds)Selforganization: Portrait of a Scientific Revolution (Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1990).Google Scholar
77. Luhmann, N Social Systems (Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 1995) ch 12.Google Scholar
78. Luhmann, Law as a Social System, above n 72, p 80.Google Scholar
79. Parsons, T The Structure of Social Action (New York: Free Press, rev edn, 1968) pp xxi–xxii.Google Scholar
80. Ibid, pp 473–487.
81. Perhaps what is fundamentally novel in Luhmann's conception of social systems is his abandonment of Parsons' input/output conception of those systems. It is not functionalism as such but any causal relationship with the environment that Luhmann rejects: Luhmann, Law as a Social System, above n 72, pp 382–383.Google Scholar
82. Luhmann, N ‘The third question: the creative use of paradox in law and legal theory’ (1998) 15 JL & Soc'y 153.Google Scholar
83. Jameson, F Postmodernism, or, the Cultural Logic of Late Capitalism (Durham, NC: Duke University Press, 1991).Google Scholar
84. Luhmann, N ‘Why does society describe itself as postmodern?’ (1995) 30 Cultural Critique 171.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
85. Luhmann, N‘Modernity in contemporary society’ in Luhmann, N,Observations on Modernity (Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 1998).Google Scholar
86. Moran, M The British Regulatory State (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2003) pp 171, 183.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
87. Luhmann, A Sociological Theory of Law, above n 72, p 282.Google Scholar
88. In the view of Matthias Klaes and myself, attempts to reduce global greenhouse gas emissions are inevitably bound to fail because of shortcomings in the international climate change negotiations that have followed the UN Framework Convention on Climate Change: Campbell, D, Klaes, M and Bignell, C ‘After Cancun: the impossibility of carbon trading’ (2010) 29 U Ql LJ 163.Google Scholar This has not prevented the burgeoning growth of national and international institutions committed to this impossible project; and, as we write, these institutions remain largely immune to the now unchallengeable evidence of the immense growth of emissions over the 20 years since the Framework Convention was opened for signature in 1992. Our initial understanding of this phenomenon was in terms of Luhmann's view on environmentalism, though we have been unable to give a sustained account of it in those terms.
89. Luhmann, N Political Theory in the Welfare State (Berlin: Walter de Gruyter, 1990) pp 216–217.Google Scholar
90. Luhmann, , above n 78, pp 469–471.Google Scholar
91. Ibid, p 471.
92. There are, of course, other concepts that seek to capture something like Luhmann's point. Moran has a concept of ‘hyper-innovation’, which itself is very interesting but does not capture the reflexivity of Luhmann's hypercomplexity.
93. Luhmann, N Ecological Communication (Cambridge: Polity Press, 1989) p 74.Google Scholar
94. King, M ‘The construction and demolition of the Luhmann heresy’ (2001) 12 Law & Critique 1, 15–17.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
95. Teubner, , above n 30, p 97.Google Scholar
96. Ibid.
97. Ibid.
98. Campbell, D ‘The limits of concept formation in legal science’ (2000) 9 Soc & Legal Stud 439, 442.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
99. My views have, in fact, been reinforced, because during those years I read Between Facts and Norms and found, I think, the point I sought to make made by Habermas: Habermas, J Between Facts and Norms (Cambridge: Polity Press, 1996) pp 51–56.Google Scholar I derive great confidence from the acknowledgement of my point by Michael King, whose work, often with Chris Thornhill, has been the leading account of Luhmann's theory of law in English: King, M‘What's the use of Luhmann's theory?’ in King, M and Thornhill, C (eds)Luhmann on Politics and Law (Oxford: Hart, 2006) p 42.Google Scholar
100. Teubner, G ‘How the law thinks: toward a constructivist epistemology of law’ (1989) 23 Law & Soc'y Rev 727, 736.CrossRefGoogle Scholar See further Teubner, G‘Dealing with paradoxes of law: Derrida, Luhmann, Wiethölter’ in Perez, O and Teubner, G (eds)Paradox and Inconsistencies in the Law (Oxford: Hart, 2005).Google Scholar
101. Teubner, G‘ Altera pars auditur: law in the collision of discourses’ in Rawlings, R (ed)Law, Society and Economy (Oxford, Clarendon Press, 1997) p 166.Google Scholar
102. Ibid, p 176.
103. Teubner, G‘The invisible cupola: from causal to collective attribution in ecological liability’ in Teubner, G, Farmer, L and Murphy, D (eds)Environmental Law and Ecological Responsibility (Chichester: Wiley, 1994).Google Scholar
104. Ibid, p 27.
105. Selznick, P‘Self-regulation and the theory of institutions’ in Teubner, et al, above n 104, p 395.Google Scholar
106. Teubner, G‘After legal instrumentalism: strategic models of post-regulatory law’ in Teubner, G (ed)Dilemmas of Law in the Welfare State (New York: Walter de Gruyter, 1988) p 309. Collins seems to take the point (31).Google Scholar
107. Teubner, above n 13. In a 2002 paper focusing on just in time manufacturing, Teubner anticipated criticisms such as those Daintith and I have put forward of network regulation, but defends the possibility of such regulation, though ‘totally incomprehensible from the Anglo-American standpoint’, as appropriate to Germany because ‘it makes sense, however, if one takes into account the varieties of capitalism’: Teubner, G ‘Idiosyncratic production regimes: co-evolution of economic and legal institutions in the varieties of capitalism’ (2002) 112 Proc Br Acad 161, 180–181.Google Scholar
108. Teubner, G‘General aspects’ in Teubner, G (ed)Juridification of Social Spheres (Berlin: Walter de Gruyter, 1987).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
109. Born in what is now the Czech Republic, Renner's education and his professional and political life were entirely centred on Vienna under the Austro-Hungarian Empire and subsequently the Austrian Republic, the Third Reich and the Second Austrian Republic. He supported Anschluss throughout the interwar period. The point is that the intellectual milieu of his views was German.
110. Kahn Freund also preceded Collins as a Fellow of Brasenose College, Oxford.
111. See now Renner, K The Institutions of Private Law and their Social Functions (New Brunswick, NJ: Transaction Publishers, 2010).Google Scholar
112. Luhmann, , above n 86, p 8.Google Scholar
113. Ibid, pp 5–6.
114. Campbell, , above n 36 andGoogle Scholar Campbell, D, ‘How sensible is the left-wing criticism of money, exchange and contract’ (2011) 20 Soc & Legal Stud 528.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
115. Though in much current regulatory theory Marx's critique of regarding labour as a commodity has been eclipsed by that of Polanyi, Marx's far more wide-ranging background critique of the alienation of labour has damaging implications for Teubner's concept of a network. Though in his discussion of ‘re-entry’ Teubner perceives (and seeks to limit the consequences of) some of the shortcomings of the ‘pure’ concepts of contract and organisation (135–136, 211–213), he is able to fashion his concept of a network only by constructing a paradox from the purely individualist and purely associative terms of a contradiction. But, to focus on just the first term, it is wrong to think that the economic actor in an exchange relationship is the atomistic individual of classical and neoclassical economics and the classical law of contract. This actor's capacity to exchange is intrinsically based on social relations, which have an integral element of trust that cannot be reduced to economic calculation, or, indeed, to a purely private economics at all: Campbell, D‘The relational constitution of contract and the limits of “economics:” Kenneth Arrow on the social background of markets’ in Deakin, S and Michie, J (eds)Contracts, Co-operation and Competition: Studies in Economics, Management and Law (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1997);Google Scholar Campbell, D‘The “hybrid contract” and the merging of the public and private law of the allocation of economic goods’ in Campbell, D and Lewis, ND (eds)Promoting Participation: Law or Politics? (London, Cavendish Publishing, 1999).Google ScholarPubMed Collins' commitment to the network concept represents a shift from his earlier views in this respect, for his earlier critique of the law of contrast involved a Marxist perception of the alienation of economic action: Collins, H The Law of Contract (London: Weidenfeld and Nicolson, 1986) pp 3–5. In support of his views there, Collins' cites Renner's book: ibid, p 210.Google Scholar
