Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-fscjk Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-24T01:33:28.120Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

An Essay on Surrogacy and Feminist Thought

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  28 April 2021

Extract

Surrogacy is not an easy issue for feminists. On one hand, it raises concerns about exploitation; one is faced with images of poor women being enlisted to produce babies for wealthy men and their wives, either because of fertility problems or because pregnancy is simply too inconvenient for those women who can afford to hire someone to do it for them. On the other hand, there is the specter of the state passing laws, once again, that tell women what they can and cannot do with their bodies. If we believe, as many of us do, that the state has no right to prohibit a woman from selling the sexual use of her body, doesn't the also have the right to sell the reproductive use? And if many of us, doctors, lawyers, law professors, have been willing to employ other women, less privileged women, to take care of our children after they are born, what is so different in moving the date back a bit and hiring them to carry our children before birth as well?

Assuming that surrogacy is not legally prohibited, does that mean that surrogacy contracts must be enforced? If we find something abhorrent in the idea of babies being taken from their mothers arms because, after all, a contract is a contract, we might argue that the contracts can be legal but unenforceable.

Type
Women's Autonomy
Copyright
Copyright © American Society of Law, Medicine and Ethics 1988

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

See, e.g., Hubbard, , “A Birthmother Is a Birthmother Is a …,” Sojourner: The Women's Forum, 71 (Sept. 1987); Pollitt, , “The Strange Case of Baby M,” The Nation (May 23, 1987); Levine, , “Motherhood Is Powerless,” Village Voice (April 14, 1987): 15.Google Scholar
In the Matter of Baby M, 217 N.J. Super. 313 (1987), rev'd in part, —A.2d—, 1988 WL 6251 (N.J.).Google Scholar
Keane, N. Breo, D., The Surrogate Mother (1981), 33.Google Scholar
In the Matter of Baby M, —A.2d—, 1988 WL 6251 (N.J.), overruling in part 217 N.J. Super. 313 (1987).Google Scholar
See, e.g., Ky. Rev. Stat. §199.590(2) (Baldwin 1982); Mich. Comp. Laws Ann. §710.69 (Supp. 1974).Google Scholar
See, e.g., Mississippi University for Women v. Hogan, 458 U.S. 718 (1982) (striking down a state statute that excluded men from enrolling in a state-supported nursing school); Orr v. Orr, 440 U.S. 268 (1979) (holding unconstitutional a state law that imposed alimony obligations on men but not women); and Craig v. Boren, 429 U.S. 190 (1976) (striking down a state law that set a lower drinking age for females than males). But see, Rostker v. Goldberg, 453 U.S. 57 (1981) (upholding the military registration of males but not females) and Michael M. v. Superior Court, 450 U.S. 464 (1981) (upholding California's statutory rape law, which made it a crime for men to have sexual intercourse with an underage woman but did not impose a similar penalty on women).Google Scholar
Both the Thirteenth Amendment prohibition on slavery and, by implication, on the sale of persons as chattels, and the Fourteenth Amendment protection of liberty are implicated by these concerns.Google Scholar
See, e.g., Coleman, , “Surrogate Motherhood: Analysis of the Problems and Suggestions for Solutions,” Tennessee Law Review, 50 (1982): 71, 109–10; Black, , “Legal Problems of Surrogate Motherhood,” New England Law Review, 16 (1981): 373, 381–83.Google Scholar
See Radin, , “Market-Inalienability,” Harvard Law Review, 100: 1849, 1925–30.Google Scholar
See, Akron v. Akron Center for Reproductive Health, 462 U.S. 416 (1983) (striking down restrictions on availability of abortion); Roe v. Wade, 410 U.S. 113 (1973) (holding that women have a privacy right that encompasses the abortion decision); Griswold v. Connecticut, 381 U.S. 479 (1965) (striking down state laws criminalizing the use of contraceptives).Google Scholar
See, Skinner v. Oklahoma, 316 U.S. 535 (1942) (holding invalid a state law providing for compulsory sterilization of criminals).Google Scholar
See, Planned Parenthood Association of Kansas City v. Ashcroft, 462 U.S. 476 (1983) (upholding requirement of a second physician in post-viability abortions and a pathologist's report for all abortions, while striking down a requitement that all abortions after twelve weeks be performed in a hospital); Roe v. Wade, 410 U.S. 113 (1973) (holding that the right to abortion was not unqualified and the state's interest increased in each trimester of the pregnancy).Google Scholar
