Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-8bhkd Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-20T04:21:20.581Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

A Normative Theory of Disagreement

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  28 September 2017

GRAHAM BEX-PRIESTLEY
Affiliation:
THE UNIVERSITY OF [email protected]
YONATAN SHEMMER
Affiliation:
THE UNIVERSITY OF [email protected]

Abstract:

Expressivists have trouble accounting for disagreement. If ethical or other normative judgments are desire-like rather than belief-like, it is puzzling why we think people often disagree in those domains. While previous expressivists have proposed only straightforwardly descriptive conditions under which disagreement occurs, we argue that disagreement itself should be understood normatively: two or more people disagree just in case their diverging attitudes imply, given a common project of theirs, that at least one of them has reason to change his or her mind.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © American Philosophical Association 2017 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Blackburn, S. (1998) Ruling Passions: A Theory of Practical Reasoning. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Bratman, M. (2000) ‘Reflection, Planning, and Temporally Extended Agency’. The Philosophical Review, 109, 3561.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carter, J. A., and Chrisman, M.. (2012) ‘Is Epistemic Expressivism Incompatible with Inquiry?Philosophical Studies, 159, 323–39.Google Scholar
Dreier, J. (2015) ‘Explaining the Quasi-Real’. In Shafer-Landau, Russ (ed.), Oxford Studies in Metaethics, vol. 10 (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 273–96.Google Scholar
Elga, A. (2007) ‘Reflection and Disagreement’. Noûs, 41, 478502.Google Scholar
Eriksson, J. (2015) ‘Explaining Disagreement: A Problem for (Some) Hybrid Expressivists’. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 96, 3953.Google Scholar
Feldman, R. (2007) ‘Reasonable Religious Disagreements’. In Antony, Louise (ed.), Philosophers Without Gods: Meditations on Atheism and the Secular (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 194214.Google Scholar
Finlay, S. (2014) ‘The Pragmatics of Normative Disagreement’. In Fletcher, Guy and Ridge, Michael (eds.), Having it Both Ways: Hybrid Theories and Modern Metaethics (New York: Oxford University Press), 124–47.Google Scholar
Foley, R. (2001) Intellectual Trust in Ourselves and Others. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Frankfurt, H. (1971) ‘Freedom of the Will and the Concept of a Person’. The Journal of Philosophy, 68, 520.Google Scholar
Gibbard, A. (1990) Wise Choices, Apt Feelings. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gibbard, A. (2003) Thinking How to Live. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Kelly, T. (2005) ‘The Epistemic Significance of Disagreement’. In Hawthorne, John and Gendler, Tamar (eds.), Oxford Studies in Epistemology, vol. 1 (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 167–96.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ridge, M. (2013) ‘Disagreement’. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 86, 4163.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rosen, G. (2001) ‘Nominalism, Naturalism, Epistemic Relativism’. Philosophical Perspectives, 15, 6991.Google Scholar
Shemmer, Y. (2014) ‘On the Normative Authority of Others’. Philosophia, 42, 517–21.Google Scholar
Stevenson, C. L. (1944) Ethics and Language. New Haven: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Velleman, J. D. (2000) The Possibility of Practical Reason. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar