Hostname: page-component-745bb68f8f-b6zl4 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-02-03T18:29:50.220Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Hume’s Scepticism and Kant’s Transcendental Deduction

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  03 February 2025

Paul Tulipana*
Affiliation:
University of California Los Angeles, Los Angeles, CA, USA
Dustin King
Affiliation:
Independent Scholar
*
Corresponding author: Paul Tulipana; Email: [email protected]

Abstract

Kant’s aim in the Transcendental Deduction is to prove that the a priori categories of the understanding necessarily apply to objects of experience. He claims that he will do this simply by explaining how they could so apply. But the idea that a mere explanation of this possibility should provide a defence of the categories’ actual (let alone necessary) applicability is surprising. We argue that it can be understood by attending to the source of the scepticism that the Critique’s Analytic is supposed to overcome: Hume’s inability to explain causal knowledge in the Enquiry.

Type
Article
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2025. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of Kantian Review

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Allais, Lucy (2011) ‘Transcendental idealism and the Transcendental Deduction’. In Schulting, D. and Verburgt, J. (eds.), Kant’s Idealism: New Interpretations of Controversial Doctrine (Dordrecht: Springer), 91107.Google Scholar
Allison, Henry (1983/2004) Kant’s Transcendental Idealism. New Haven: Yale University Press; second edition, 2004.Google Scholar
Allison, Henry (2015) Kant’s Transcendental Deduction. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ameriks, Karl (1978) ‘Kant’s Transcendental Deduction as a regressive argument’. Kant-Studien, 69, 14, 273-87.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ameriks, Karl (1982) ‘Recent work on Kant’s theoretical philosophy’. American Philosophical Quarterly, 19, 124.Google Scholar
Arnold, N. Scott (1983) ‘Hume’s skepticism about inductive inferences’. Journal of the History of Philosophy, 21, 3155.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Baier, Annette C. (1991) A Progress of Sentiments. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Beauchamp, Tom L., and Rosenberg, Alexander (1981) Hume and the Problem of Causation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Bennett, Jonathan (1966) Kant’s Analytic. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Broughton, Janet (1983) ‘Hume’s skepticism about causal inferences’. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 64, 318.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Crepet, William L. (2000) ‘Progress in understanding angiosperm history, success, and relationships: Darwin’s abominably “perplexing phenomenon”’. Proc Natl Acad Sci, 97, 1293912941.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Edgar, Scott (2010) ‘The explanatory structure of the Transcendental Deduction and a cognitive interpretation of the first “Critique”’. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 40, 285314.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Engstrom, Stephen (1994) ‘The Transcendental Deduction and skepticism’. Journal of the History of Philosophy, 32, 359–80.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Flew, Antony (1961) Hume’s Philosophy of Belief. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Friedman, W. E. (2009) ‘The meaning of Darwin’s “abominable mystery”’. American Journal of Botany, 96, 521.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Garrett, Don (1997) Cognition and Commitment in Hume’s Philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goldhaber, Charles (2024) ‘Kant’s offer to the skeptical empiricist’. Journal of the History of Philosophy, 62, 421–47.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Guyer, Paul (1987) Kant and the Claims of Knowledge. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hatfield, Gary (2003) ‘What were Kant’s aims in the Deduction?Philosophical Topics, 31, 12, 165-98.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Henrich, Dieter (1969) ‘The proof-structure of Kant’s Transcendental Deduction’. The Review of Metaphysics, 22, 640–59.Google Scholar
Henrich, Dieter (1976/2004) ‘Identity and objectivity: an inquiry into Kant’s Transcendental Deduction’. In Henrich, D. (ed.), Repr. in his The Unity of Reason (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 2004), 123208.Google Scholar
Henrich, Dieter (1989) ‘Kant’s notion of a deduction and the methodological background of the first Critique ’. In Förster, Eckart (ed.), Kant’s Transcendental Deductions (Stanford: Stanford University Press), 2946.Google Scholar
Kemp Smith, Norman (1941) The Philosophy of David Hume: A Critical Study of Its Origins and Central Doctrines. London: MacMillan.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kitcher, Patricia (2011) Kant’s Thinker. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McCann, Edwin (1985) ‘Skepticism and Kant’s B-Deduction’. History of Philosophy Quarterly, 2, 7189.Google Scholar
Onof, Christian, and Schulting, Dennis (2015) ‘Space as form of intuition and as formal intuition. On the note to B160 in Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason’. Philosophical Review, 124, 158.Google Scholar
Owen, David (1999) Hume’s Reason. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Pereboom, Derk (1995) ‘Self-Understanding in Kant’s Transcendental Deduction’. Synthese, 103, 142.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schulting, Dennis (2012) Kant’s Deduction and Apperception: Explaining the Categories. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.Google Scholar
Strawson, P. F. (1966) The Bounds of Sense: An Essay on Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Stove, D. C. (1973) Probability and Hume’s Inductive Scepticism. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stroud, Barry (1977) Hume. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Wolff, Robert Paul (1963) Kant’s Theory of Mental Activity. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Zangwill, Israel (1895) The Big Bow Mystery. Chicago: Rand, McNally & Co.Google Scholar