Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-gb8f7 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-25T09:05:00.221Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Habitual Desire: On Kant’s Concept of Inclination

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 June 2016

Eric Entrican Wilson*
Affiliation:
Georgia State University

Abstract

Tamar Schapiro has offered an important new ‘Kantian’ account of inclination and motivation, one that expands and refines Christine Korsgaard’s view. In this article I argue that Kant’s own view differs significantly from Schapiro’s. Above all, Kant thinks of inclinations as dispositions, not occurrent desires; and he does not believe that they stem directly from a non-rational source, as she argues. Schapiro’s ‘Kantian’ view rests on a much sharper distinction between the rational and non-rational parts of the soul. In the process of explaining these (and other) differences, I argue that Kant’s own view is in some respects philosophically superior to Schapiro’s.

Type
Articles
Copyright
© Kantian Review 2016 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Baxley, Anne Margaret (2003) ‘Autocracy and Autonomy’. Kant Studien, 94(1), 123.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Baxley, Anne Margaret (2010) Kant’s Theory of Virtue: The Value of Autocracy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bratman, Michael (1983) ‘Taking Plans Seriously’. Social Theory and Practice, 9, 271287.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Clarke, Desmond M. (1993) ‘Dormitive Powers and Scholastic Qualities: A Reply to Hutchison’. History of Science, 31, 317327.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Csikszentmihalyi, Mihaly (1990) Flow: The Psychology of Optimal Experience. New York: Harper Collins.Google Scholar
Denis, Lara (2000) ‘Kant’s Cold Sage and the Sublimity of Apathy’. Kantian Review, 4, 4873.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Denis, Lara (ed.) (2010) Kant’s ‘Metaphysics of Morals’: A Critical Guide. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Descartes, René (1985) ‘The Passions of the Soul’. In John Cottingham, Robert Stoothoff and Dugald Murdoch (trs), The Philosophical Writings of Descartes, vol. 1, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Engstrom, Stephen (2002) ‘The Inner Freedom of Virtue’. In M. Timmons (ed.), Kant’s ‘Metaphysics of Morals’: Interpretive Essays (New York: Oxford University Press), 289316.Google Scholar
Engstrom, Stephen (2010) ‘Reason, Desire, and the Will’. In L. Denis (ed.), Kant’s ‘Metaphysics of Morals’: A Critical Guide (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 2850.Google Scholar
Foreman, David (2012) ‘Kant on Moral Freedom and Moral Slavery’. Kantian Review, 17(1), 132.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Frierson, Patrick (2005) ‘Kant’s Empirical Account of Human Action’. Philosopher’s Imprint, 5(7), 134.Google Scholar
Gnassounou, Bruno, and Max, Kistler, (2007) ‘Introduction’. In M. Kistler and B. Gnassounou, Dispositions and Causal Powers (Burlington, VT: Ashgate), 1–40.Google Scholar
Grenberg, Jeanine (2011) ‘Feeling, Desire and Interest in Kant’s Theory of Action’. Kant-Studien, 92(2), 153179.Google Scholar
Guyer, Paul (2005) ‘Theory and Practice of Autonomy’. In Kant’s System of Nature and Freedom. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Guyer, Paul (2010) ‘Moral Feelings in the Metaphysics of Morals’. In L. Denis (ed.), Kant’s ‘Metaphysics of Morals’: A Critical Guide (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 130151.Google Scholar
Guyer, Paul (2013) ‘Progress toward Autonomy’. In O. Sensen (ed.), Kant on Moral Autonomy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 7186.Google Scholar
Hampshire, Stuart (1971) ‘Dispositions’. In Freedom of Mind and Other Essays. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Hampshire, Stuart (1975) Freedom of the Individual. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Höwing, Thomas (2013) ‘Das Verhältnis der Vermögen des Menschlischen Gemüts zu den Sittengesetzen (MS 6:211–214)’. In A. Trampota, O. Sensen and J. Timmermann (eds), Kant’s ‘Tugendlehre’: A Comprehensive Commentary (Berlin: Walter de Gruyter), 2557.Google Scholar
