Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-g8jcs Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-25T11:22:58.707Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

How to Take Offense: Responding to Microaggression

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  22 November 2018

REGINA RINI*
Affiliation:
YORK UNIVERSITY (TORONTO) [email protected]

Abstract

A microaggression is a small insulting act made disproportionately harmful by its part in an oppressive pattern of similar insults. How should you respond when made the victim of a microaggression? In this paper I survey several morally salient factors, including effects upon victims, perpetrators, and third parties. I argue, contrary to popular views, that ‘growing a thicker skin’ is not good advice nor is expressing reasonable anger always the best way to contribute to confronting oppression. Instead, appropriately responding to microaggression involves difficult application of practical wisdom that does not easily fall under a simple prescription.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © American Philosophical Association 2018 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

I want to thank the editors and referees for JAPA for extensive and helpful feedback on this paper. Parts of the paper were presented at a Brooklyn Public Philosophers event at the Brooklyn Public Library and at a Binghamton University Philosophy colloquium. A full version was presented at the 2017 Pacific APA in Seattle, where it benefited enormously from engagement by commenter Lauren Ashwell, copanelist Allan Hazlett, and chair Lani Watson. Thanks also to Samuel Gates, Rebecca Harrison, Ian Olasov, and Lisa Tessman for helpful discussion.