California permits the sale of organs but prohibits brokering. Cal. Penal Code §367f(e) (West 1986).Google Scholar
Law, “Rethinking Sex and the Constitution,” University of Pennsylvania Law Review, 132 (1984): 955.Google Scholar
Id.: 963–66.Google Scholar
Id.: 966–68. As will be discussed below, Catharine MacKinnon's approach to feminist jurisprudence comes closest to what Prof. Law calls the respect-for-difference theory.Google Scholar
Id.: 1016–17.Google Scholar
See, e.g., The contract in the Baby M case, In the Matter of Baby M, —A.2d—, 1988 WL 6251 (N.J.) Appendix A.Google Scholar
See, e.g., Akron v. Akron Center for Reproductive Health, 462 U.S. 416 (1983); Roe v. Wade, 410 U.S. 113 (1973).Google Scholar
Planned Parenthood of Missouri v. Danforth, 428 U.S. 52 (1976) (striking down state requirement for spousal consent).Google Scholar
Radin, , supra note 9, at 1934.Google Scholar
See “Rumpelstiltskin Revisited: The Inalienable Rights of Surrogate Mothers,” Harvard Law Review, 99 (1986): 1936, 1942–46.Google Scholar
See, e.g., Williams, , “Equality's Riddle: Pregnancy and the Equal Treatment/Special Treatment Debate,” N.Y.U. Review of Law and Social Change, 13 (1984–85): 325 (hereinafter cited as Williams, , “Equality's Riddle”); Williams, , “The Equality Crisis: Some Reflections on Culture, Courts and Feminism,” Women's Rights Law Reporter, 7 (1982): 175 (hereinafter cited as Williams, , “The Equality Crisis”); Taub, , Book Review, Columbia Law Review, 80 (1980): 1686.Google Scholar
Williams, , “The Equality Crisis,” supra note 23, at 196.Google Scholar
See “Rumpelstiltskin Revisited,” supra note 22, for a discussion of alienability and waivability of rights.Google Scholar
See, e.g., Cal. Civil Code §7005 (b) (West 1987).Google Scholar
See, e.g., Colker, , “Anti-Subordination Above All: Sex, Race and Equal Protection,” N.Y.U. Law Review, 61 (1986): 1003; Scales, , “The Emergence of Feminist Jurisprudence: An Essay,” Yale Law Journal, 95 (1986): 1373; MacKinnon, C., Sexual Harassment of Working Women: A Case of Sex Discrimination (1979).Google Scholar
MacKinnon, C., supra note 27, at 4.Google Scholar
Colker, , supra note 27.Google Scholar
The test in fact reminds me of the only question my grandmother ever asked about world events. Whether people were talking about the election of the president of the United States, the results of the World Series, or the recognition of a new country by the United Nations, my grandmother wanted to know, “Will it be good for the Jews?”Google Scholar
208 U.S. 412 (1908).Google Scholar
See, e.g., Lochner v. N.Y., 198 U.S. 45 (1905).Google Scholar
29 USC 201–19 amnd. 1977.Google Scholar
See Klaff, , “The Tender Years Doctrine: A Defense,” California Law Review, 70 (1982): 335.Google Scholar
Hubbard, , supra note 1.Google Scholar
California Fed. Savings & Loan v. Guerra, 107 S.Ct. 683 (1987).Google Scholar
See Williams, , “Equality's Riddle,” supra note 23.Google Scholar
417 U.S. 484 (1974) (holding that the equal protection clause does not require employers to provide disability coverage for pregnancy when they choose to cover other disabilities).Google Scholar
429 U.S. 125 (1976) (holding that Title VII does not prohibit the exclusion of pregnancy coverage from employee disability plans).Google Scholar
Williams, , “Equality's Riddle,” supra note 23, at 352.Google Scholar
See Colker, supra note 27, at 1007–8: “From an anti-subordination perspective, both facially differentiating and facially neutral policies are invidious only if they perpetuate racial or sexual hierarchy.”Google Scholar
MacKinnon, C., supra note 27, at 117.Google Scholar
Klaff, supra note 34, at 337.Google Scholar
Id.: 337–39. 45. Id.: 340–41.Google Scholar
Mich. Stat. Ann. §25.312(3) (Callaghan 1987).Google Scholar
See, e.g., Garska v. McCoy, 278 S.E.2d 357 (W.Va., 1981).Google Scholar
See, e.g., Surrogate Parenting Assocs. v. Kentucky ex rel Armstrong, 707 S.W.2d 209, 213 (Ky. 1986), stating that if a surrogate mother decided to keep her child, “[s]he would be in the same position vis-a-vis the child and the biological father as any other mother with a child born out of wedlock.”Google Scholar
405 U.S. 645 (1972).Google Scholar
434 U.S. 246 (1978).Google Scholar
441 U.S. 380 (1979).Google Scholar
463 U.S. 248 (1983).Google Scholar
463 U.S. 248, 269 (1983).Google Scholar
463 U.S. 248, 262 (1983).Google Scholar
In the Matter of Baby M, —A.2d—, 1988 WL 6251, at 9 (N.J.).Google Scholar
Williams, , “The Equality Crisis,” supra note 23.Google Scholar