Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-94fs2 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-16T15:20:44.826Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The Possibility Bias is not Justified

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  23 September 2024

SAMUEL KIMPTON-NYE*
Affiliation:
KING'S COLLEGE LONDON [email protected]
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Necessity, but not possibility, is typically thought to be rare and suspicion-worthy. This manifests in an asymmetry in the burden of proof incurred by modal claims. In general, claims to the effect that some proposition is impossible/necessary require significant argumentative support and, in general, claims to the effect that some proposition is possible/contingent are thought to be justified freely or by default. Call this the possibility bias. In this article, I argue that the possibility bias is not epistemically justified. We should regard possibility with at least as much suspicion, that is to say as incurring at least as much of an explanatory demand, as necessity. In fact, I suggest that we might even be justified in reversing the burden of proof asymmetry and adopting a necessity bias. This has quite radical implications for philosophical methodology and hence for many first-order philosophical concerns.

Type
Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution and reproduction, provided the original article is properly cited.
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2024. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of The American Philosophical Association

1. Introduction

It is an entrenched part of contemporary philosophical lore that possibilityFootnote 1 is cheap and bountiful whereas necessity is expensive and scarce.Footnote 2 If any propositions are necessary, they must be members of some elite class. Propositions of mathematics and logic may qualify (though some doubt even this, for example, Wittgenstein as interpreted by Dummett (Reference Dummett1959), Putnam (Reference Putnam, Cohen and Wartofsky1969), Mortensen (Reference Mortensen1989), Nozick (Reference Nozick2001)). At the very least, necessity is believed to require explanation, and many recent authors have assumed that any theory that implies the existence of brute necessity is to be rejected on that basis (see Van Cleve 2018 for discussion). Perhaps we have been convinced by Putnam (Reference Putnam1975) and Kripke (Reference Kripke1980) to admit necessities concerning theoretical identities and the constitution and origin of individuals. But the induction of these a posteriori necessities into the mainstream philosophical psyche was hard fought and continues to face stiff opposition (see, e.g., Sidelle Reference Sidelle1989; Chalmers Reference Chalmers1996; Jackson Reference Jackson1998; Chalmers and Jackson Reference Chalmers and Jackson2001; Nozick Reference Nozick2001; Priest Reference Priest2018). Necessity, unlike possibility, is to be viewed with extreme suspicion, or so philosophical orthodoxy would have it.

Sidelle, for example, finds it “hard to believe that there are people who do not find the notion of real necessity either incomprehensible or at least extremely troublesome” (Sidelle Reference Sidelle1989, 85). Similarly, Nozick maintains “that there are no interesting and important metaphysical necessities” (Nozick Reference Nozick2001, 120–21). Merricks suggests “that we ought to assume, for any distinct and contingent states of affairs S and S*, either that S can obtain in some possible world where S* does not obtain or vice versa, unless there is some reason to think otherwise” (Merricks Reference Merricks1998, 117–18). Fine thinks that to deny the possibility of alien properties would be “too outlandish to deserve consideration” (Fine Reference Fine, Gendler and Hawthorne2002). Sider thinks that “it is intuitively plausible that any pattern of occupation of spacetime points is possible” (Sider Reference Sider2005, 189). According to Rosen, “[M]etaphysical possibility is, as it were, the default status for propositions” (Rosen Reference Rosen and MacBride2006, 23). And Wilson has, without endorsing it, drawn attention to this bias in favour of possibility/contingency over necessity: “The general thought, not often articulated, seems to be that contingency is the ‘default’ modal status for a proposition and that the job of a theory of modality is to provide an account of necessity as deviation from this default status” (Wilson Reference Wilson2020, 13).

This orthodox suspicion of necessity and penchant for possibility leads to belief in a stark asymmetry in the burden of proof incurred by modal assertions. Claims to the effect that some proposition is necessary are generally thought to incur significant argumentative cost as evidenced by, for example, the lengths to which Kripke and Putnam had to go to persuade philosophers that it is necessary that water is H2O and that tigers are mammals. On the other hand, philosophers have considered themselves free to assert all manner of possibilities very cheaply, that is, with little to no argumentative support. Very peculiar possibilities indeed are often invoked as unargued for (or very minimally argued for) premises in arguments to surprising conclusions. Examples include Plantinga's (Reference Plantinga1974) argument from the possibility of a perfect being to the actual existence of God, Sider's (Reference Sider1993) argument from the possibility of “gunk” (matter that is infinitely divisible) against mereological nihilism, Chalmers's (Reference Chalmers1996) argument from the possibility of phenomenal “zombies” against physicalism, and Fine's (Reference Fine, Gendler and Hawthorne2002) argument from the possibility of alien properties for the independence of natural and metaphysical modality.

Call this suspicion of necessity, penchant for possibility, and the resulting asymmetry in the burden of proof incurred by assertions of possibility and necessity the possibility bias:

The possibility bias: Necessity, but not possibility, is to be treated with suspicion. In general, asserting that some proposition is impossible/necessary is expensive in the sense that it incurs a heavy burden of proof. In general, asserting that some proposition is merely possible/contingent is cheap in the sense that doing so incurs little to no burden of proof.

One might thus think of the possibility bias as a metaphilosophical norm: when doing philosophy, one ought not to assert that some proposition is necessary without sufficient argumentative support, and one may assert that some proposition is merely possible/contingent with little to no argumentative support.