References

Abramson, Kate. (2014) ‘Turning up the Lights on Gaslighting’. Philosophical Perspectives, 28, 130.Google Scholar
Ahmad, Asam. (2015) ‘A Note on Call-Out Culture’. Briarpatch Magazine. https://briarpatchmagazine.com/articles/view/a-note-on-call-out-culture.Google Scholar
Alcoff, Linda Martín. (1996) ‘The Problem of Speaking for Others’. In Roof, Judith and Wiegman, Robyn (eds.), Who Can Speak? Authority and Critical Identity (Champaign, IL: University of Illinois Press), 97119.Google Scholar
Amaya, Santiago. (2013) ‘Slips’. Nous, 47, 559–76.Google Scholar
Brennan, Samantha. (2016) ‘The Moral Status of Micro-Inequities’. In Michael Brownstein, and Jennifer Saul, (eds.), Implicit Bias and Philosophy, Volume 2: Moral Responsibility, Structural Injustice, and Ethics (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 235–53.Google Scholar
Beatty, Paul. (2015) The Sellout. New York: Picador.Google Scholar
Benson, Paul. (2000) ‘Feeling Crazy: Self Worth the Social Character of Responsibility’. In Catriona Mackenzie, and Natalie Stoljar, (eds.) Relational Autonomy: Feminist Perspectives on Autonomy, Agency, and the Social Self (New York: Oxford University Press), 7293.Google Scholar
Berenstain, Nora. (2016) ‘Epistemic Exploitation’. Ergo, 3, 569–90.Google Scholar
Bloomfield, Paul. (2014) The Virtues of Happiness. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Bommarito, Nicolas (2017) ‘Virtuous and Vicious Anger’. Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy, 11, 127.Google Scholar
Burrow, Sylvia. (2005) ‘The Political Structure of Emotion: From Dismissal to Dialogue’. Hypatia, 20, 2743.Google Scholar
Calhoun, Cheshire. (1989) ‘Responsibility and Reproach’. Ethics, 99, 389406.Google Scholar
Campbell, Bradley, and Manning, Jason. (2016) ‘Campus Culture Wars and the Sociology of Morality’. Comparative Sociology, 15, 147–78.Google Scholar
Campbell, Sue. (1994) ‘Being Dismissed: The Politics of Emotional Expression’. Hypatia, 9, 4665.Google Scholar
Davis, Peggy C. (1989) ‘Law As Microaggression’. The Yale Law Journal, 98, 1559–77.Google Scholar
Dotson, Kristie. (2011) ‘Tracking Epistemic Violence, Tracking Practices of Silencing’. Hypatia, 26, 236–57.Google Scholar
Fatima, Saba. (2017) ‘On the Edge of Knowing: Microaggression and Epistemic Uncertainty as a Woman of Color’. In Kirsti Cole, and Holly Hassel, (eds.), Surviving Sexism in Academia: Feminist Strategies for Leadership (New York: Routledge), 147–57.Google Scholar
Flanagan, Owen. (2016) The Geography of Morals: Varieties of Moral Possibility. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Fricker, Miranda. (2007) Epistemic Injustice: Power and the Ethics of Knowing. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Friedlaender, Christina. (2018) ‘On Microaggressions: Cumulative Harm and Individual Responsibility’. Hypatia. http://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/hypa.12390/full.Google Scholar
Frye, Marilyn. (1983) ‘Oppression’. In Frye, The Politics of Reality (Trumansburg: Crossing Press), 116.Google Scholar
Govier, Trudy. (1993) ‘Self-Trust, Autonomy, and Self-Esteem’. Hypatia, 8, 99120.Google Scholar
Harwood, Stacey Anne, et al. (2015) ‘Racial Microaggressions at the University of Illinois at Urbana-Champaign: Voices of Students of Color in the Classroom’. University of Illinois at Urbana-Champaign. http://www.racialmicroaggressions.illinois.edu/files/2015/03/RMA-Classroom-Report.pdf.Google Scholar
Hay, Carol. (2011) ‘The Obligation to Resist Oppression’. Journal of Social Philosophy, 42, 2145.Google Scholar
Holroyd, Jules. (2012) ‘Responsibility for Implicit Bias’. Journal of Social Philosophy, 43, 274306.Google Scholar
Leboeuf, Céline. (2017) ‘Anger as a Political Emotion: A Phenomenological Perspective’. In Myisha Cherry, and Owen Flanagan, (eds.), The Moral Psychology of Anger (Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield International), 1530.Google Scholar
Lilienfeld, Scott O. (2017) ‘Microaggressions: Strong Claims, Inadequate Evidence’. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 12, 138–69.Google Scholar
Lukianoff, Greg, and Haidt, Jonathan. (2015) ‘The Coddling of the American Mind’. The Atlantic. September. https://www.theatlantic.com/magazine/archive/2015/09/the-coddling-of-the-american-mind/399356/.Google Scholar
McTernan, Emily. (2017) ‘Microaggressions, Equality, and Social Practices’. Journal of Political Philosophy. https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/abs/10.1111/jopp.12150.Google Scholar
Medina, José. (2012) The Epistemology of Resistance: Gender and Racial Oppression, Epistemic Injustice, and Resistant Imaginations. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Mills, Charles W. (1997) The Racial Contract. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
Murphy, Jeffrie G., and Hampton, Jean. (1990) Forgiveness and Mercy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Nagel, Thomas. (1974) ‘What is it Like to Be a Bat?Philosophical Review, 83, 435–50.Google Scholar
Nussbaum, Martha C. (2016) Anger and Forgiveness: Resentment, Generosity, and Justice. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Pierce, Chester. (1970) ‘Offensive Mechanisms’. In Barbour, Floyd B. (ed.), The Black Seventies (Boston: Porter Sargeant), 265–82.Google Scholar
Rini, Regina. (2015) ‘Microaggression, Macro Harm’. Los Angeles Times, October 12. http://www.latimes.com/opinion/op-ed/la-oe-1012-rini-microaggression-solidarity-20151012-story.html.Google Scholar
Rini, Regina A. (2017) ‘Why Moral Psychology is Disturbing’. Philosophical Studies, 174, 1439–58.Google Scholar
Ronson, Jon. (2015) So You've Been Publicly Shamed. New York: Riverhead Books.Google Scholar
Saul, Jennifer. (2013) ‘Scepticism and Implicit Bias’. Disputatio, 5, 244–63.Google Scholar
Scanlon, T. M. (1998) What We Owe To Each Other. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Silvermint, Daniel. (2013) ‘Resistance and Well-being’. Journal of Political Philosophy, 21, 405–25.Google Scholar
Silvermint, Daniel. (2017) ‘Rage and Virtuous Resistance’. Journal of Political Philosophy, 25, 461–86.Google Scholar
Smith, Angela M. (2005) ‘Responsibility for Attitudes: Activity and Passivity in Mental Life’. Ethics, 115, 236–71.Google Scholar
Srinivasan, Amia. (2017) ‘The Aptness of Anger’. Journal of Political Philosophy. http://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/jopp.12130/abstract.Google Scholar
Strawson, Peter F. (1962) ‘Freedom and Resentment’. Proceedings of the British Academy, 48, 125.Google Scholar
Sue, Derald Wing. (2010) Microaggressions in Everyday Life: Race, Gender, and Sexual Orientation. Hoboken, NJ: Wiley.Google Scholar
Sue, Derald Wing, et al. (2007) ‘Racial Microaggressions in Everyday Life: Implications for Clinical Practice’. American Psychologist, 62, 271–86.Google Scholar
Tessman, Lisa. (2005) Burdened Virtues: Virtue Ethics for Liberatory Struggles. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Thomas, Kenneth R. (2008) ‘Macrononsense in Multiculturalism’. American Psychologist, 63, 274–75.Google Scholar
Thomas, Laurence M. (1998) ‘Moral Deference’. In Willet, Cynthia (ed.), Theorizing Multiculturalisms (New York: Blackwell Publishers), 359–81.Google Scholar
Tosi, Justin, and Warmke, Brandon. (2016) ‘Moral Grandstanding’. Philosophy and Public Affairs, 44, 197217.Google Scholar
Trần, Ngọc Loan. (2013) ‘Calling IN: A Less Disposable Way of Holding Each Other Accountable’. BDG Blog. https://www.bgdblog.org/2013/12/calling-less-disposable-way-holding-accountable/.Google Scholar
Tschaepe, Mark. (2016) ‘Addressing Microaggressions and Epistemic Injustice: Flourishing from the Work of Audre Lorde’. Essays in the Philosophy of Humanism, 24, 87101.Google Scholar
Walker, Margaret Urban. (2006) Moral Repair: Reconstructing Moral Relations After Wrongdoing. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Young, Iris Marion. (2013) Responsibility for Justice. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Zheng, Robin. (2016a) ‘Why Yellow Fever Isn't Flattering: A Case Against Racial Fetishes’. Journal of the American Philosophical Association, 2, 400–19.Google Scholar
Zheng, Robin. (2016b) ‘Attributability, Accountability, and Implicit Bias’. In Michael Brownstein, and Jennifer Saul, (eds.), Implicit Bias and Philosophy, Volume 2: Moral Responsibility, Structural Injustice, and Ethics (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 6289.Google Scholar