Published online by Cambridge University Press: 02 January 2018
Legal paternalism occurs when the law forces individuals to avoid certain risks (‘hard paternalism’), or, without coercion, nudges them away from such risks (‘soft paternalism’), on the ground that otherwise they will make unwise decisions. The questions when and how such approaches should be taken are of fundamental importance in a society in which there are increasing risks to health and livelihood resulting from technological developments and greater freedom of choice. However, they are not openly addressed in policy-making circles and have also been neglected in the European legal literature. In this paper, I attempt to explain these paradoxes and to outline a theoretical benefit–cost framework for determining when and how legal paternalism might be considered appropriate.
I am grateful to Willem Van Boom and to members of the Behavioural Approaches to Contract and Tort Research Programme for comments on an earlier presentation; also to Professor Jenny Steele and the editors for some helpful suggestions.
This is an extended version of an inaugural lecture delivered at the University of Rotterdam on 14 May 2009.
1. A survey in 2002 revealed that 25.1% of cyclists wore helmets on major built-up roads ( Gregory, K, Inwood, C and Sexton, B TRL Research Report 578 Cycle Helmet Wearing in 2002 (London: Department for Transport, 2003)Google Scholar). In Greater London, the figure (for 2000) was 50% ( Fulbrook, J Cycle helmets and contributory negligence’ (2004) 3 Journal of Personal Injury Law 171 at 172Google Scholar).
2. Australia was the first country to introduce mandatory helmets for pedal cyclists in 1990. It was followed shortly thereafter by New Zealand. For a survey of the laws in different jurisdictions and of studies of their effectiveness, see the website available at http://www.dft.gov.uk/pgr/roadsafety/research/rsrr/theme1/bicyclehelmetsreviewofeffect4726?page=9.
3. Road Traffic Act 1988, s 17 and Motor Cycles, (Protective Helmets) Regulations 1998, SI 1998/1807.
4. Regelment Verkeersregels en Verkeerstekens 1990, art 60.
5. Under Building Act 1984, s 1(1A) and Building Regulations 2000, SI 2000/2531, Part P.
6. Bouwbesluit, incorporating standardisation norm NEN 1010.
7. HR July 2003, NJ 2005, 103.
8. Sunstein, CR and Thaler, RH ‘Libertarian paternalism is not an oxymoron’ (2003) 70 University of Chicago Law Review 1159 CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Dworkin, G ‘Moral paternalism’ (2005) 24 Law and Philosophy 305.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
9. Eg Pope, TM Balancing public health against individual liberty: the ethics of smoking regulations’ (1999) 61 University of Pittsburgh Law Review 419.Google Scholar
10. Thaler, RH and Sunstein, CR Nudge: Improving Decisions About Health, Wealth, and Happiness (New Haven: Yale University Press, 2008).Google Scholar
11. Froom v Butcher[1976] QB 286. In the recent case of Smith v Finch[2009] EWHC 53 (QB), [2009] All ER (D) 158 (Jan), Griffiths Williams J decided that, in principle, the failure of a pedal cyclist to wear a helmet could give rise to a reduction of damages on this ground if there is strong evidence that wearing the helmet would have prevented or mitigated the injury received. See also Fulbrook, above n 1, who, however, argues that in the large majority of cases such evidence is unlikely.
12. There is a useful survey in Sunstein, CR (ed) Behavioral Law and Economics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
13. Particularly influential have been Kennedy, D ‘Distributive and paternalist motives in contract and tort law’ (1982) 41 Harvard Law Review 563 Google Scholar; Kronman, A ‘Paternalism and the law of contracts’ (1983) 92 Yale Law Journal 763 CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Zamir, E ‘The efficiency of paternalism’ (1998) 84 Virginia Law Review 229 CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Sunstein and Thaler, above n 8; Camerer, C et al ‘Behavioral economics and the case for asymmetric paternalism’ (2003) 151 University of Pennsylvania Law Review 1211 CrossRefGoogle Scholar; Dworkin, above n 8; Glaeser, EL ‘Paternalism and psychology’ (2006) 73 University of Chicago Law Review 133 Google Scholar; Klick, J and Gh Mitchell ‘Government regulation of irrationality: moral and cognitive hazards’ (2006) 90 Minnesota Law Review 1620 Google Scholar; Whitman, DG and Mj Rizzo ‘Paternalism slopes’ (2007) 2 NYU Journal of Law and Liberty 411 Google Scholar; Hill, C ‘Anti-anti-anti paternalism’ (2003) 2 NYU Journal of Law and Liberty 444.Google Scholar
14. ‘Paul Burrows has been a notable exception. See, eg, Analysing legal paternalism’ (1995) 15 International Review of Law & Economics 489.
15. Eg ‘The Government's drugs strategy is under review and we might hear more about that later this month. The worry is that that might culminate in the adoption of a paternalistic “we know best” approach that disempowers local people, communities, service providers and commissioners’: Mr D Burrows, MP, HC Deb, col 1548, 11 July 2007.
16. Ogus, A Regulation: Legal Form and Economic Theory (Oxford: Hart Publishing, 2004), pp 35–38.Google Scholar
17. Ibid, pp 38–41.
18. Lacey, MJ and Haakonssen, K A Culture of Rights: The Bill of Rights in Politics, Philosophy and Law 1791 and 1991 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992).Google Scholar
19. Ogus, A Comparing regulatory systems’ in Parker, D and Saal, D (eds) International Handbook on Privatisation (Cheltenham: Edward Elgar, 2003) ch 23.Google Scholar
20. Myerson, J and Green, L Discounting of delayed rewards: models of individual choice’ (1994) 64 Journal of Experimental Analysis of Behavior 263.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
21. Kuran, T and Sunstein, CR Availability cascades and risk regulation’ (1999) 51 Stanford Law Review 683.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
22. Whitman and Rizzo, above n 13, at 440–441.
23. JS Mill On Liberty (London: Longmans, 1890) p 60.
24. Eg Nozick, R Anarchy, State and Utopia (New York: Basic Books, 1974) p 34.Google Scholar
25. Kleinig, J Paternalism (Manchester: Manchester University Press, 1983) pp 55–67.Google Scholar
26. Thaler and Sunstein, above n 10, pp 44–49. There is some empirical evidence which suggests that cigarette taxes, on this basis, make people happier: Gruber, JH and Mullainathan, S Do cigarette taxes make smokers happier?’ (2005) 5(1) Advances in Economic Analysis & Policy, art 4.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
27. Dworkin, G Paternalism: second thoughts’ in Sartorius, R (ed) Paternalism (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1983) p 102.Google ScholarPubMed
28. Glaeser, above n 13; Whitman and Rizzo, above n 13.
29. Ogus, A ‘Regulatory paternalism: when is it justified?’ in Hopt, KJ et al (eds) Corporate Governance in Context: Corporations, States, and Market in Europe, Japan and the United States (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2005) pp 303–320.Google Scholar
30. Camerer et al, above n 13, at 1214–1218. For consideration of different points along the spectrum, see Valdes, EG On justifying legal paternalism’ (1990) 3 Ratio Juris 173 at 180.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
31. Camerer et al, above n 13.
32. Sunstein and Thaler, above n 8; see also Thaler and Sunstein, above n 10, pp 4–6.
33. Hill, above n 13.
34. Glaeser, above n 13; Whitman and Rizzo, above n 13; Edwards, MA The Ftc and new paternalism’ (2008) 60 Administrative Law Review 323.Google Scholar
35. The following paragraphs draw on, but are significantly different from, Zamir, above n 13.
36. Fulbrook, above n 1, at 172.
37. Of those involved in a road accident in the Netherlands, snorfiets riders are (unsurprisingly) more likely (27%) than motor cyclists (13%) to have a head injury (Dutch Institute for Road Safety Research Fact sheet, available at http://www.swov.nl/rapport/Factsheets/UK/FS_Helmets.pdf), but by itself that does not take us far in assessing the difference in the risk of a head injury. For Spain, see Lardelli-Claret, P et al Position on the moped, risk of head injury and helmet use: an example of confounding effect’ (2003) 32 International Journal of Epidemiology 162.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
38. The status quo ante is important. The situation may be different in the UK simply because moped riders are already accustomed to wearing helmets. So, the opposite effect might occur in relation to alcohol and tobacco consumption, those already addicted being less responsive to health warnings than to increases in the price of cigarettes: Ringold, DJ Boomerang effects in response to public health interventions: some unintended consequences in the alcoholic beverage market’ (2002) 25 Journal of Consumer Policy 27.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
39. An American columnist, John Tierney, has suggested that motor cycle riders who do not wish to wear helmets should be required to obtain a special licence for which they would have to take an extra driving course and submit proof of health insurance: ‘Free and Easy Riders’New York Times 17 June 2006, quoted in Thaler and Sunstein, above n 10, p 202; but this would, of course, significantly increase the costs.
40. Coase, R ‘The problem of social cost’ (1960) 3 Journal of Law and Economics 1 CrossRefGoogle Scholar; and see Ogus, A ‘Inglaterra sin pescado y patatas fritas, o qué más deberíamos haber descubierto en el ensayo de Coase sobre costos sociales’ (‘England without fish-and-chips, or what more should we have discovered in Coase's social cost paper?’) (2002) 3 Revista Argentina de Teoría Jurídica.Google Scholar