Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-2plfb Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-23T08:59:14.231Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Extended Virtues and the Boundaries of Persons

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  30 March 2016

ROBERT J. HOWELL*
Affiliation:
SOUTHERN METHODIST [email protected]

Abstract:

What sorts of things undergird a person's character and what does the answer tell us about the person's relationship to her body, her environment, and the people who surround her? For the purpose of ascribing virtue, vice, and character, what are the boundaries of the person? Traditionally, philosophers have accepted mentalism, the view that only mental features are relevant to character. Even philosophers inclined to say that character is partially constituted by nonmental features would be inclined to accept skindividualism: a person's virtue must involve a disposition that is wholly grounded by features inside the person's skin. Drawing from arguments in the philosophy of mind and data from social psychology, I argue that skindividualism is wrong. Virtues can be extended, in the sense that the grounds for a person's virtues might not be inside that individual's skin. If this is the case, persons are not skindividuals.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © American Philosophical Association 2016 

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Adams, Frederick R., and Aizawa, Kenneth. (2010) ‘Defending the Bounds of Cognition’. In The Extended Mind. (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press), 6780.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Adams, Fred, and Aizawa, Kenneth. (2009) ‘Why the Mind Is Still in the Head’. In Robbins, Philip and Aydede, Murat (eds.), Cambridge Handbook of Situated Cognition. (New York: Cambridge University Press), 7895.Google Scholar
Adams, Frederick R., and Aizawa, Kenneth. (2008) The Bounds of Cognition. Hoboken, NJ: Blackwell Publishing.Google Scholar
Alfano, Mark. (2013) Character as Moral Fiction. New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Annas, Julia. (2011) Intelligent Virtue. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Banuazizi, A., and Movahedi, S.. (1975) ‘Interpersonal Dynamics in a Simulated Prison: A Methodological Analysis’. American Psychologist, 30, 152160.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chalmers, David. (1996) The Conscious Mind. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Clark, Andy, and Chalmers, David J.. (1998) ‘The Extended Mind’. Analysis, 58, 719.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Clark, Andy. (2008) Supersizing the Mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Damasio, Antonio R. (1994) Descartes’ Error: Emotion, Reason, and the Human Brain. New York: Putnam.Google Scholar
Doris, John M. (2002) Lack of Character: Personality and Moral Behavior. New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fisher, Justin. (2008) ‘Critical Notice of The Bounds of Cognition’. Journal of Mind and Behavior, 29, 345–57.Google Scholar
Gallagher, Shaun. (2013a) ‘The Socially Extended Mind’. Cognitive Systems Research, 25–26, 412.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gallagher, Shaun. (2013b) ‘A Pattern Theory of Self’. Frontiers in Human Neuroscience, 7, 17.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Gallagher, Shaun. (2013c) ‘Ambiguity in the Sense of Agency’. In Clark, A., Kiverstein, J., and Vierkant, T. (eds.), Decomposing the Will (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 118–35.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gettler, Lee T., McDade, Thomas W., Feranil, Alan B., and Kuzawa, Christopher W.. (2011) ‘Longitudinal Evidence that Fatherhood Decreases Testosterone in Human Males’. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 108, 16194–99. doi:10.1073/pnas.1105403108.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Gray, Peter. (2013) ‘Why Zimbardo's Prison Experiment Isn't in My Textbook’. Available at: http://www.psychologytoday.com/blog/freedom-learn/201310/why-zimbardo-s-prison-experiment-isn-t-in-my-textbook.Google Scholar
Haney, C., Banks, W. C., and Zimbardo, P. G.. (1973). ‘A Study of Prisoners and Guards in a Simulated Prison’. Naval Research Review, 30, 417.Google Scholar
Harman, Gilbert. (1999) ‘Moral Philosophy Meets Social Psychology: Virtue Ethics and the Fundamental Attribution Error’. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 99, 315–31.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harman, Gilbert. (2000) ‘The Nonexistence of Character Traits’. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 100, 223–26.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harman, Gilbert. (2009) ‘Skepticism about Character Traits’. Journal of Ethics, 13, 235–42.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kilham, W., and Mann, L.. (1974). ‘Level of Destructive Obedience as a Junction of Transmitter and Executant Roles in the Milgram Obedience Paradigm’. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 29, 696702.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Latané, B., and Darley, J. M.. (1968) ‘Group Inhibition of Bystander Intervention in Emergencies’. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 10, 215–21.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Latané, B., and Darley, J. M.. (1970) The Unresponsive Bystander: Why Doesn't He Help? New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts.Google Scholar
Latané, Bibb, and Nida, Steve. (1981) ‘Ten Years of Research on Group Size and Helping’. Psychological Bulletin, 89, 308–24. doi:10.1037/0033-2909.89.2.308.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Merritt, Maria. (2000) ‘Virtue Ethics and Situationist Personality Psychology’. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 3, 365–83.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Milgram, S. (1974) Obedience to Authority: An Experimental View. New York: Harpercollins.Google Scholar
Miller, Christian B. (2013) Moral Character: An Empirical Theory. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rupert, Robert D. (2009) Cognitive Systems and the Extended Mind. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Russell, Daniel C. (2012) Happiness for Humans. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sabini, John, and Silver, Maury. (2005) ‘Lack of Character? Situationism Critiqued’. Ethics, 115, 535–62.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Selinger, Evan, and Seager, Thomas. (2012) ‘Digital Jiminy Crickets’. Slate, July 13, 2012. Available at: http://www.slate.com/articles/technology/future_tense/2012/07/ethical_decision_making_apps_damage_our_ablity_to_make_moral_choices_.html.Google Scholar
Upton, Candace L. (2005) ‘A Contextual Account of Character Traits’. Philosophical Studies, 122, 133–51.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Upton, Candace L. (2009) Situational Traits of Character: Dispositional Foundations and Implications for Moral Psychology and Friendship. Lanham, MD: Lexington Books.Google Scholar
Weiskopf, Daniel A. (2008) ‘Patrolling the Mind's Boundaries’. Erkenntnis, 68, 265–76.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wilson, Robert A. (2004) Boundaries of the Mind: The Individual in the Fragile Sciences: Cognition. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar