Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-8ctnn Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-23T01:48:34.209Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Kant’s Causal Power Argument Against Empirical Affection

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  31 January 2017

Jonas Jervell Indregard*
Affiliation:
Sun Yat-Sen University

Abstract

A well-known trilemma faces the interpretation of Kant’s theory of affection, namely whether the objects that affect us are empirical, noumenal or both. I argue that, according to Kant, the things that affect us and cause representations in us are not empirical objects. I articulate what I call the Causal Power Argument, according to which empirical objects cannot affect us because they do not have the right kind of power to cause representations. All the causal powers that empirical objects have are moving powers, and such powers can only have spatial effects. According to Kant, however, the representations that arise in us as a result of the affection of our sensibility are non-spatial. I show that this argument is put forward by Kant in a number of passages, and figures as a decisive reason for rejecting empirical affection and instead endorsing affection by the things in themselves.

Type
Articles
Copyright
© Kantian Review 2017 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Adickes, Erich (1929) Kants Lehre von der doppelten Affektion unseres Ich als Schlüssel zu seiner Erkenntnistheorie. Tübingen: Verlag von J. C. B. Mohr.Google Scholar
Allais, Lucy (2004) ‘Kant’s One World: Interpreting “Transcendental Idealism”’. British Journal for the History of Philosophy, 12/4, 655684.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Allison, Henry E. (1996) Idealism and Freedom. Essays on Kant’s Theoretical and Practical Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Allison, Henry E. (2004) Kant’s Transcendental Idealism. An Interpretation and Defense. Revised and enlarged edition. New Haven and London: Yale University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ameriks, Karl (2000) Kant’s Theory of Mind. New edition. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ameriks, Karl (2011) ‘Kant’s Idealism on a Moderate Interpretation’. In Dennis Schulting and Jacco Verburgt (eds), Kant’s Idealism: New Interpretations of a Controversial Doctrine. (Dordrecht and London: Springer), pp. 2953.Google Scholar
Aquila, Richard (1982) ‘Is Sensation the Matter of Appearance?’ In Moltke S. Gram (ed.), Interpreting Kant (Iowa City, IA: University of Iowa Press), pp. 1119.Google Scholar
Baumgarten, Alexander (2013) Metaphysics: A Critical Translation with Kant’s Elucidations, Selected Notes, and Related Materials. Trans. and ed. Courtney D. Fugate and John Hymers. London: Bloomsbury.Google Scholar
de Boer, Karin (2014) ‘Kant’s Multi-Layered Conception of Things in Themselves, Transcendental Objects, and Monads’. Kant-Studien, 105/2, 221260.Google Scholar
Descartes, René (1984–91). The Philosophical Writings of Descartes, 3 vols. Tr. John Cottingham, Robert Stoothoff, Dugald Murdoch and Anthony Kenny. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Falkenstein, Lorne (1990) ‘Kant’s Account of Sensation’. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 20/1, 6388.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Falkenstein, Lorne (1995) Kant’s Intuitionism: A Commentary on the Transcendental Aesthetic . Toronto: University of Toronto Press.Google Scholar
Gram, Moltke S. (1985) The Transcendental Turn. Gainesville, FL: University of Florida Press.Google Scholar
Hall, Bryan (2010) ‘Appearances and the Problem of Affection in Kant’. Kantian Review, 14/2, 3866.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hennig, Boris (2011) ‘Kants Modell kausaler Verhältnisse: Zu Watkins’ Kant and the Metaphysics of Causality ’. Kant-Studien, 102/3, 367384.Google Scholar
Henschen, Tobias (2014) ‘Kant on Causal Laws and Powers’. Studies of History and Philosophy of Science, 48, 2029.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Hogan, Desmond (2009) ‘Noumenal Affection’. Philosophical Review, 118/4, 501532.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kalter, Alfons (1975) Kants vierter Paralogismus. Meisenheim/Glan: Anton Hain.Google Scholar
Kant, Immanuel (1900– ) Kants gesammelte Schriften. Ed. Königlich Preussischen Akademie der Wissenschaften. Berlin: Walter de Gruyter.Google Scholar
Kant, Immanuel (1987) ‘Eine neu aufgefundene Reflexion Kants “Vom inneren Sinne” (Loses Blatt Leningrad 1)’. Ed. Reinhard Brandt. Kant-Forschungen, 1, 130.Google Scholar
Kant, Immanuel (1992– ) The Cambridge Edition of the Works of Immanuel Kant. Ed. Paul Guyer and Allen W. Wood. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Kitcher, Patricia (2011) Kant’s Thinker. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Langsam, Harold (1994) ‘Kant, Hume, and Our Ordinary Concept of Causation’. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 54/3, 625647.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Langton, Rae (1998) Kantian Humility: Our Ignorance of Things in Themselves. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Nitzan, Lior (2010) ‘The Thought of an Object and the Object of Thought: A Critique of Henry E. Allison’s “Two Aspect” View’. Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie, 92/2, 176198.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Piché, Claude (2004) ‘Kant and the Problem of Affection’. Symposium, 8/2, 275297.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pollok, Konstantin (2006) ‘Kant’s Critical Concepts of Motion’. Journal of the History of Philosophy, 44/4, 559575.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Powell, C. Thomas (1988) ‘Kant’s Fourth Paralogism’. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 48/3, 389414.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Robinson, Hoke (1994) ‘Two Perspectives on Kant’s Appearances and Things in Themselves’. Journal of the History of Philosophy, 32/3, 411441.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sellars, Wilfrid (1967) ‘Some Remarks on Kant’s Theory of Experience’. Journal of Philosophy, 64/20, 633647.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stang, Nicholas (2015) ‘Who’s Afraid of Double Affection?Philosophers’ Imprint, 15/18, 128.Google Scholar
Vaihinger, Hans (1881–92) Commentar zu Kants Kritik der reinen Vernunft. 2 vols. Stuttgart: W. Spemann.Google Scholar
Watkins, Eric (1995) ‘Kant’s Theory of Physical Influx’. Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie, 77/3, 285324.Google Scholar
Watkins, Eric (2004) ‘Kant’s Model of Causality: Causal Powers, Laws, and Kant’s Reply to Hume’. Journal of the History of Philosophy, 42/4, 449488.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Watkins, Eric (2005) Kant and the Metaphysics of Causality. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Watkins, Eric (2014) ‘Efficient Causation in Kant’. In Tad M. Schmaltz (ed.), Efficient Causation: A History (Oxford: Oxford University Press), pp. 258282.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Westphal, Kenneth (2004) Kant’s Transcendental Proof of Realism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar