Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-r5fsc Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-20T12:44:36.479Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Rights and Law: Analysis and Theory by Andrew Halpin, Oxford: Hart Publishing, 1997, ix + 226 + (bibliography and index) 18 pp (paperback £16.99, hardback £35)

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  02 January 2018

Abstract

Image of the first page of this content. For PDF version, please use the ‘Save PDF’ preceeding this image.'
Type
Book Review
Copyright
Copyright © Society of Legal Scholars 1998

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1. Halpin, Andrew Righrs and Law: Analysis and Theory (Oxford: Hart Publishing, 1997) (hereafter R&L) pp 823 Google Scholar.

2. See Hart, H L ADefinition and Theory in Jurisprudence’ in Essays in Jurisprudence and Philosophy (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1983) pp 2148 CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

3. See Finnis, John Natural Law and Natural Rights (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1980) ch 1Google Scholar.

4. R&L pp 106, 123, 137.

5. Although see Hart above n 2 at 21-48; Finnis above n 3; Brian Bix ‘Conceptual Questions and Jurisprudence’ (1995) 1 Legal Theory 465.

6. It is not obvious how the use of “conception” at pp 106ff is consistent with the rejection of that term at p 11.

7. R&L pp 27-48.

8. Raz, Joseph and MacCormick, NeilVoluntary Obligations and Normative Powers’ (1972) 46 Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volume 59 at 81Google Scholar.

9. R&L pp 60-68.

9a. The tramp example is traditional. However, occasionally life imitates jurisprudence. Shortly before Christmas, a vagrant in France committed and confessed to a crime so as to spend midwinter in a relatively warm cell. Unfortunately the court sentenced him to precisely 12 months’ imprisonment with no parole: ‘Warm-up in the cooler backfires’ Guardian 22 December 1997.

10. R&L p 72.

11. R&L pp 81-94. 12. R&L p 86.

13. R&L p 98.

14. R&L p 106.

15. R&L pp 114-122.

16. R&L p p 1 13- 1 14.

17. R&L p 12.

18. R&L pp 127-140.

19. [1932] AC 562.

20. See Twining, William and Mien, David How to Do Things with Rules (London: Weidenfeld and Nicolson, 3rd edn, 1991) pp 181–182 Google Scholar.

21. R&L p 157.

22. R&L p 152.

23. See the analysis of Elmer's Case in Schauer, Frederick Playing by the Rules: A Philosophical Examination of Rule-Based Decision-Making in Law and in Life (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1991) pp 200206 Google Scholar.

24. R&L pp 123, 156.

25. R&L pp 159-165.

26. Outlined above, text accompanying n 17.

27. There are brief references to these problems on pp 172 and 173. On institutional choice, see generally Komesar, Neil K Imperfect Alternatives: Choosing Institutions in Law, Economics, and Public Policy (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1994)Google Scholar.

28. Eg Anthony Lester ‘English Judges as Law Makers’ [1993] PL 269 at 27 1; John Laws ‘Is the High Court the Guardian of Fundamental Constitutional Rights’ [1993] PL 59 at

29. Eg R&L pp 8,20, 21.66, 89, 100, 101, 119.

30. See the discussion of ‘false scent’ in Fowler, H W (rev Ernest Gowers) A Dictionary of Modern English Usage (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1965) pp 187188 Google Scholar.

31. R&L p 265, emphasis in original.