Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-r5fsc Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-22T18:34:08.006Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Justice as Lawfulness

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  27 November 2018

TRISTAN J. ROGERS*
Affiliation:
UNIVERSITY OF [email protected]

Abstract

What is the relationship between justice as an individual virtue and justice as an institutional virtue? The latter has been exhaustively explored by political philosophers, whereas the former remains underexplored in the literature on virtue ethics. This article defends the view that individual justice is logically prior to institutional justice, and argues that this view requires a conception of individual justice I call ‘justice as lawfulness’. The resulting view consists of three claims. First, just institutions are composed of the relations between just persons. Second, the just person has a disposition to act in accordance with the legal and social norms (collectively, the nomoi) of the existing political tradition. Third, departures from the nomoi require that the just person act with practical wisdom to reform the nomoi according to an implicit standard of justice in the political tradition.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © American Philosophical Association 2018 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

Thanks to the following people for helpful comments on this article, which is based on chapter 4 of my (2017) doctoral dissertation Virtue Politics (Rogers 2017): Julia Annas, Joe Espena, Mario Ivan Juarez-Garcia, Mark LeBar, Fred Miller Jr., John Proios, Gregory Robson, Daniel C. Russell, David Schmidtz, Bjorn Wastvedt, and a handful of anonymous reviewers.

References

Annas, Julia. (1993) The Morality of Happiness. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Annas, Julia. (2002) ‘My Station and its Duties: Ideals and the Social Embeddedness of Virtue’. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 102, 109–23.Google Scholar
Aristotle. (1998) Politics. Edited by Reeve, C. D.. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett.Google Scholar
Aristotle. (2000) Nicomachean Ethics. Edited by Crisp, Roger. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Burke, Edmund. ([1790] 1999) Reflections on the Revolution in France. Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Fund.Google Scholar
Cohen, G. A. (1997) ‘Where the Action Is: On the Site of Distributive Justice’. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 26, 1, 330.Google Scholar
Cohen, G.A. (2008) Rescuing Justice and Equality. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Gaus, Gerald. (2011) The Order of Public Reason. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Hardimon, Michael O. (1994) ‘Role Obligations’. The Journal of Philosophy, 91, 333–63.Google Scholar
Hayek, F. A. (1973) Law, Legislation and Liberty. Vol. 1. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Hursthouse, Rosalind. (1991) ‘After Hume's Justice’. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 91, 229–45.Google Scholar
Hursthouse, Rosalind. (1999) On Virtue Ethics. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Kekes, John. (1998) A Case for Conservatism. New York: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Kraut, Richard. (2002) Aristotle. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Larmore, Charles. (1994) ‘Pluralism and Reasonable Disagreement’. Social Philosophy and Policy, 11, 6179.Google Scholar
LeBar, Mark. (2005) ‘Eudaimonist Autonomy’. American Philosophical Quarterly, 42, 171–84.Google Scholar
LeBar, Mark. (2009) ‘Virtue Ethics and Deontic Constraints’. Ethics, 119, 642–71.Google Scholar
LeBar, Mark. (2013a) The Value of Living Well. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
LeBar, Mark. (2013b) ‘Virtue and Politics’. In Russell, Daniel C. (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Virtue Ethics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 265–89.Google Scholar
LeBar, Mark. (2014) ‘The Virtue of Justice Revisited’. In Hooft, StanVan and Nafsika Athanassoulis (eds.), The Handbook of Virtue Ethics (London: Acumen Publishing), 265–75.Google Scholar
Lucas, J. R. (1980) On Justice. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
McCloskey, Deidre. (2007) The Bourgeois Virtues: Ethics for an Age of Commerce. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Plato. (1997a) Apology. In Cooper, John (ed.), The Complete Works of Plato (Indianapolis, IN: Hackett), 1736.Google Scholar
Plato. (1997b) Crito. In Cooper, John (ed.), The Complete Works of Plato (Indianapolis, IN: Hackett), 3748.Google Scholar
Rawls, John. ([1958] 1999a) ‘Justice as Fairness’. In Freeman, Samuel (ed.), Collected Papers (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press), 4772.Google Scholar
Rawls, John. ([1971] 1999b) ‘Justice as Reciprocity’. In Freeman, Samuel (ed.), Collected Papers (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press), 190224.Google Scholar
Rawls, John. ([1971] 1999c) A Theory of Justice. Revised ed. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Rawls, John. ([1988] 1999d) ‘The Priority of Right and Ideas of the Good’. In Freeman, Samuel (ed.), Collected Papers (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press), 449–72.Google Scholar
Rawls, John. (1993) Political Liberalism. New York: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Rawls, John. ([1997] 1999e) ‘The Idea of Public Reason Revisited’. In Freeman, Samuel (ed.), Collected Papers (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press), 573615.Google Scholar
Rogers, Tristan J. (2017) Virtue Politics. Unpublished doctoral dissertation. Tucson, AZ: University of Arizona.Google Scholar
Russell, Daniel C. (2012) ‘What Virtue Ethics Can Learn from Utilitarianism’. In Ben Eggleston and Dale E. Miller (eds.), The Cambridge Companion to Utilitarianism (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 258–79.Google Scholar
Scanlon, T. M. (1998) What We Owe to Each Other. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Sidgwick, Henry. ([1874] 1981) The Methods of Ethics. 7th ed. Indianapolis, IN: Hackett.Google Scholar
Schmidtz, David, and Thrasher, John. (2014) ‘The Virtues of Justice’. In Timpe, Kevin and Boyd, Craig (eds.), Virtues and Their Vices (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 5974.Google Scholar
Schmidtz, David. (2016) ‘A Realistic Political Ideal’. Social Philosophy and Policy, 33, 110.Google Scholar
Solum, Lawrence. (2008) ‘Natural Justice: An Aretaic Account of the Virtue of Lawfulness’. In Colin Farrelly and Lawrence Solum (eds.), Virtue Jurisprudence (New York: Palgrave MacMillan), 167–92.Google Scholar
Tomasi, John. (2012) Free Market Fairness. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Watson, Gary. (1990) ‘On the Primacy of Character’. In Owen Flanagan and Amélie Oksenberg Rorty (eds.), Identity, Character, and Morality (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press), 449–70.Google Scholar
Wiggins, David. (2004) ‘Neo-Aristotelian Reflections on Justice’. Mind, 113, 477512.Google Scholar
Williams, Bernard. (1980) ‘Justice as a Virtue’. In Rorty, Amélie Oksenberg (ed.), Essays on Aristotle's Ethics (Berkeley, CA: University of California Press), 189200.Google Scholar