Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-tf8b9 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-25T22:32:14.287Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Critical Empiricism

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  27 December 2018

Abstract

Image of the first page of this content. For PDF version, please use the ‘Save PDF’ preceeding this image.'
Type
Review Symposium Comment
Copyright
Copyright © American Bar Foundation, 1989 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 For a fuller description of what I have elsewhere called the problem of conceptualism, see Whitford, , “Lowered Horizons: Implementation Research in a Post-CLS World,” 1966 Wis. L. Rev. 755, 767–72. The argument I develop later to justify the utility of observation is a refinement of an argument first stated in that earlier article. Id. at 769.Google Scholar

2 These capacities are much emphasized by Coombe in an essay in this issue and are the sources of what she there calls subjectivity.Google Scholar

3 A graphic, and tragic, recent example of this common understanding is the official explanation given for the shooting down of an Iranian passenger airliner by an American warship in the Persian Gulf. That explanation attributed the tragedy to a misreading of images on a radar screen by American servicemen in battle for the first time and biased by the emotions of that circumstance to interpret the images as suggesting an attack on their ship that was in fact not occurring.Google Scholar

4 Though never with quite the specificity stated in the text, there are critiques of the Law & Society movement by other Critical Legal Scholars that come close to questioning the ability of empirical research to teach anything not learnable in other ways. See Kelman, , Trashing,” 36 Stan. L. Rev. 293 (1984); White, , “From Realism to Critical Studies: A Truncated Intellectual History.” 40 Sw. L. J. 819 (1986)CrossRefGoogle Scholar

5 Trubek and Esser, at note 77, very specifically deny any rejection of what they call” investigatory practices,” which I presume includes observation. Their definition of” empiricism,” text at note 84, seems to contemplate that what they call empirical research need not include observation, however.Google Scholar

6 e. g., Goetz, & Scott, , “Principles of Relational Contracts,” 67 Va. L Rev. 1089 (1981)CrossRefGoogle Scholar

7 Sometimes learning is said to be transformative only if the learning results in discarding whole world views, or ideologies, in favor of others. But I have in mind as “transformative” even little insights as long they are not logically compelled from preexisting knowledge. The second part of this comment discusses whether little insights can qualify as” critical empiricism.”Google Scholar

8 Archimedes' principle is that an object submerged in water displaces its volume regardless of the object's weight. I was told in my high school physics class that Archimedes arrived at the insight while in the bathtub, whereupon he jumped out, unclothed, and ran into the street shouting” Eureka, I have it.”Google Scholar

9 Macaulay, , “Non-contractual Relations in Business: A Preliminary Study,” 28 Am. Soc. Rev. 55 (1963)CrossRefGoogle Scholar

10 Whitford, 1986 Wis. L. Rev. at 776–79 (cited in note 1)Google Scholar

11 See Sarat, & Silbey, , “The Pull of the Policy Audience,” 10 Law & Policy 97 (1988)CrossRefGoogle Scholar

12 See Kennedy, 58 S. Cal. L. Rev. 251 (1985)Google Scholar

13 This point is discussed extensively by Trubek and Esser and is the basis on which they direct their strongest criticism at the work of the Amherst group. On the subjectivity of causation, see Kelman, , “The Necessary Myth of Objective Causation Judgments in Liberal Political Theory,” 63 Chi. -Kent L. Rev. 579 (1987).Google Scholar

14 Sarat & Silbey, 10 Law & Policy Google Scholar

15 I reject the view, associated with some strains of the Marxist left, that by legitimating the existing order, the welfare state reforms have delayed the revolution that represents the only true hope for progressive change. I agree that the welfare state reforms have tended to legitimate the existing order, but I am not so confident that revolution, rather than a successful repression and further subordination of disadvantaged groups, would have been the consequence of a failure to adopt them. Nor is revolution always a more desirable alternative than incremental reform. Witness (insert whatever revolutionary society particularly appalls you-e. g., Iran)Google Scholar

16 Joel Handler's research on the American welfare system and Herman Goldstein's work on the American police seem to me examples of politically correct implementation research. Both scholars are intensely empirical, engaging in extensive observation. They have concentrated on studying and promoting successful reform experiments, and I suspect their work has helped these experiments to survive and perhaps even to expand. e. g., J. Handler, The Discretionary Decision (1986); H. Goldstein, Reshaping the Police Function: The Problem-oriented Approach (forthcoming, 1989).Google Scholar