116. Teubner, G‘“Global Bukowina”: legal pluralism in the world society in Teubner, G (ed)Global Law Without a State (Aldershot: Dartmouth, 1997).Google Scholar
117. Teubner, G‘Social constitutionalism: alternatives to state-centred constitutional theory’ in Joerges, C, Sand, I-J and Teubner, G (eds)Transnational Governance and Constitutionalism (Oxford: Hart, 2004).Google Scholar
118. Teubner, G ‘The anonymous matrix: human rights violations by “private” transnational actors’ (2006) 69 Mod L Rev 327.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
119. Teubner, G Constitutional Fragments (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2012).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
120. Teubner, G‘A constitutional moment? The logics of “hitting the bottom”’ in Kjaer, PF, Teubner, G and Febbrajo, A (eds)The Financial Crisis in Constitutional Perspective (Oxford: Hart, 2011) p 11.Google Scholar
121. Coase, RH Economists and public policy in Coase, RH Essays on Economics and Economists (Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press, 1992) p 62.Google Scholar
122. Campbell ‘The “hybrid contract” and the merging of the public and private law of the allocation of economic goods ,’ above n 116; Campbell, D ‘Relational contract and the nature of private ordering: a comment on Vincent-Jones’ (2007) 14 Ind J Global Legal Stud 279;CrossRefGoogle Scholar Campbell, D ‘Gathering the water: abuse of rights after the recognition of government failure’ (2010) 7 J Jurisprudence 413;Google Scholar Campbell, D ‘Dicey in the age of globalisation’ (2011) 17 Eur Public L 571.Google Scholar
123. Coase, RH ‘Advertising and free speech’ (1977) 6 J Legal Stud 1, 5.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
124. Campbell, D ‘Bringing law and lawyers to the people: statism and anarchy in left-wing legal thought’ (2002) 11 Soc & Legal Stud 413.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
125. Tanzi, V and Schuknecht, L Public Spending in the 20th Century (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000) table 1.1.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
126. Castles, FG‘Testing the retrenchment hypothesis: an aggregate overview’ in Castles, FG (ed)The Disappearing State (Cheltenham: Edward Elgar, 2007) ch 2.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
127. Teubner, , above n 30, p 158Google Scholar.
128. Goodrich, P ‘Law's labour's lost’ (2009) 72 Mod L Rev 296, 310.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
129. Daintith, , above n 23, p 293.Google Scholar
130. Prior to Collins' Introduction, Roger Brownsword, sometimes in work with the late John Adams, had done the most to develop the network idea within the English law of contract. His Fribourg paper helpfully reviews an important body of work going back to 1989: Brownsword, R‘Network contracts revisited’ in Amstutz, and Teubner, (eds), above n 8.Google Scholar Reasons of space prevent me from exploring the English law literature on networks. I will say only that Brownsword's work has struggled with the fact that it was principally stimulated by Junior Books Ltd v Veitchi Co Ltd [1983] 1 AC 250 (HL), which, though at the time lauded as a way of getting round an illegitimate contractual way of determining the range of liability, surely was an inauspicious foundation. But in Collins' Introduction (55–56), we find him welcoming the possibility that the Teubnerian network might put fresh legs under Junior Books. This seems to revive views Collins held about this case in the 1980s, from which he had, out of greater respect for the parties' allocation of risks rather than what was needed ‘as a matter of fairness’, moved away: cf Collins, H The Law of Contract (London: Weidenfeld and Nicolson, 1986) pp 109, 113;Google Scholar Collins, H The Law of Contract (London: Butterworths, 4th edn, 2003) pp 323, 327–328.Google Scholar
131. I am seeking to turn Teubner's own usage against him: Teubner, , above n 121, pp 3–10.Google Scholar
132. Druey, , above n 26, pp 95–96.Google Scholar
- 1
- Cited by