Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-t5tsf Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-19T10:19:26.009Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Kant's Justification of the Death Penalty Reconsidered

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  03 June 2011

Benjamin S. Yost
Affiliation:
Providence College, Providence, RI

Extract

It is hard to know what to think about Kant's ‘passionate sermons’ on capital punishment. Kant clearly feels that it is one of the most important punishments in the state's arsenal. But his vehement insistence on the necessity of execution strikes many readers as philosophically suspect. Critics argue that Kant's embrace of the death penalty is incompatible with, or at least not required by, the fundamental tenets of his moral and legal philosophy (Schwarzschild 1985; Merle 2000; Potter 2002; Hill 2003). These arguments typically employ one of two strategies. The first is to deny that execution is required by retribution in even a prima facie sense; arguments along this line typically question the coherence of Kant's doctrine of the ius talionis (Sarver 1997). The second is to show that there are inviolable moral principles that render the death penalty illegitimate; this criticism typically appeals to the value of human dignity or the right to life (Radin 1980; Pugsley 1981; Schwarzschild 1985; Merle 2000; Potter 2002). There is a third strategy that could be used to criticize Kant, although it is not aimed at him specifcally. This strategy invokes legal principles of fairness or due process. It asserts that, regardless of capital punishment's moral appropriateness or legitimacy, capital punishment is unjust due to the fallibility of legal actors and institutions (Nathanson 2001). Someone adopting the third strategy might claim that, while Kant's justifcation may be acceptable in principle, it fails to justify the death penalty in the world we live in.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © Kantian Review 2010

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Baldus, D., Pulaski, C. and Woodworth, G.. (1983) ‘Comparative review of death sentences: an empirical study of the Georgia experience’, Journal of Criminal Law and Criminology, 74: 661753.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Beccaria, C. (1963) On Crimes and Punishments (New York: Macmillan).Google Scholar
Byrd, B. S. (1989) ‘Kant's theory of punishment: deterrence in its threat, retribution in its execution’, Law and Philosophy, 8(2): 151200.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Clark, M. (2004) ‘A non-retributive Kantian approach to punishment’, Ratio, 17(1): 1227.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Finkelstein, C. (2002) ‘Death and retribution’, Criminal Justice Ethics, 21(2): 1221.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fleischacker, S. (1988) ‘Kant's theory of punishment’, Kant Studien, 79: 434–49.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hill, T. E. (1997) ‘Kant on punishment: a coherent mix of deterrence and retribution?’, Jahrbuch fuer Recht und Ethik, 5: 291314.Google Scholar
Hill, T. E. (2003) ‘Treating criminals as ends in themselves’, Jahrbuch fuer Recht und Ethik, 11: 1736.Google Scholar
Höffe, O. (2002) Categorical Principles of Law: A Counterpoint to Modernity (University Park, PA: The Pennsylvania State University Press).Google Scholar
Holtman, S. W. (1997) ‘Toward social reform: Kant's penal theory reinterpreted’, Utilitas, 9: 3–2.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Korsgaard, C. M. (1996) Creating the Kingdom of Ends (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Merle, J. C. (2000) ‘A Kantian critique of Kant's theory of punishment’, Law and Philosophy, 19(3): 311–38.Google Scholar
Murphy, J. G. (1987) ‘Does Kant have a theory of punishment?’, Columbia Law Review, 87(3): 509–32.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nathanson, S. (2001) An Eye for an Eye: The Immorality of Punishing by Death (Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefeld).Google Scholar
Potter, N. T. (2002) ‘Kant and capital punishment today’, Journal of Value Inquiry, 36(2–2): 267282.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pugsley, R. (1981) ‘A retributivist argument against capital punishment’, Hofstra Law Review, 9: 1501–23.Google Scholar
Radin, M. J. (1980) ‘Cruel punishment and respect for persons: super due process for death’, Southern California Law Review, 53: 1143–85.Google Scholar
Sarver, V. T. (1997) ‘Kant's purported social contract and the death penalty’, Journal of Value Inquiry, 31(4): 455–72.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Scheid, D. E. (1983) ‘Kant's retributivism’, Ethics, 93: 262–82.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schwarzschild, S. S. (1985) ‘Kantianism on the death penalty (and related social problems)’, Archiv fuer Rechts- und Sozialphilosophie, 71: 343–71.Google Scholar
Shafer-Landau, R. (2000) ‘Retributivism and desert’, Pacifc Philosophical Quarterly, 81(2): 189214.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shell, S. M. (1997) ‘Kant on punishment’, Kantian Review, 1: 115–35.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sorell, T. (1988) Moral Theory and Capital Punishment (Oxford, UK: Blackwell).Google Scholar
Sussman, D. (2008) ‘Shame and punishment in Kant's Doctrine of Right’, Philosophical Quarterly, 58(231): 299317.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Uleman, J. K. (2004) ‘External freedom in Kant's Rechtslehre: political, metaphysical’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 68(3): 578601.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Yost, B. S. (2007) ‘Rule of law abolitionism’, Studies in Law, Politics and Society, 42: 5389.CrossRefGoogle Scholar