Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-t7fkt Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-25T20:56:24.091Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The Demand for Systematicity and the Authority of Theoretical Reason in Kant

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  31 January 2017

Sasha Mudd*
Affiliation:
University of Southampton

Abstract

Kant’s notoriously unclear attempt to defend the regulative principle of systematic unity as the supreme principle of theoretical reason in the Appendix to the Transcendental Dialectic has left its status a source of controversy. According to the dominant interpretation, the principle ought to be understood as a methodologically necessary device for extending our understanding of nature. I argue that this reading is flawed. While it may correctly affirm that the principle is normative in character, it wrongly implies that it binds with mere hypothetical necessity. I offer novel grounds for thinking that if reason’s principle is normative, then it binds agents categorically instead.

Type
Articles
Copyright
© Kantian Review 2017 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Abela, P. (2010) ‘The Demands of Systematicity: Rational Judgement and the Structure of Nature’. In Graham Bird (ed.), A Companion to Kant (Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell), pp. 408422.Google Scholar
Allison, H. (2004) Kant’s Transcendental Idealism. New Haven: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Buchdahl, G. (1969) Metaphysics and the Philosophy of Science. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Buchdahl, G. (1992) Kant and the Dynamics of Reason: Essays on the Structure of Kant’s Philosophy. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Gardner, S. (2010) ‘The Primacy of the Practical’. In Graham Bird (ed.), A Companion to Kant (Oxford: Blackwell), pp. 259274.Google Scholar
Grier, M. (2001) Kant’s Doctrine of Transcendental Illusion. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Guyer, P. (1990) ‘Reason and Reflective Judgement: Kant on the Significance of Systematicity’. Nous, 24, 1743.Google Scholar
Guyer, P. (2000) Kant on Freedom, Law and Happiness. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Guyer, P. (2001) ‘From Nature to Morality: Kant’s New Argument in the Critique of Teleological Judgement’. In H. F. Fulda and J. Stolzenberg (eds), Architektonik und System in der Philosophie Kants (Hamburg: Felix MeinerVerlag), pp. 375404.Google Scholar
Guyer, P. (2006) Kant. New York: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
—— Guyer, P. Walker, R. (1990) ‘Kant’s Conception of Empirical Law’. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, supplementary volume 64, 221–58.Google Scholar
Kant, I. (1996) ‘What is Orientation in Thinking?’. Trans A. Wood in A. Wood and G. di Giovanni (eds), Religion and Rational Theology (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), pp. 118.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kant, I. (1998) Critique of Pure Reason , Trans P. Guyer and A. Wood. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Kant, I. (1999) Practical Philosophy. Trans. and ed. M. Gregor. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Kant, I. (2000) Critique of the Power of Judgement. Trans. P. Guyer and E. Mathews. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Kemp Smith, N. (1964) A Commentary to Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.Google Scholar
Kitcher, P. (1986) ‘Protecting the Order of Nature’. In R. Butts (ed.), Kant’s Philosophy of Science (Dordrecht: D. Reidel), pp. 201233.Google Scholar
Kitcher, P. (1994) ‘The Unity of Science and Nature’. In P. Parrini (ed.), Kant and Contemporary Epistemology (Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic), pp. 253272.Google Scholar
Kleingeld, P. (1998) ‘Kant on the Unity of Theoretical and Practical Reason’. Review of Metaphysics, 52, 311339.Google Scholar
McFarland, J. D. (1970) Kant’s Concept of Teleology. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.Google Scholar
Mudd, S. (2016) ‘Rethinking the Priority of Practical Reason in Kant’. European Journal of Philosophy, 24, 78102.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
O’Neill, O. (1989) Constructions of Reason. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
O’Neill, O. (1992) ‘Vindicating Reason’. In P. Guyer (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Kant (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), pp. 280308.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pickering, M. (2011) ‘The Idea of the Systematic Unity of Nature as a Transcendental Illusion’. Kantian Review, 16/3, 429448.Google Scholar
Velkley, R. (1989) Freedom and the End of Reason. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Wartenberg, T. (1992) ‘Reason and the Practice of Science’. In P. Guyer (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Kant (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), pp. 228248.Google Scholar
Willaschek, M. (2010) ‘The Primacy of Practical Reason and the Idea of a Practical Postulate’. In A. Reath and J. Timmermann (eds), Kant’s Critique of Practical Reason: A Critical Guide (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), pp. 168196.Google Scholar