Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-g8jcs Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-25T17:15:36.007Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Kantians and Cosmopolitanism: O'Neill and Cosmopolitan Universalism

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  27 September 2011

Peter Sutch
Affiliation:
Cardiff University, Wales

Extract

The history of what we now term international relations theory is as rich and as complex as any area in the history of political thought. Yet in the last few decades one particular type of political philosophy has come to be almost unambiguously associated with liberal international relations theory. The dominance of Kantian cosmopolitanism in contemporary liberal international relations theory is quite remarkable. Its position is challenged, within liberalism, only by the utilitarian cosmopolitanism of thinkers such as Peter Singer and, from outside the liberal tradition, by communitarians such as Michael Walzer or Alasdair MacIntyre. At least, this is how the debate is portrayed in the current literature. In this article I want to suggest that the biggest challenge to Kantian cosmopolitanism comes from within the neo-Kantian tradition.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © Kantian Review 2000

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Notes

1 For an overview of this complexity see Boucher, D., Political Theories of International Relations: From Thucydides to the Present (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1988).Google Scholar

2 O'Neill, O., Towards Justice and Virtue: A Constructive Account of Practical Reasoning (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996)CrossRefGoogle Scholar: hereafter TJV.

3 See, for example, Jones, C., Global Justice: Defending Cosmopolitanism (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999), pp. 228–9Google Scholar; Pogge, T., ‘Cosmopolitanism and sovereignty’, Ethics, 103 (1992), pp. 4950Google Scholar, Beitz, C., ‘Cosmopolitan liberalism and the states system’, in Brown, C. (ed.), Political Restructuring in Europe: Ethical Perspectives (London: Routledge, 1994), pp. 124–6.Google Scholar

4 For an examination of the relation between Kant's cosmopolitanism and the cosmopolitanism of his contemporaries see Kleingeld, P., ‘Six varieties of cosmopolitanism in late eighteenth century Germany’, Journal of the History of Ideas, 60/3 (July 1999), 505–24.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

5 For an overview of these traditions see (for example) Brown, C., International Relations Theory: New Normative Approaches (Brighton: Harvester-Wheatsheaf, 1992)Google Scholar or Hutchings, K., International Political Theory (London: Sage, 1999).Google Scholar

6 The Moral Law: Kant's Groundwork of the Metaphysic of Morals, tr. Paton, H. J. (London and New York: Routledge, 1999), p. 95.Google Scholar

7 Kant, I., To Perpetual Peace: A Philosophical Sketch, in Perpetual Peace and Other Essays, tr. Humphrey, T. (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1983), pp. 112–18.Google Scholar

8 Brown, C., ‘International theory and international society: the viability of the middle way’, Review of International Studies, 21 (1995), 189.Google Scholar Also Brown, , International Relations Theory, p. 37Google Scholar.

9 Rawls, J., Political Liberalism (New York: Columbia University Press, 1993), p. 100.Google ScholarO'Neill, , TJV, p. 48.Google Scholar

10 Rawls, J., ‘The law of peoples’, in Shute, S. and Hurley, S. (eds), On Human Rights: The Oxford Amnesty Lectures (New York: Basic Books, 1993).Google Scholar

11 Rawls, , Political Liberalism, p. 99Google Scholar, and lecture 3 passim.

12 Ibid., p. 99.

13 Ibid., p. 90.

14 Ibid., p. 98.

15 Rawls, , ‘Law of peoples’, p. 86.Google Scholar

16 Ibid., §12.2.

17 Cf. Rawls, , Political Liberalism, p. 108.Google Scholar

18 Rawls, , ‘Law of peoples’, pp. 46Google Scholar, 50. See also Political Liberalism, lecture 7.

19 Rawls, , The Law of Peoples (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1999), p. 86.Google Scholar

20 O'Neill, , TJV, p. 48.Google Scholar

21 Ibid., p. 46.

22 O'Neill, O., Constructions of Reason: Explorations of Kant's Practical Philosophy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1989), p. x.Google ScholarO'Neill, , TJV, pp. 3, 6.Google Scholar

23 TJV, p. 51.

24 Ibid., p. 47.

25 Ibid., p. 51.

26 Cf. O'Neill, O., ‘Abstraction, idealization and ideology in ethics’, in Evans, J. (ed.), Moral Philosophy and Contemporary Problems, Supplement to Philosophy, 22 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1987).Google Scholar

27 TJV, p. 57.

28 Ibid., p. 74.

29 Ibid., pp. 89–90.

30 Ibid., p. 97.

31 Ibid., p. 101.

32 Ibid., p. 112.

33 Ibid., p. 113. Cf. the political consequences of these assumptions in O'Neill, , ‘Justice and boundaries’, in Brown, C. (ed.), Political Restructuring in Europe: Ethical Perspectives (London: Routledge, 1994).Google Scholar

34 Ibid., p. 85.

35 Mackie, J. L., Ethics: Inventing Right and Wrong (Harmondsworth: Penguin Books, 1977).Google Scholar

36 Ibid., p. 78.

37 Ibid., pp. 97–8.

38 While the phrase ‘plainly false’ is a little strong, the substitution of the phrase ‘highly contestable’ would serve my purposes here.

39 It is interesting to note here that both Rawls and Pogge accept that the third stage of universalization models the preferred liberal view.

40 O'Neill, O., Faces of Hunger: An Essay on Poverty, justice and Development (London: George Allen & Unwin, 1986), p. 144Google Scholar: hereafter FH.

41 TJV, p. 156. See also ‘Ethical reasoning’, p. 714, and FH, p. 144.

42 Rawls, , ‘Law of Peoples’, p. 81.Google Scholar

43 Mackie, , Ethics, p. 239.Google Scholar

44 TJV, p. 172.

45 Ibid., p. 157.

46 See particularly Walzer, M., Thick and Thin: Moral Arguments at Home and Abroad (Notre Dame, and London: University of Notre Dame Press, 1994).Google Scholar

47 My thoughts on Walzer's work are laid out in Sutch, P., ‘Constructing international community’, in Evans, M. (ed.), The Edinburgh Companion to Contemporary Liberalism (Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, 2000)Google Scholar and Sutch, P., Ethics, Justice and International Relations (London: Routledge, 2000)Google Scholar, ch. 7.

48 TJV. p. 110 n. 29.

49 Ibid., ch. 4.4, passim.

50 Ibid., p. 113.

51 Ibid., pp. 157, 172–3.

52 Ibid., p. 174. O'Neill goes on to talk about acting on non-universalizable principles but there is a prior communitarian meaning in this phrase that O'Neill does briefly acknowledge.

53 Ibid., p. 7.

54 See particularly C. Beitz, ‘Cosmopolitan liberalism and the states system’, in Brown (ed.), Political Restructuring and Pogge, T., ‘Cosmopolitanism and sovereignty’, Ethics, 103 (Oct. 1992), 4875.Google Scholar