I take the aforementioned authors to endorse the possibility bias, or something like it. There are, of course, exceptions. Patricia Churchland, for example, objects to the zombie argument: “That someone can imagine the possibility [of zombies] is not evidence for the real possibility” (Reference Churchland1996, 403). The implication is that possibility claims are not sufficiently epistemically justified by citations of what one can imagine; i.e., that real possibilities do not come so cheaply as two-a-penny imaginings. More generally, and particularly since van Inwagen's “Modal Epistemology” (Reference Inwagen1998), philosophers have increasingly raised doubts about the premises of such “possibility arguments”. Furthermore, the possibility bias may not hold sway over all domains of inquiry, mathematics being a case in point: it might be harder to establish the consistency of standard mathematics than it is to establish what follows necessarily from certain axioms. The latter is computationally tractable, but there is no test for consistency that can be implemented by a computer and, as per Gödel's 2nd theorem, mathematics could only “prove” its consistency if it were inconsistent.Footnote 3

To be clear, then, the target of my argument is those philosophers labouring under the possibility bias, which I take to be a significant subset of philosophers as evidenced by the above. (If necessity comes cheaper than consistency, viz. possibility, in mathematics, then I am happy to bracket that domain.) My aim in this article is to argue that belief in the possibility bias, which to recap, says that in general, necessity claims incur a heavier burden of proof than do possibility claims, is not epistemically justified. We've no reason to believe anything that might vindicate this bias such as that, for example, mere possibilities are more plentiful or more frequently encountered than necessities, or that mere possibilities are more ontologically innocent than necessities.

My strategy involves examining some of the most likely ways of justifying the possibility bias and finding them all wanting.Footnote 4 I recognise that even if I am successful here this success will not constitute a closed case because there could be some other route to justification of the bias that I have not discussed. But if there are other justifications, then we should hear them. Indeed, I think the philosophical community is owed such a justification given what's at stake for areas of philosophy that tend to appeal to possibilities in their investigations. Accordingly, this article should be seen as starting a debate about the relative justificatory burdens incurred by our modal assertions and the corresponding metaphilosophical implications.

2. Humean Naturalism

The “[great] denier of necessary connections” (Lewis Reference Lewis1986b, ix) was David Hume. Humean naturalism, which for present purposes I will assume comprises an empiricist epistemology and a physicalist ontology, is an attractive guard against straying into the overly metaphysical, in the pejorative sense of “metaphysical” where one might find books on spirits and astral projection in the “metaphysics” sections of certain bookshops, and promises to keep philosophy appropriately tethered to science. The influence of naturalism so conceived from Hume and Kant, through the Logical Positivists and contemporary philosophers, is hard to overstate. So, it is worth first examining whether naturalism yields a route to justification of the possibility bias.

The point is not to reject Humean naturalism. Rather, I concede that there is something attractive in general about the (what one might call broadly “Humean naturalistic”) constraints imposed on philosophical theorizing by empiricism and physicalism. The aim of this section, then, is to argue that the possibility bias cannot be justified by appeal to this independently attractive approach to philosophy. I will proceed by first showing how two broad claims about modality typically associated with the name “Humean” may justify the bias, before then considering if either of these can really be justified on laudable empiricist/physicalist grounds.

The Humean approach to modality comprises both a negative claim and a positive claim. According to the negative claim, worldly necessity, i.e., necessity for (or necessary connections between) concrete things in the world, as opposed to between our concepts/ideas, is obscure, i.e., mysterious or spooky, or otherwise unrespectable in some sense. According to the positive claim, imaginability entails possibility. Regarding the negative claim, if worldly necessity were indeed obscure, perhaps we would want to say that there is no necessity in the world and, hence, that possibility reigns supreme, which would justify the possibility bias. Regarding the positive claim, imagination is relatively unconstrained, so, if imaginability did entail possibility, possibility would be relatively unconstrained too, which would justify the possibility bias.

The Humean rejection of necessity and accompanying acceptance of possibility has been endorsed widely, particularly by those of a naturalist/empiricist persuasion, such as Ayer:

Like Hume, I divide all genuine propositions into two classes: those which, in his terminology, concern “relations of ideas,” and those which concern “matters of fact.” The former class […] I allow to be necessary and certain only because they are analytic. That is, I maintain that the reason why these propositions cannot be confuted in experience is that they do not make any assertion about the empirical world. (Ayer Reference Ayer1936, 31)

And Quine:

In principle, therefore, I see no higher or more austere necessity than natural necessity; and in natural necessity, or our attributions of it, I see only Hume's regularities. (Quine Reference Quine1966, 76)

But the Humean influence reaches well beyond the austere empiricism of the early-to-mid-20th century to the more indulgent, realist, metaphysics of David Lewis and David Armstrong, each of whom nonetheless thinks of himself as operating within the confines of naturalism. Lewis and Armstrong both endorse a principle of recombination. And Lewis, at least, is explicit that this principle is motivated by “the Humean denial of necessary connections” (Lewis Reference Lewis1986b, 87):

[P]atching together parts of different possible worlds yields another possible world. Roughly speaking, the principle is that anything can coexist with anything else […] Likewise, anything can fail to coexist with anything else (Lewis Reference Lewis1986a, 87–88)

The idea for possibility, then, is that all the combinations of simple particulars, properties and relations […] constitute the possibilities for first-order states of affairs. (Armstrong Reference Armstrong1997, 160)

Clearly, these philosophers are under the influence of the possibility bias. The question, however, is: can the attractive package comprising empiricism and physicalism, justify either the claim that necessity is obscure and possibility reigns supreme or the claim that imaginability entails possibility, and thereby confer justification on the possibility bias?

Consider first the claim that worldly necessity is “obscure and uncertain” and hence that we should not admit its existence.Footnote 5 Why might the Humean naturalist think that worldly necessity is obscure? Answer: because we cannot empirically observe necessity in the world, only constant conjunctions of events. According to the empiricist component of Humean naturalism, all knowledge of the world comes from the senses, but since we can have no sensory experience of necessary connections, we can have no knowledge of such things. We may project the idea of necessary connection from our own minds onto the constant conjunctions that we do observe, but that is not to say that the necessity is really there in the world. The idea that necessary connections should thus be positively banished arguably stems from the physicalist component of Humean naturalism: if necessary connections are not the sorts of things that can be detected by respectable empirical/scientific means, i.e. detected causally, we should not posit them as part of the furniture of the world (that's not to say that this is Hume's view, see, e.g., Strawson (Reference Strawson2015)). Quine sums up this typical interpretation of Hume:

The doctrine that necessity is no more than regularity was expounded by David Hume […]. His, indeed, was the battle cry. “There are no necessary connections in matters of fact.” (Quine Reference Quine1966, 71)

However, the idea that necessity is more obscure than possibility is not justified by naturalistic scruples. We can grant that we have no empirical access to necessary connections in the world and that this motivates skepticism about worldly necessity. But empiricism should make us just as skeptical about real, worldly, mere possibility as it does about necessity. Assume that we in fact observe one billiard ball hitting a second and the second ball moving in a straight line away from the first after the collision. We can no more observe the possibility that the second ball did (e.g.) a loop-the-loop in mid-air after the collision (or any other merely possible post-collision effect), and so acquire knowledge that this really is a possibility, than we can observe a necessary connection between the collision and the second ball's actual movement. The letter of Humean empiricism renders belief in mere possibilities no more justified than belief in necessary connections.

Next consider the claim that what we can imagine is possible.Footnote 6 This is an idea taken up enthusiastically by many contemporary philosophers, as evidenced by the diversity of arguments from possibility above. Sidelle is explicit on this point: “the supposition that what is imaginable is possible is so fundamental to philosophical discussion” (Sidelle Reference Sidelle1989, 87). One might then argue as follows. Imaginability is relatively unconstrained. Imaginability entails possibility, which renders possibility unconstrained, too. Hence, the possibility bias is justified.

But now we can ask: can the claim that imaginability entails possibility be justified on naturalistic grounds? Ayer hints at a positive answer in the above, suggesting that only those propositions that could not possibly be confuted in experience are necessary, and all other propositions that could possibly be confuted in experience are contingent.

How do we know whether a proposition could possibly be confuted in experience and thus whether it is contingent? According to Hume:

The contrary of every matter of fact is still possible; because it can never imply a contradiction, and is conceived by the mind with the same facility and distinctness, as if ever so conformable to reality. (Enquiry 4.3, SBN 26, my emphasis)

The idea being that if the negation of a proposition can be imagined, or conceived (I won't distinguish between these terms), without contradiction, then the negation of that proposition may conform, or is “conformable” to reality, which makes the proposition contingent, i.e., possibly false.

But to merely imagine the negation of a proposition “conforming to reality” is not to have some empirical evidence that it is possibly false. The reasoning here says, for some true proposition, P: “I can imagine P being false because I can imagine a situation in which my experience confutes P” and “if I can imagine P being false in this way, then it is possible that P is false”. None of this says anything about actual empirical evidence telling in favour of a true proposition's being possibly false or a false proposition's being possibly true. For any true proposition, P, that is never actually confuted in experience, we have no empirical grounds for maintaining that P is possibly false, just a purported link between our being able to imagine P being confuted in experience and the possibility that P is false. Empiricism does not justify the claim that imaginability entails possibility.

Perhaps it will be objected that the type of possibility entailed by imaginability is conceptual rather than worldly and that my argument above does not threaten the entailment from imaginability to conceptual possibility. Fine. But this would not justify the possibility bias which I take to apply to real, worldly, possibilities—when philosophers assert that zombies, schmass, or perfect beings are possible they mean that there really is a way the world could be such that these possibilities obtained, not just that they engender no conceptual confusion or inconsistency. If the possibilities were merely conceptual, possibility arguments would not support the realist conclusions of their proponents, such as that the mental and the physical are distinct, that there are distinct varieties of modality or that God exists.

To summarize: We have no more empirical access to mere possibilities than we do to necessary connections and the imaginability-possibility link cannot be justified on empiricist grounds.Footnote 7 So, naturalism (empiricism plus physicalism, for present purposes) tells just as much in favour of skepticism about possibility as it tells in favour of skepticism about necessity. The possibility bias cannot be justified on Humean naturalistic grounds. Importantly, I am willing to grant that naturalism is an independently attractive constraint on philosophizing, so this section isn't best understood as merely a response to the Humean naturalists. The quite general point here is that there is an independently attractive approach to philosophy (empiricism plus physicalism) but this cannot be successfully used (regardless of whether we would call ourselves “Humean” in doing so) in defence of the possibility bias.

2.1. More on Imaginability and Possibility

I'll now defend my assumption that imaginability does not entail real possibility. Recently, Justin Clarke-Doane (Reference Clarke-Doane2019; Reference Clarke-Doane2021) has advanced an ingenious argument against the idea that metaphysical necessity is absolute or otherwise uniquely metaphysically significant. The core of the argument is that the “grounds on which we judge that paradigmatic metaphysical possibilities are possible in some real sense” (Clarke Doane Reference Clarke-Doane2019, 279, my emphasis) may equally serve to ground judgements such as ‘it is possible that you had different parents’ or ‘it is possible that water was XYZ’. But these examples are paradigm metaphysical impossibilities.

The implication, then, is that where we draw the line between “real” possibility and “non-real” possibility or between possibility and impossibility is just a contingency of natural language semantics. If this were the case, I could not rest my argument on the idea that imaginability does not entail real possibility.

However, as Clarke-Doane himself notes, his argument assumed that “the grounds on which we judge that paradigmatic metaphysical possibilities are possible in some real sense” are good grounds, which is “an assumption that one could conceivably deny” (2019, 279). Now the grounds offered (Clarke-Doane Reference Clarke-Doane2019, sec. 2) are all in the service of justifying paradigmatic judgements of metaphysical possibility. They are accounts of the epistemology of modality crafted in order to make our paradigmatic judgements of possibility turn out to be justified. The whole point of this article, however, is to call into question the justificatory status of paradigmatic judgements of possibility. In the current context, for any ground on which we judge that paradigmatic metaphysical possibilities are possible to be a good ground, it must be good for some reason that is independent of its ability to render our paradigmatic judgements of possibility justified, since my contention is that the latter are symptomatic of the possibility bias. This was my point regarding the conceivability-possibility link (which in fact is the first ground canvassed by Clarke-Doane): we are yet to see what might motivate this ground independently of its ability to render paradigmatic judgements of possibility justified, that is to say, independently of the sway of the possibility bias.