Hutchison, Keith (1991) ‘Dormitive Virtues, Scholastic Qualities, and the New Philosophies’. History of Science, 29, 245278.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
James, Susan (1997) Passion and Action: The Emotions in Seventeenth-Century Philosophy. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Johnston, Mark (1992) ‘How to Speak of the Colors’. Philosophical Studies, 68, 221263.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Korsgaard, Christine (2008) ‘Self-Constitution in the Ethics of Plato and Kant’. In The Constitution of Agency: Essays on Practical Reason and Moral Psychology (New York: Oxford University Press), 100–26.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kant, Immanuel (1900–) Kants gesammelte Schriften. Ed. Königlich-Preußlichen Akademie der Wissenschaften. Berlin: Walter de Gruyter.Google Scholar
Kant, Immanuel (1996) The Metaphysics of Morals. Trans. and ed. Mary Gregor. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kant, Immanuel (1997a) Groundwork for the Metaphysics of Morals. Trans. and ed. Mary Gregor. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Kant, Immanuel (1997b) Critique of Practical Reason. Trans. and ed. Mary Gregor. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kant, Immanuel (1997c) Lectures on Ethics. Trans. Peter Heath. Ed. Peter Heath and J. B. Schneewind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kant, Immanuel (1997d) Lectures on Metaphysics. Trans. Karl Ameriks and Steve Naragon. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kant, Immanuel (1998) Religion within the Boundaries of Mere Reason. Trans. and ed. George di Giovanni and Allen Wood. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kant, Immanuel (2000) Critique of the Power of Judgement. Trans. Paul Guyer and Eric Matthews. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kant, Immanuel (2006) Anthropology from a Pragmatic Point of View. Trans. and ed. Robert Louden. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Louden, Robert B. (2011) ‘Moral Strength: Virtue as a Duty to Oneself’. In Kant’s Human Being. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nagel, Thomas (1970) The Possibility of Altruism. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Newmark, Catherine (2008) Passion – Affekt – Gefühl: Philosophische Theorien der Emotionen zwischen Aristoteles und Kant. Hamburg: Felix Meiner Verlag.Google Scholar
Papish, Laura (2007) ‘The Cultivation of Sensibility in Kant’s Moral Philosophy’. Kantian Review, 12(2), 128146.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ryle, Gilbert (2000) The Concept of Mind. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Schapiro, Tamar (2009) ‘The Nature of Inclination’. Ethics, 119, 229256.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schapiro, Tamar (2011) ‘Foregrounding Desire: A Defense of Kant’s Incorporation Thesis’. Journal of Ethics, 15(3), 147167.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schapiro, Tamar (2012) ‘On the Relation between Wanting and Willing’. Philosophical Issues: A Supplement to Noûs, 22(1), 334350.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schueler, G. F. (1995) Desire: Its Role in Practical Reason and the Explanation of Action. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Taylor, Gabrielle (2006) Deadly Vices. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Watkins, Eric (2005) Kant and the Metaphysics of Causality. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Wilson, Eric Entrican (forthcoming) ‘Self-Legislation and Self-Command in Kant’s Ethics’. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly.Google Scholar
Wood, Allen (1999) Kant’s Ethical Thought. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wuerth, Julian (2011) ‘Moving Beyond Kant’s Account of Agency in the Grounding’. In L. Jost and J. Wuerth (eds), Perfecting Virtue: New Essays on Kantian Ethics and Virtue Ethics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 147163.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wuerth, Julian (2013) ‘Sense and Sensibility in Kant’s Practical Agent: Against the Intellectualism of Korsgaard and Sidgwick’. European Journal of Philosophy, 21(1), 136.CrossRefGoogle Scholar