In short, my view is that Clarke-Doane's argument would need to demonstrate that “the grounds on which we judge that paradigmatic metaphysical possibilities are possible in some real sense” (Reference Clarke-Doane2019, 279) are good grounds in a way that does not simply assume the possibility bias.

Clarke-Doane takes a deflationary moral from his argument (Reference Clarke-Doane2019, sec. 7). But in arguing against Clarke-Doane—that we cannot justifiably believe that imaginability is a guide to real possibility—I'm not thereby advocating anything more “inflationary” about, say, the existence of a single privileged kind of real possibility. (There may not even be any real possibility because everything is necessary!). We should suspend judgement on the imaginability-possibility link until it can be justified in a way that does not assume the veracity of “paradigmatic judgements of possibility” since the latter I take to be symptomatic of the (itself unjustified) possibility bias.

3. Reductive Theories of Modality

Reductive theories of modality seek to analyse the modal in non-modal terms. This project is motivated by concerns similar to those already touched on: modality (necessity in particular) strikes many philosophers as mysterious. And if modality is mysterious, it is a mystery how we can come to have modal knowledge, so, it would be good if we could reduce modality to something more familiar, to which our epistemic access is uncontroversial.

Lewisian modal realism is a paradigm attempt at a reductive theory of modality, it reduces possibility and necessity to quantification over other concrete (but spatiotemporally isolated) worlds just like ours. This purports to render modality unmysterious because it is just a matter of quantification over additional familiar things like the actual world that we inhabit. Granted, Lewisian modal realism has raised notorious epistemological problems. Accordingly, other philosophers have sought to reduce modality to quantification over worlds not understood as concrete like our world but as abstract entities (e.g., Plantinga Reference Plantinga1974; Adams Reference Adams1974; Stalnaker Reference Stalnaker1976). The problem with these views is that they fail to be properly reductive because unanalysed modality remains in the definitions they give of abstract possible worlds (e.g., if worlds are maximal sets of consistent propositions “consistency” enters as residual unanalysed modality). This is a point that Lewis (Reference Lewis1986a) raised forcefully against “linguistic” or “ersatz” possible worlds and used to motivate his modal realism. Lewis, pushing the Humean spirit to the extreme, was particularly concerned that modality was to be fully reduced to something else (at all costs!).Footnote 8

The relevance of this is that reductionist proponents of abstract possible worlds have sought to avoid circularity worries, whereby modality reappears in the definition of a world, by giving a combinatorial definition of a possible world. On one such view, possible worlds are identified with sets of space-time points, with each set representing the possibility that its space-time points are occupied by matter (e.g., Heller Reference Heller1998). As Sider puts it: “the multiplicity of worlds results from the combinatorial nature of set theory: for any combination of space-time points there exists a set containing all and only those points […] Modality is not needed to rule out impossible representations of worlds because it is intuitively plausible that any pattern of occupation of space-time points is possible” (Sider Reference Sider2005, 189, my emphasis). In a similar vein, Armstrong maintains that: “The idea for possibility […] is that all the combinations of simple particulars, properties and relations […] constitute the possibilities for first-order states of affairs. Notice that I am not saying ‘all the possible combinations’, which would be trivial, but ‘all the combinations’. The hypothesis is that these combinations are all of them possibilities” (Armstrong Reference Armstrong1997, 160, my emphasis).

So, perhaps one could justify the possibility bias on the grounds of wanting to provide a reductive (but not Lewisian modal realist) account of modality in terms of possible worlds, according to which every combination of space-time points (or particulars and properties) represents a possible way the world could be. On such a picture, possibility would reign supreme. The problem is that while this strategy may eliminate modality from the definition of a possible world, modality reappears in the definition of ‘true in’ a possible world (Lewis Reference Lewis1986a, 150–57; Sider Reference Sider2005, 189–90). So, letting possibility run free and completely unconstrained (as per the possibility bias) cannot be justified on the grounds that it helps yield a reduction of modality to abstract possible worlds because the reduction ultimately fails. But more simply, the possibility bias appears to be assumed prior to the construction of these views; their starting assumption is that possibility is plentitudinous. As Sider insists: “it is intuitively plausible that any pattern of occupation of space-time points is possible” (Reference Sider2005, 189). They then seek to capture this assumption in non-modal, combinatorial terms. So, this type of reductionism about modality cannot independently justify the possibility bias.

Reconsider the Lewisian reduction of modality. Perhaps Lewis requires a plenitude of possible worlds in order for his modal realism to be able to do all of its assigned theoretical work (Lewis Reference Lewis1986a, 5–69). In this case, one might use Lewisian modal realism (LMR) to justify the possibility bias: LMR is justified, LMR implies a plenitude of possibilities, therefore the possibility bias is justified. The problem with this is that LMR remains deeply implausible to many, and so probably is not itself justified to the extent that would be required in order for it to confer justification on the possibility bias (and LMR may not even be fully reductive, in which case a large part of its motivation would disappear). Furthermore, to do the theoretical work of accounting for modality, Lewisian worlds need only be as plentitudinous as we antecedently think possibilities themselves are. If we are working with the possibility bias in mind, then of course we will think that possibilities/possible worlds will be plentitudinous. But if we reject the bias, then we must suspend judgement on how plentitudinous the Lewisian worlds must be in order to do the work of accounting for modality. So, LMR's prospects in accounting for modality cannot provide independent justification for the possibility bias.

In general: an account of modality cannot justify the possibility bias if it is crafted with the possibility bias in mind. Rather, for an account of modality to be able to confer justification on the possibility bias, justification of the possibility bias must follow independently from it.

4. Nozick's Evolutionary Argument

Nozick thinks that the typical method for evaluating whether a proposition is necessary consists in trying to imagine counterexamples to it, that is, situations in which it would be false. If we are presented with some proposition, P, such that we can imagine no situation in which it would be false (perhaps P = “2 + 2 = 4”), then we deem P necessary. Nozick's concern is that while we are good at imagining alternative situations, we are not perfect at doing so. So, a failure to imagine a situation in which P is false does not constitute a good reason to believe that P is necessary, according to Nozick, because there may be some situations that would confute P but which we just can't imagine due to our own intellectual limitations (Euclidean geometry, after all, turned out not to be true of our universe even though it was taken by many to be self-evident and thus necessary).

Nozick argues that it is implausible that evolution would instil in us a faculty for assessing all possible worlds: “Since our ancestors evolved in the actual world, there were no selective pressures to reward accuracy about all possible worlds, and there was no handicap to being right only at the actual world […] We therefore should be wary of concluding that a statement S is necessarily true, simply because we and others have been unable to generate counterexamples to it” (Nozick Reference Nozick2001, 122). What's more, Nozick suggests that there may have been some selective pressure to find certain true propositions to be self-evident and hence the sorts of things to which we could not imagine any counterexample. But if the self-evidence of a proposition may be given an evolutionary explanation, there is no need to explain self-evidence in terms necessity (Nozick Reference Nozick2001, 125).

Does this “evolutionary argument” yield a justification for the possibility bias? No. Nozick's claim is just that we shouldn't trust our intuitions or imaginative capacities as a guide to how far possibility extends because selective pressures are unlikely to have ensured that our imaginative capacities reliably track the possibilities. But one cannot infer from this that possibility is in fact abundant and hence that we are by default justified in asserting possibilities, whatever they may be. The real lesson to be learnt here seems to be that we must suspend judgement on, or at least take a thoroughly fallibilist attitude to beliefs about, how far the possibilities extend because “there were no selective pressures to reward accuracy about all possible worlds, and there was no handicap to being right only at the actual world” (Reference Nozick2001, 125). As with Humean empiricism, the rationale cuts both ways: it is just as hard to see what justifies beliefs about what could be the case as it is to see what justifies beliefs about what must be the case.

5. Possibility is Logically Weaker than Necessity

One might argue that the relative logical strength of possibility and necessity makes possibilities “easier to know” than necessities (Nozick Reference Nozick2001, 121). How so? Well, since “P” implies “possibly P” but “P” does not imply “necessarily P”, to know “possibly P” it suffices to know “P” but knowing “P” is insufficient for knowing “necessarily P”. Alternatively: evidence of what is actually the case may be adduced in support of possibility claims but not necessity claims. This, one might maintain, is what justifies the possibility bias.

The problem is that this observation is irrelevant to typical philosophical debates in which what is at stake is not whether some proposition, P, is possible or necessary. Rather, we are typically concerned with whether some true proposition is contingent or necessary (or whether some false proposition is possible or impossible). To illustrate a typical debate, we might ask whether the true proposition that water is H2O is necessary? Or, we might ask, given that there is no such property as (e.g.) schmass, whether it is possible that schmass existed? The possibility bias stacks the deck in favour of contingency/possibility, but what justifies this? When investigating the two options “P is possible” and “P is necessary”, one could adduce evidence from the actual world in favour of the former but not the latter: P's being actual implies that P is possible but not that P is necessary (assuming the truth of P → <>P). But when investigating the truth of modal propositions more typical in the context of philosophical debates such as “P is possible” and “P is impossible” (when P is false, e.g., P = “schmass exists”) or “P is contingent” and “P is necessary” (when P is true, e.g., P = “water is H2O”) knowledge of actuality cannot tell in favour of either option. So, the relative logical strength of possibility and necessity is unable to justify the possibility bias in typical philosophical contexts.

Perhaps we can compare the relative strength of possibility and impossibility, and of contingency and necessity, i.e., the logically contrary modalities relevant to typical debates in philosophy, if we think about modality in terms of possible worlds. Here's Nozick again:

To say that something is possible is to say that it holds in at least one possible world, while to say that it is necessary is to make the stronger statement that it holds in all possible worlds […] Moreover, to say that something is possible is weaker than to say that it is impossible, for to say it is impossible is to say that it fails to hold in all circumstances (all possible worlds), while to say it is possible is to say merely that there is at least one circumstance (one possible world) in which it holds. (Nozick Reference Nozick2001, 121)

On this way of seeing things, to say that “schmass exists” is possible is just to say that “schmass exists” is true in at least one possible world, whereas to say that “schmass exists” is impossible is to say that “schmass exists” is false in all possible worlds. Since the latter claim requires something of all possible worlds and the former just requires something of at least one world, the latter claim is “stronger” than the former, or so Nozick suggests. Similarly, to say that “water is H2O” is contingent is to say that it fails to be true in at least one possible world, whereas to say that “water is H2O” is necessary is to say that it is true in all possible worlds. Again, since the latter, but not the former, claim requires something of all possible worlds, the latter claim may be thought to be stronger. By thinking about modality in terms of possible worlds, we seem to have a way of saying that possibility/contingency is weaker than impossibility/necessity, which may serve to justify the possibility bias in contexts that we care about.

My response to this involves going on the offensive and arguing that, in fact, on this way of thinking about modality in terms of other possible worlds, possibility is more burdensome than necessity.

5.1 Possible Worlds and Ontological Commitment

If, for some true proposition, P (perhaps P = “water is H2O”), Paul asserts that P is contingent (i.e., that P is possibly false) and Niamh asserts that P is necessarily true (i.e., the negation of what Paul asserts), then, according to the possibility bias, the burden of proof is squarely on Niamh to say why P's modal status deviates from the default. According to the reasoning at the end of the previous section, this bias may be justified by the fact that Niamh's statement is stronger than Paul's in the sense that hers, but not his, requires something of all possible worlds.

Perhaps there is some plausibility to the idea that, given an array of possible worlds, a claim that requires something of all possible worlds is stronger than a claim that requires something of at least one possible world. If, however, we suspend judgement on whether there are any possible worlds besides the actual world, things look quite different.

Remember, we are assuming that P is true and that what is at stake is whether P is necessary or contingent, as is typical of debates in philosophy over which the possibility bias holds sway. For Paul's assertion “P is possibly false” to be true, there needs to be at least one possible world in which P does not obtain. Whereas the truth of Niamh's assertion “P is necessarily true” does not require the existence of any other possible worlds besides the actual world. Possible worlds semantics treats the possibility and necessity operators as existential and universal quantifiers (respectively) over worlds. But only existentially quantified statements are existentially committing. So, possibility looks burdensome in a way that necessity is not. This casts doubt on the Nozickian invocation of possible worlds to justify the possibility bias and perhaps even tells in favour of a necessity bias; if possibility, but not necessity, is existentially committing, then claims of mere possibility/contingency incur a burden of proof that must be paid to offset the cost of their ontological commitment.

At this point, one might object as follows: you can't simultaneously suspend judgement on the existence of possible worlds and accept Leibnizian biconditionalsFootnote 9 as giving the truth conditions for modal statements. If you accept Leibnizian biconditionals, you accept that there is a plentitudinous array of possible worlds. So, you cannot claim that Paul's assertion is more burdensome than Niamh's because it requires the existence of at least one other possible world because you were already committed to a plentitude of possible worlds by accepting a possible worlds semantics for Paul's and Niamh's assertions.

This objection fails because we can separate the question of the truth conditions for modal statements from the question of which modal statements are in fact (believed to be) true. We could, as deRosset points out, accept the Leibnizian biconditionals but still deny the existence of any possible worlds thereby rendering all statements true iff necessary and false iff impossible:

[W]e could embrace the theory of possible worlds […] without ontological extravagance, if we could swallow […] Spinozistic necessitarianism. Then there would be only one possible world, the world we all inhabit. (deRosset 2014, 113)

Similarly, Divers (Reference Divers2004; Reference Divers, Bob and Aviv2009) argues that adoption of a possible worlds semantics only incurs ontological commitment if one also positively believes in mere possibilities; belief in necessities incurs no such commitment:

[T]hose who accept the possible-worlds analyses, and are prepared to accept various claims of necessity and impossibility, would not be committed to asserting anything that involved a commitment—or, at least, any immediately demonstrable ontological commitment—to the existence of possible worlds. (Divers Reference Divers, Bob and Aviv2009, 214)

One could thus endorse a possible worlds semantics and remain agnostic about the existence of possible worlds and thereby suffer an “assertability deficit” as compared with the realist only when it comes to certain claims of mere possibility, because possibility, but not necessity, is interpreted as having existential content according to the possible worlds analysis of modality (Divers Reference Divers, Bob and Aviv2009, 214).

Given the Leibnizian analysis of modality, it is only the requirement to account for contingency/mere possibility that forces the existence of possible worlds besides the actual world. If we were Spinozistic necessitarians we could accept the Leibnizian biconditionals and remain committed only to the existence of the actual world. Hence, there is an important sense in which the possible worlds account of modality renders mere possibility/contingency more burdensome than impossibility/necessity, because the former, but not the latter, requires the existence of possible worlds besides the actual world. This, then, is why one may accept an account of modality in terms of other possible worlds but conclude, contrary to the Nozickian line, that it is indeed mere possibility/contingency that is “stronger” than impossibility/necessity, because the former, but not the latter, requires the existence of other possible worlds besides the actual world. Possible worlds do not justify the possibility bias; if anything, they tell in favour of a necessity bias.

One might respond at this point that abstract possible worlds come cheaply since they can be understood as, say, constructions out of universals where we have independent reasons to postulate the existence of universals.Footnote 10 However, I think it is still very much an open question whether there are good independent reasons to posit the existence of universals. So, the point above stands if we suspend judgement on the existence of universals, which is surely the less “committal” view. The main point is that contra Nozick, there is reason to think that contingency claims are stronger/more committal than necessity claims.

6. Conclusion: Generalizing and Implications

In this article, I have highlighted the possibility bias—the pervasive (even if implicit) idea that assertions of possibility incur a lower justificatory burden than do claims of necessity—and I've surveyed, and rejected, four ways of justifying this bias. Perhaps some will find this piecemeal approach dissatisfying since it leaves open some other way to justify the bias. I'd like to think that the foregoing discussion is important nonetheless, given the prominence of the views discussed in relation to this question about the relative justificatory costs associated with claims of possibility and necessity. I hope to have at least encouraged philosophers to rethink the implications of Humean naturalism, reductive theories of modality, evolution and the relative logical strength of possibility and necessity, for the epistemology of modality. This article is intended to initiate a debate. I'd consider it progress if another author responded with a purported justification of the possibility bias not considered here.

Nevertheless, I do think that the delivery of some such justification is a far from trivial task. I think that there is a more general lesson to be drawn from the previous sub-section. The idea there was that given an account of modality in terms of possible worlds, possibility and not necessity is ontologically committing, and since ontological commitment is something to be avoided, assertions of possibility ought to be thought of as incurring a higher justificatory burden than assertions of necessity. Now this point already enjoys a degree of generality because it holds whatever one's ontology of worlds is. Whether one thinks that worlds are platonic universal properties, abstract propositions or whatever else, possibility, and not necessity, is going to be what incurs the ontological commitment to these entities. So, the point isn't restricted to those thinking about modality in, say, Lewisian modal realist terms.

But the point is more general still. Dispositionalism about modality (Borghini and Williams Reference Borghini and Williams2008; Jacobs Reference Jacobs2010; Vetter Reference Vetter2015) has enjoyed prominence in recent years. On this view, very roughly, for it to be possible that P is for there to be some dispositional property instantiated, the manifestation of which is or includes P; and for it to be necessary that not-P is for it to be the case that there is no disposition for it to be the case that P. It is possibility that is ontologically committing because for a non-actual possibility to obtain requires the existence of the relevant dispositional property. Necessity by contrast is understood negatively as the absence of relevant dispositions. If there were good independent reasons for adopting a modal metaphysics (such as dispositionalism) that makes possibility but not necessity ontologically committing, this would count in favour of rejecting the possibility bias and embracing a necessity bias.

Essentialism about modality, by contrast, seems to make assertions of necessity incur commitment to some essence or other; possibility is then understood negatively as the absence of constraint by essence (e.g., Fine Reference Fine1994). However, some prominent proponents of essentialism about modality are careful to emphasize the point that essences are not things or entities (Lowe Reference Lowe2008; Tahko Reference Tahko2022). So, it is not obvious that even essentialism makes necessity more ontologically burdensome than mere possibility. It might be responded that essence claims are ideologically loaded, which suffices to make essentialist necessity claims metaphysically or epistemically objectionable in a way that essentialist contingency claims are not.Footnote 11 Either way, there is scope for further research here. If, for example, one thought it is important for philosophical method that the bias is justified and if essentialism justified it, then so much the better for essentialism and this would be an important point in favour of essentialism and against other currently popular accounts of modality.

In general, the debate here is open and, in my opinion, interesting and worthy of further serious investigation. This is because failure to justify the possibility bias has ramifications throughout philosophy. As mentioned in the introduction, many philosophical arguments proceed by appeal to weird and wonderful possibilities in their premises. But if we are not justified in believing these possibilities, then we are not justified in believing the conclusions of these possibility arguments. There is then the potential for sweeping scepticism about a whole class of philosophical arguments. Hence, a quite radically different meta-philosophical landscape may not be far off, one in which more consistent effort is put into defending claims of possibility perhaps by engagement with relevant aspects of science. And where possibilities cannot be appropriately defended, possibility arguments in which they feature as premises may be rejected or reinterpreted. We may still think that zombies (for example) are imaginable, even if not really possible. And so, we may interpret the zombie argument as telling us something about our ways of thinking about the world rather than about the world itself. Indeed, this seems a reasonable interpretation of certain arguments in ethics that appeal to very strange scenarios involving convoluted trolley problems or utility monsters, for example: it doesn't matter whether a utility monster is really possible because the point of this argument is to uncover our own deep ways of thinking about the relevant ethical issues. Why not, then, construe much of metaphysics and other subdisciplines of philosophy along similar lines? The full implications of rejecting the possibility bias await further exploration.

Acknowledgements

My thanks to Francesca Bellazzi, Heather Battaly, Toby Friend, Giacomo Giannini, Max Jones, Jessica Leech, Will Morgan, Andrea Raimondi, Tom Schoonen, Vanessa Seifert, Tuomas Tahko, Matthew Tugby, Barbara Vetter and some anonymous reviewers for their very helpful feedback.

Footnotes

1 Here and throughout, I use ‘possibility’ as short for ‘mere possibility’ i.e., possibility that is not actual.

2 In this article I am concerned with alethic modality. What more might be said to characterize the notion at issue is contentious (see sect 2.1 for details), but I hope it can be sufficiently gestured at just in the course of the discussion.

3 Many thanks indeed to a reviewer for raising this interesting case.

4 Heil (Reference Heil2015) is a stand-out in rejecting the possibility bias as I am understanding it here, i.e., in an epistemological-cum-metaphilosophical sense. Wilson (Reference Wilson2020), though similar, is primarily concerned with arguing the first-order metaphysical point that possibility and not necessity is the primary explanatory target of a metaphysics of modality, which falls out of his own preferred Quantum Modal Realism. My work here can be understood as adding meat to the bones of Heil's idea by scrutinizing and ultimately rejecting prominent routes to a justification of the bias.

5 “[T]here are no ideas, which occur in metaphysics, more obscure and uncertain [than necessary connections]” (Hume, EHU 7.1.3/61–62); [N]or is it possible for us ever to form the most distant idea of [necessity], consider'd as a quality in bodies. (T 1.3.14.24)

6 “To form a clear idea of any thing, is an undeniable argument for its possibility” (Hume, T 1.3.6.5)

7 Furthermore, Berto and Schoonen (Reference Berto and Schoonen2018) argue that cognitive psychology casts serious doubt on the Humean idea that conceivability entails possibility in the relevant sense because the most plausible accounts of conceiving do not rule out our being able to conceive the impossible.

8 Work on advanced modalizing suggests that even Lewisian modal realism is left with residual unanalysed modality (e.g., Parsons Reference Parsons and Maclaurin2012; Jago Reference Jago2016; Marshall Reference Marshall2016).

9 “Possibly p” is true iff p is true in some possible world; “necessarily p” is true iff p is true in all possible worlds; contingency and impossibility are then defined in terms of possibility and negation.

10 Thanks to a reviewer for raising this.

11 Thanks to a reviewer for flagging this.

References

Adams, Robert Merrihew. 1974. ‘Theories of Actuality’. Noûs 8 (3): 211–31.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Armstrong, D. M. 1997. A World of States of Affairs. Cambridge; New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ayer, A. J. 1936. Language, Truth, and Logic. London: V. Gollancz.Google Scholar
Berto, Francesco, and Schoonen, Tom. 2018. ‘Conceivability and Possibility: Some Dilemmas for Humeans’. Synthese 195 (6): 26972715. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-017-1346-7.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Borghini, Andrea, and Williams, Neil E. 2008. ‘A Dispositional Theory of Possibility’. Dialectica 62 (1): 2141. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1746-8361.2007.01130.x.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chalmers, David. 1996. The Conscious Mind: In Search of a Fundamental Theory. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Chalmers, David, and Jackson, Frank. 2001. ‘Conceptual Analysis and Reductive Explanation’. Philosophical Review 110 (3): 315–61. https://doi.org/10.1215/00318108-110-3-315.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Churchland, Patricia Smith. 1996. ‘The Hornswoggle Problem’. Journal of Consciousness Studies 3 (5–6): 402–8.Google Scholar
Clarke-Doane, Justin. 2019. ‘Modal Objectivity’. Noûs 53 (2): 266–95. https://doi.org/10.1111/nous.12205.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Clarke-Doane, Justin. 2021. ‘Metaphysical and Absolute Possibility’. Synthese 198 (8): 1861–72. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-019-02093-0.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
deRosset, Louis. 2014. ‘Possible Worlds for Modal Primitivists’. Journal of Philosophical Logic 43 (1): 109–31. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10992-012-9254-2.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Divers, John. 2004. ‘Agnosticism About Other Worlds: A New Antirealist Programme in Modality’. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 69 (3): 660–85. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1933-1592.2004.tb00522.x.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Divers, John. 2009. ‘Modal Commitments’. In Modality: Metaphysics, Logic, and Epistemology, edited by Bob, Hale and Aviv, Hoffmann. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Dummett, Michael. 1959. ‘Wittgenstein's Philosophy of Mathematics’. The Philosophical Review 68 (3): 324–48. https://doi.org/10.2307/2182566.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fine, Kit. 1994. ‘Essence and Modality: The Second Philosophical Perspectives Lecture’. Philosophical Perspectives 8: 116. https://doi.org/10.2307/2214160.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fine, Kit. 2002. ‘Varieties of Necessity’. In Conceivability and Possibility, edited by Gendler, Tamar Szabo and Hawthorne, John, 253–81. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Heil, John. 2015. ‘III—Aristotelian Supervenience’. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 115 (1pt1): 4156.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Heller, Mark. 1998. ‘Five Layers of Interpretation for Possible Worlds’. Philosophical Studies: An International Journal for Philosophy in the Analytic Tradition 90 (2): 205–14.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Inwagen, Peter Van. 1998. ‘Modal Epistemology’. Philosophical Studies 92 (1): 6784.Google Scholar
Jackson, Frank. 1998. From Metaphysics to Ethics: A Defence of Conceptual Analysis. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Jacobs, Jonathan D. 2010. ‘A Powers Theory of Modality: Or, How I Learned to Stop Worrying and Reject Possible Worlds’. Philosophical Studies 151 (2): 227–48. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-009-9427-1.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jago, Mark. 2016. ‘Advanced Modalizing Problems’. Mind 125 (499): 627–42. https://doi.org/10.1093/mind/fzv172.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kripke, Saul A. 1980. Naming and Necessity. Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Lewis, David. 1986a. On the Plurality of Worlds. Oxford, UK; New York, NY, USA: B. Blackwell.Google Scholar
Lewis, David. 1986b. Philosophical Papers Vol. II. Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Lowe, E. J. 2008. ‘Two Notions of Being: Entity and Essence’. Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplements 62 (July): 2348. https://doi.org/10.1017/S1358246108000568.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Marshall, Daniel Graham. 2016. ‘A Puzzle for Modal Realism’. Philosophers’ Imprint 16.Google Scholar
Merricks, Trenton. 1998. ‘There Are No Criteria of Identity Over Time’. Noûs 32 (1): 106–24.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mortensen, Chris. 1989. ‘Anything Is Possible’. Erkenntnis 30 (3): 319–37. https://doi.org/10.1007/BF00168284.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nozick, Robert. 2001. Invariances: The Structure of the Objective World. 1st edn edition. Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Parsons, Josh. 2012. ‘Against Advanced Modalizing’. In Rationis Defensor: Essays in Honour of Colin Cheyne, edited by Maclaurin, James, 139–53. Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Plantinga, Alvin. 1974. The Nature of Necessity. Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Priest, Graham. 2018. ‘Metaphysical Necessity: A Skeptical Perspective’. Synthese 198 (Suppl 8): 1873–85. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-018-1885-6.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Putnam, Hilary. 1969. ‘Is Logic Empirical?’ In Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science: Proceedings of the Boston Colloquium for the Philosophy of Science 1966/1968, edited by Cohen, Robert S. and Wartofsky, Marx W., 216–41. Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science. Dordrecht: Springer Netherlands. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-010-3381-7_5.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Putnam, Hillary. 1975. ‘The Meaning of “Meaning”’. Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science 7: 131–93.Google Scholar
Quine, W. V. O. 1966. The Ways of Paradox. New York: Random.Google Scholar
Rosen, Gideon. 2006. ‘The Limits of Contingency’. In Identity and Modality, edited by MacBride, Fraser, 1339. Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sidelle, Alan. 1989. Necessity, Essence, and Individuation: A Defense of Conventionalism. Cornell University Press. https://www.jstor.org/stable/10.7591/j.ctvr7f2pd.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sider, Theodore. 1993. ‘Van Inwagen and the Possibility of Gunk’. Analysis 53 (4): 285–89. https://doi.org/10.1093/analys/53.4.285.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sider, Theodore. 2005. ‘Reductive Theories of Modality’. The Oxford Handbook of Metaphysics. 8 September 2005. https://doi.org/10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199284221.003.0008.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stalnaker, Robert. 1976. ‘Possible Worlds’. Noûs 10 (1): 6575. https://doi.org/10.2307/2214477.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Strawson, Galen. 2015. ‘“Humeanism”’. Journal of the American Philosophical Association 1 (1): 96102. https://doi.org/10.1017/apa.2014.13.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tahko, Tuomas E. 2022. ‘Possibility Precedes Actuality’. Erkenntnis, 121. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-022-00518-w.Google Scholar
Van Cleve, James. 2018. ‘Brute Necessity’. Philosophy Compass 13 (9): e12516. https://doi.org/10.1111/phc3.12516.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vetter, Barbara. 2015. Potentiality: From Dispositions to Modality. First edition. Oxford Philosophical Monographs. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wilson, Alastair. 2020. The Nature of Contingency: Quantum Physics as Modal Realism. Oxford, New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar